philosophy

Lesson 5: Philosophy of Religion–Arguments for the Existence of God

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Essay on
philosophy
Just from $13/Page
Order Essay

Philosophy of religion is typically concerned with the nature and existence of God. 

YouTube Videos

This folder contains the YouTube videos which explain the different arguments for the existence of God.

God’s Existence

This folder contains readings concerning arguments for the existence and non-existence of God.

Lesson 3: Epistemology

Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that deals with knowledge. In this lesson we discuss the various attempts to define knowledge and consider the case for skepticism, the view that knowledge is ultimately impossible.

This lesson introduces epistemology by exploring the definition of knowledge and the challenge of skepticism. 

Lesson 4 Learning Outcomes

At the end of this lesson, students will be able to:

1. Read, analyze, and critique texts about epistemology.

2. Demonstrate knowledge of key concepts, major arguments, problems, and terminology in the philosophy by identifying the origins, historical developments, key figures, and general emphases of epistemology.

3. Present logically persuasive arguments.

4. Demonstrate critical thinking skills in evaluation and application of philosophical concepts to various aspects of life by

· evaluating the merits and demerits of the philosophical approaches of key figures in the history of epistemology;

· applying each of these philosophical approaches to particular problems.

Lesson 4 Checklist
Open the folder on the definition of knowledge, then:

· view the video about the different kinds of knowledge

· view the video about the Gettier problem

Utilitarianism

John Stuart Mill

Copyright ©

2

0

1

0–

20

1

5

All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett

[Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as
though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations,
are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . . . . indicates the
omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth.

First launched: September 2005 Last amended: April 200

8

Contents

  • Chapter 1: General Remarks
  • 1

  • Chapter 2: What utilitarianism is
  • 4

    ·Higher and Lower Pleasures· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 5
    ·Happiness as an Aim· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8
    ·Self-Sacrifice· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    11

    ·Setting the Standard too High?· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    12

    ·Is Utilitarianism Chilly?· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

    3

    ·Utilitarianism as ‘Godless’· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .

    15

    ·Expediency· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 15
    ·Time to Calculate?· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

    6

    ·Bad Faith· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1

    7

  • Chapter 3: What will motivate us to obey the principle of utility?
  • 18

    Chapter 4: What sort of proof can be given for the principle of utility? 24

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill

    Chapter 5: The connection between justice and utility 28
    ·Punishment· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 38
    ·Wages· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3

    9

    ·Taxation· . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 39

    ii

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 1: General remarks

    Chapter 1: General Remarks

    Little progress has been made towards deciding the contro-
    versy concerning the criterion of right and wrong. Among all
    the facts about the present condition of human knowledge,
    the state of this controversy is •most unlike what might
    have been expected and •most indicative significant of the
    backward state in which theorizing on the most important
    subjects still lingers. That is how little progress has been
    made! From the dawn of philosophy the question concerning
    the summum bonum [Latin, = ‘the greatest good’] or, what is the
    same thing, concerning the foundation of morality, has

    •been regarded as the main problem in speculative
    thought,

    •occupied the most gifted intellects, and
    •divided them into sects and schools, vigorously war-
    ring against one another.

    And after more than two thousand years the same discus-
    sions continue! Philosophers still line up under the same
    opposing battle-flags, and neither thinkers nor people in
    general seem to be any nearer to being unanimous on the
    subject than when young Socrates listened to old Protagoras
    and asserted the theory of utilitarianism against the popular
    morality of the so-called ‘sophist’ (I’m assuming here that
    Plato’s dialogue is based on a real conversation). [Except on

    page

    14

    , ‘popular’ is used in this work only to mean ‘of the people’, with

    no implication about being liked.]

    It is true that similar confusion and uncertainty, and
    in some cases similar disagreements, exist concerning the
    basic principles of all the sciences—even including the one
    that is thought to be the most certain of them, namely
    mathematics—without doing much harm, and usually with-
    out doing any harm, to the trustworthiness of the conclu-

    sions of those sciences. This seems odd, but it can be
    explained: the detailed doctrines of a science usually •are
    not deduced from what are called its first principles and
    •don’t need those principles to make them evident. If this
    weren’t so, there would be no science more precarious, and
    none whose conclusions were more weakly based, than
    algebra. This doesn’t get any of its certainty from what
    are commonly taught to learners as its •elements ·or first
    principles·, because •these, as laid down by some of its most
    eminent teachers, are as full of fictions as English law and as
    full of mysteries as theology. The truths that are ultimately
    accepted as the first principles of a science are really the last
    results of metaphysical analysis of the basic notions that
    are involve in the science in question. Their relation to the
    science is not that of •foundations to a building but of •roots
    to a tree, which can do their job equally well if they are never
    dug down to and exposed to light. But though in science the
    particular truths precede the general theory, the reverse of
    that might be expected with a practical art such as morals
    or legislation. [Here an ‘art’ is any activity requiring a set of rules or

    techniques, and ‘practical’ means ‘having to do with human conduct’.]
    All action is for the sake of some end; and it seems natural to
    suppose that rules of action must take their whole character
    and colour from the end at which actions aim. When we are
    pursuing something, a clear and precise conception of what
    we are pursuing would seem to be the first thing we need,
    rather than being the last we are to look forward to. One
    would think that a test ·or criterion· of right and wrong must
    be •the means of discovering what is right or wrong, and not
    •a consequence of having already discovered this.

    1

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 1: General remarks

    The difficulty can’t be avoided by bringing in the popu-
    lar theory of a natural ·moral· faculty, a sense or instinct
    informing us of right and wrong. For one thing, the ‘criterion’
    dispute includes a dispute about whether there is any such
    moral instinct. And, anyway, believers in it who have
    any philosophical ability have been obliged to abandon the
    idea that it—·the moral faculty or ‘moral sense’ or moral
    intuition·—picks out what is right or wrong in this or that
    •particular case in the way that our other senses pick up
    the sight or sound that is actually present ·in the •particular
    concrete situation·. Our moral faculty, according to all those
    of its friends who are entitled to count as thinkers, supplies
    us only with the •general principles of moral judgments; it
    belongs with reason and not with sense-perception; what we
    can expect from it are the abstract doctrines of morality,
    and not the perception of morality in particular concrete
    situations. The intuitionist school of ethics insists on the
    necessity of general laws just as much as does the inductive
    school (as we might label it). They both agree that ·knowing·
    the morality of an individual action is not a matter of •direct
    perception but of the •application of a law to an individual
    case. The two schools mostly agree also in what moral laws
    they recognize; but they differ on

    •what makes those moral laws evident, and
    •what give them their authority.

    According to the intuitionists, the principles of morals are
    evident a priori: if you know the meanings of the terms in
    which they are expressed, you’ll have to assent to them.
    According to the inductivists, •right and wrong are questions
    of observation and experience just as •truth and falsehood
    are. But both schools hold equally that morality must be
    deduced from principles; and the intuitive school affirm
    as strongly as the inductive does that there is a science of
    morals—·i.e. an organized system containing basic axioms

    from which the rest can be rigorously deduced·. Yet they
    seldom attempt to provide a list of the a priori principles that
    are to serve as the premises of the science; and they almost
    never make any effort to reduce those various principles to
    one first principle, one first all-purpose ground of obligation.
    Instead, they either •treat the ordinary precepts of morals
    as though they had a priori authority or •lay down as the
    all-purpose groundwork of those maxims some general moral
    principle that is much less obviously authoritative than the
    maxims themselves and hasn’t ever been widely accepted.
    Yet to support their claims there ought to be one fundamental
    principle or law at the root of all morality; or if there are sev-
    eral of them, •they should be clearly rank-ordered in relation
    to one another, and •there should be a self-evident principle
    or rule for deciding amongst them when they conflict ·in a
    particular case·.

    The lack of any clear recognition of an ultimate standard
    may have •corrupted the moral beliefs of mankind or made
    them uncertain; on the other hand, the bad effects of this de-
    ficiency may have •been moderated in practice. To determine
    how far things have gone in the •former way and how far in
    the •latter would require a complete critical survey of past
    and present ethical doctrine. But it wouldn’t be hard to show
    that whatever steadiness or consistency mankind’s moral
    beliefs have achieved has been mainly due to the silent influ-
    ence of a standard that hasn’t been ·consciously· recognised.
    In the absence of an acknowledged first principle, ethics has
    been not so much a •guide to men in forming their moral
    views as a •consecration of the views they actually have; but
    men’s views—both for and against—are greatly influenced by
    what effects on their happiness they suppose things to have;
    and so the principle of utility—or, as Bentham eventually
    called it, ‘the greatest happiness principle’—has had a large
    share in forming the moral doctrines even of those who

    2

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 1: General remarks

    most scornfully reject its authority. And every school of
    thought admits that the influence of actions on happiness
    is a very significant and even predominant consideration in
    many of the details of morals, however unwilling they may
    be to allow the production of happiness as the fundamental
    principle of morality and the source of moral obligation. I
    might go much further and say that a priori moralists can’t
    do without utilitarian arguments (I am not talking about the
    ones who don’t think they need to argue at all!). It is not my
    present purpose to criticise these thinkers; but I can’t refrain
    from bringing in as an illustration a systematic treatise by
    one of the most illustrious of the a priori moralists, the
    Metaphysics of Ethics by Kant. This remarkable man, whose
    system of thought will long remain one of the landmarks
    in the history of philosophical thought, lays down in that
    treatise a universal first principle as the origin and ground
    of moral obligation:

    Act in such a way that the rule on which you act
    could be adopted as a law by all rational beings.

    But when he begins to derive any of the actual duties of
    morality from this principle he fails, almost grotesquely, to
    show that there would be any contradiction—any logical
    impossibility, or even any physical impossibility—in the
    adoption by all rational beings of the most outrageously
    immoral rules of conduct. All he shows is that the universal
    adoption of such rules would have consequences that no-one
    would choose to bring about.

    In the present work I shall, without further discussion
    of the other theories, try to contribute something towards
    the understanding and appreciation of the Utilitarian or
    Happiness theory, and towards such proof as it can be given.
    Obviously this can’t be ‘proof’ in the ordinary and popular
    meaning of that word. Questions about ultimate ends can’t
    be settled by direct proof. You can prove something to be

    good only by showing that it is a means to something that
    is admitted without proof to be good. The art of medicine is
    proved to be good by its conducing to health, but how is it
    possible to prove that health is good? The art of music is
    good because (among other reasons) it produces pleasure,
    but what proof could be given that pleasure is good? So if it
    is claimed that

    •there is a comprehensive formula that covers every-
    thing that is good in itself, and

    •whatever else is good is not good as an end but as a
    means ·to something that is covered by the formula·,

    the formula may be accepted or rejected but it can’t be
    given what is commonly called a ‘proof’. But we shouldn’t
    infer that its acceptance or rejection must depend on blind
    impulse or arbitrary choice. There is a broader meaning of
    the word ‘proof’ in which this question is as capable of ·being
    settled by· ‘proof’ as any other of the disputed questions in
    philosophy. The subject is within reach of the faculty of
    reason, which doesn’t deal with it solely by ·moral· intuitions
    ·such as the intuitionists believe in·. Considerations can
    be presented that are capable of determining the intellect
    either to give or withhold its assent to the doctrine; and this
    is equivalent to proof.

    We shall examine presently what sort of thing these con-
    siderations are and how they apply to the question at hand.
    In doing this we shall be examining what rational grounds
    can be given for accepting or rejecting the utilitarian formula.
    But if there is to be rational acceptance or rejection, the
    formula should first be correctly understood. I believe that
    •the chief obstacle to acceptance of the utilitarian principle
    has been people’s very imperfect grasp of its meaning, and
    that if the misunderstandings of it—or even just the very
    gross ones—could be cleared up, the question would be
    greatly simplified and a large proportion of its difficulties

    3

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    removed. So before I embark on the philosophical grounds
    that can be given for assenting to the utilitarian standard, I
    shall offer some illustrations of the doctrine itself; aiming to

    •show more clearly what it is,
    •distinguish it from what it is not, and
    •dispose of such of the practical objections to it as

    come from or are closely connected with mistaken
    interpretations of its meaning.

    Having thus prepared the ground, I shall afterwards try to
    throw as much light as I can on the question, considered as
    one of philosophical theory.

    Chapter 2: What utilitarianism is

    Some people have supposed that those who stand up for
    ‘utility’ as the test of right and wrong use that term in the
    restricted and merely colloquial sense in which ‘utility’ is
    opposed to pleasure. A passing remark is all that needs to
    be given to that ignorant blunder. [This is probably a protest

    against, among other things, a school-master in Dickens’s fine novel

    Hard Times, whose approach to education insisted on what is ‘useful’

    and flatly opposed any kind of pleasure.] I owe an apology to the
    philosophical opponents of utilitarianism for even briefly
    seeming to regard them as capable of so absurd a misunder-
    standing. The blunder is all the more extraordinary given
    that another of the common charges against utilitarianism is
    the opposite accusation that it bases everything on pleasure
    (understood very crudely). One able writer has pointedly
    remarked that the same sort of persons, and often the very
    same persons, denounce the theory ‘as impracticably dry
    when the word “utility” precedes the word “pleasure”, and
    as too practicably voluptuous when the word “pleasure”
    precedes the word “utility” ’! Those who know anything
    about the matter are aware that every writer from Epicurus
    to Bentham who maintained the theory of ‘utility’ meant

    by it not •something to be contrasted with pleasure but
    •pleasure itself together with freedom from pain; and instead
    of opposing the useful to the agreeable or the ornamental,
    they have always declared that ‘useful’ includes these among
    other things. Yet the common herd, including the herd
    of writers—not only in newspapers and magazines but in
    intellectually ambitious books—are perpetually falling into
    this shallow mistake. Having caught up the word ‘utilitarian’,
    while knowing nothing whatever about it but its sound, they
    habitually express by it keeping out or neglecting pleasure in
    some of its forms, such as beauty, ornament and amusement.
    And when the term ‘utility’ is ignorantly misused in this way,
    it isn’t always in criticism of utilitarianism; occasionally it
    occurs when utilitarianism is being complimented, the idea
    being that utility is something •superior to frivolity and the
    mere pleasures of the moment, ·whereas really it •includes
    them·. This perverted use is the only one in which the
    word ‘utility’ is popularly known, and the one from which
    the young are now getting their sole notion of its meaning.
    Those who introduced the word, but who had for many
    years stopped using it as a doctrinal label, may well feel

    4

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    themselves called upon to resume it, if by doing so they can
    hope to contribute anything towards rescuing it from this
    utter degradation.1

    The doctrine that the basis of morals is utility, or the
    greatest happiness principle, holds that actions are right
    in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong in
    proportion as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.
    By ‘happiness’ is meant pleasure and the absence of pain;
    by ‘unhappiness’ is meant pain and the lack of pleasure. To
    give a clear view of the moral standard set up by the theory,
    much more needs to be said, especially about what things
    the doctrine includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure, and
    to what extent it leaves this as an open question. But these
    supplementary explanations don’t affect the theory of life on
    which this theory of morality is based—namely the thesis
    that

    pleasure and freedom from pain are the only things that
    are desirable as ends, and that

    everything that is desirable at all is so either •for the
    pleasure inherent in it or •as means to the promotion
    of pleasure and the prevention of pain.

    (The utilitarian system has as many things that are desirable,
    in one way or the other, as any other theory of morality.)

    Now, such a theory of life arouses utter dislike in many
    minds, including some that are among the most admirable in
    feeling and purpose. The view that life has (as they express
    it) no higher end —no better and nobler object of desire and
    pursuit—than pleasure they describe as utterly mean and
    grovelling, a doctrine worthy only of pigs. The followers of

    Epicurus were contemptuously compared with pigs, very
    early on, and modern holders of the utilitarian doctrine are
    occasionally subjected to equally polite comparisons by its
    German, French, and English opponents.

    ·Higher and Lower Pleasures·

    When attacked in this way, the Epicureans have always
    answered that it is not they but their accusers who represent
    human nature in a degrading light, because the accusation
    implies that human beings are capable only of pleasures
    that pigs are also capable of. If this were true, there’d
    be no defence against the charge, but then it wouldn’t
    be a charge; for if the sources of pleasure were precisely
    the same for humans as for pigs, the rule of life that is
    good enough for them would be good enough for us. The
    comparison of the Epicurean life to that of beasts is felt
    as degrading precisely because a beast’s pleasures do not
    satisfy a human’s conceptions of happiness. Human beings
    have •higher faculties than the animal appetites, and once
    they become conscious of •them they don’t regard anything
    as happiness that doesn’t include •their gratification. Admit-
    tedly the Epicureans were far from faultless in drawing out
    the consequences of the utilitarian principle; to do this at
    all adequately one must include—·which they didn’t·—many
    Stoic and some Christian elements. But every Epicurean
    theory of life that we know of assigns to the •pleasures
    of the intellect, of the feelings and imagination and of the
    moral sentiments a much higher value as pleasures than

    1 I have reason to believe that I am the first person who brought the word ‘utilitarian’ into ·general· use. I didn’t invent it, but adopted it from a
    passing expression in Mr. Galt’s Annals of the Parish. After using it as a label for several years, he and others abandoned it because of their growing
    dislike for anything resembling a badge or slogan marking out a sect. But as a name for •one single opinion, not •a set of opinions—to stand for the
    recognition of utility as a standard, not any particular way of applying the standard—the term fills a gap in the language, and offers in many cases a
    convenient way of avoiding tiresome long-windedness.

    5

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    to •those of mere sensation. But it must be admitted that
    when utilitarian writers have said that mental pleasures
    are better than bodily ones they have mainly based this on
    mental pleasures being more permanent, safer, less costly
    and so on—i.e. from their circumstantial advantages rather
    than from their intrinsic nature. And on all these points
    utilitarians have fully proved their case; but they could, quite
    consistently with their basic principle, have taken the other
    route—occupying the higher ground, as we might say. It
    is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognise
    that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more
    valuable than others. In estimating ·the value of· anything
    else, we take into account •quality as well as •quantity; it
    would be absurd if the value of pleasures were supposed to
    depend on •quantity alone.

    ‘What do you mean by “difference of quality in pleasures”?
    What, according to you, makes one pleasure •more valuable
    than another, merely as a pleasure, if not its being •greater
    in amount?’ There is only one possible answer to this.

    Pleasure P1 is more desirable than pleasure P2 if: all
    or almost all people who have had experience of both
    give a decided preference to P1, irrespective of any
    feeling that they ought to prefer it.

    If those who are competently acquainted with both these
    pleasures place P1 so far above P2 that •they prefer it even
    when they know that a greater amount of discontent will
    come with it, and •wouldn’t give it up in exchange for
    any quantity of P2 that they are capable of having, we are
    justified in ascribing to P1 a superiority in quality that so
    greatly outweighs quantity as to make quantity comparatively
    negligible.

    Now, it is an unquestionable fact that the way of life
    that employs the higher faculties is strongly preferred ·to
    the way of life that caters only to the lower ones· by people

    who are equally acquainted with both and equally capable of
    appreciating and enjoying both. Few human creatures would
    agree to be changed into any of the lower animals in return
    for a promise of the fullest allowance of animal pleasures;

    •no intelligent human being would consent to be a fool,
    •no educated person would prefer to be an ignoramus,
    •no person of feeling and conscience would rather be
    selfish and base,

    even if they were convinced that the fool, the dunce or the
    rascal is better satisfied with his life than they are with
    theirs. . . . If they ever think they would, it is only in cases of
    unhappiness so extreme that to escape from it they would
    exchange their situation for almost any other, however unde-
    sirable they may think the other to be. Someone with higher
    faculties •requires more to make him happy, •is probably
    capable of more acute suffering, and •is certainly vulnerable
    to suffering at more points, than someone of an inferior type;
    but in spite of these drawbacks he can’t ever really wish
    to sink into what he feels to be a lower grade of existence.
    Explain this unwillingness how you please! We may attribute
    it to

    •pride, a name that is given indiscriminately to some of
    the most and to some of the least admirable feelings
    of which human beings are capable;

    •the love of liberty and personal independence (for the
    Stoics, that was one of the most effective means for
    getting people to value the higher pleasures); or

    •the love of power, or the love of excitement, both of
    which really do play a part in it.

    But the most appropriate label is a sense of dignity. All
    human beings have this sense in one form or another, and
    how strongly a person has it is roughly proportional to how
    well endowed he is with the higher faculties. In those who
    have a strong sense of dignity, their dignity is so essential

    6

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    to their happiness that they couldn’t want, for more than a
    moment, anything that conflicts with it.

    Anyone who thinks that this preference takes place at a
    sacrifice of happiness—anyone who denies that the superior
    being is, other things being anywhere near equal, happier
    than the inferior one—is confusing two very different ideas,
    those of happiness and of contentment. It is true of course
    that the being whose capacities of enjoyment are low has the
    greatest chance of having them fully satisfied ·and thus of
    being contented·; and a highly endowed being will always feel
    that any happiness that he can look for, given how the world
    is, is imperfect. But he can learn to bear its imperfections,
    if they are at all bearable; and they won’t make him envy
    the person who isn’t conscious of the imperfections only
    because he has no sense of the good that those imperfections
    are imperfections of —·for example, the person who isn’t
    bothered by the poor quality of the conducting because he
    doesn’t enjoy music anyway·. It is better to be a human
    being dissatisfied than a pig satisfied; better to be Socrates
    dissatisfied than a fool satisfied. And if the fool or the pig
    think otherwise, that is because they know only their own
    side of the question. The other party to the comparison
    knows both sides.

    ‘But many people who are capable of the higher pleasures
    do sometimes, under the influence of temptation, give prefer-
    ence to the lower ones.’ Yes, but this is quite compatible with
    their fully appreciating the intrinsic superiority of the higher.
    Men’s infirmity of character often leads them to choose the
    nearer good over the more valuable one; and they do this just
    as much when •it’s a choice between two bodily pleasures
    as when •it is between a bodily pleasure and a mental one.
    They pursue sensual pleasures at the expense of their health,
    though they are perfectly aware that health is the greater
    good, ·doing this because the sensual pleasures are nearer·.

    ‘Many people who begin with youthful enthusiasm for
    everything noble, as they grow old sink into laziness and
    selfishness.’ Yes, this is a very common change; but I
    don’t think that those who undergo it voluntarily choose
    the lower kinds of pleasures in preference to the higher.
    I believe that before they devote themselves exclusively to
    the lower pleasures they have already become incapable of
    the higher ones. In most people a capacity for the nobler
    feelings is a very tender plant that is easily killed, not only
    by hostile influences but by mere lack of nourishment; and
    in the majority of young persons it quickly dies away if their
    jobs and their social lives aren’t favourable to keeping that
    higher capacity in use. Men lose their high aspirations as
    they lose their intellectual tastes, because they don’t have
    time or opportunity for indulging them; and they addict
    themselves to lower pleasures not because they deliberately
    prefer them but because they are either •the only pleasures
    they can get or •the only pleasures they can still enjoy. It may
    be questioned whether anyone who has remained equally
    capable of both kinds of pleasure has ever knowingly and
    calmly preferred the lower kind; though throughout the
    centuries many people have broken down in an ineffectual
    attempt to have both at once.

    I don’t see that there can be any appeal against this
    verdict of the only competent judges! On a question as to
    which is the better worth having of two pleasures, or which
    of two ways of life is the more agreeable to the feelings
    (apart from its moral attributes and from its consequences),
    the judgment of those who are qualified by knowledge of
    both must be admitted as final—or, if they differ among
    themselves, the judgment of the majority among them. And
    we can be encouraged to accept this judgment concerning the
    quality of pleasures by the fact that there is no other tribunal
    to appeal to even on the question of quantity. What means

    7

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    do we have for deciding which is the more acute of two pains,
    or the more intense of two pleasurable sensations, other
    than the collective opinion of those who are familiar with
    both? ·Moving back now from quantity to quality·: there are
    different kinds of pain and different kinds of pleasure, and
    every pain is different from every pleasure. What can decide
    whether a particular ·kind of· pleasure is worth purchasing
    at the cost of a particular ·kind of· pain, if not the feelings
    and judgment of those who are experienced ·in both kinds·?
    When, therefore, those feelings and judgments declare the
    pleasures derived from the higher faculties to be preferable in
    kind, apart from the question of intensity, to those that can
    be enjoyed by animals that don’t have the higher faculties,
    their opinion on this subject too should be respected.

    I have dwelt on this point because you need to understand
    it if you are to have a perfectly sound conception of utility
    or happiness, considered as the governing rule of human
    conduct. But you could rationally accept the utilitarian
    standard without having grasped ·that people who enjoy the
    higher pleasures are happier than those who don’t·. That’s
    because the utilitarian standard is not •the agent’s own
    greatest happiness but •the greatest amount of happiness
    altogether; and even if it can be doubted whether a noble
    character is always happier because of its nobleness, such
    a character certainly makes other people happier, and the
    world in general gains immensely from its existence. So
    utilitarianism would achieve its end only through the general
    cultivation of nobleness of character, even if

    each individual got benefit only from the nobleness of
    others, with his own nobleness serving to reduce his
    own happiness.

    But mere statement of this last supposition [the indented one

    just above] brings out its absurdity so clearly that there is no
    need for me to argue against it.

    ·Happiness as an Aim·

    According to the greatest happiness principle as I have
    explained it, the ultimate end. . . ., for the sake of which
    all other things are desirable (whether we are considering
    our own good or that of other people) is an existence as free
    as possible from pain and as rich as possible in enjoyments.
    This means rich in •quantity and in •quality; the test of
    •quality, and the rule for measuring it against •quantity,
    being the preferences of those who are best equipped to
    make the comparison—equipped, that is, by the range of
    their experience and by their habits of self-consciousness
    and self-observation. If the greatest happiness of all is (as
    the utilitarian opinion says it is) •the end of human action, is
    must also be •the standard of morality; which can therefore
    be defined as:

    the rules and precepts for human conduct such that:
    the observance of them would provide the best pos-
    sible guarantee of an existence such as has been
    described—for all mankind and, so far as the nature
    of things allows, for the whole sentient creation.

    Against this doctrine, however, another class of objectors
    rise up, saying that the rational purpose of human life and
    action cannot be happiness in any form. For one thing, it is
    unattainable, they say; and they contemptuously ask ‘What
    right do you have to be happy?’, a question that Mr. Carlyle
    drives home by adding ‘What right, a short time ago, did you
    have even to exist?’. They also say that men can do without
    happiness; that all noble human beings have felt this, and
    couldn’t have become noble except by learning the lesson
    of . . . .renunciation. They say that thoroughly learning and
    submitting to that lesson is the beginning and necessary
    condition of all virtue.

    8

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    If the first of these objections were right, it would go to
    the root of the matter; for if human beings can’t have any
    happiness, the achieving of happiness can’t be the end of
    morality or of any rational conduct. Still, even if human
    beings couldn’t be happy there might still be something to
    be said for the utilitarian theory, because utility includes not
    solely •the pursuit of happiness but also •the prevention or
    lessening of unhappiness; and if the •former aim is illusory
    there will be all the more scope for —and need of —the •latter.
    At any rate, that will be true so long as mankind choose to
    go on living, and don’t take refuge in the simultaneous act
    of suicide recommended under certain conditions by ·the
    German poet· Novalis. But when someone positively asserts
    that ‘It is impossible for human life to be happy’, if this isn’t
    something like a verbal quibble it is at least an exaggeration.
    If ‘happiness’ is taken to mean a continuous state of highly
    pleasurable excitement, it is obvious enough that this is
    impossible. A state of exalted pleasure lasts only moments,
    or—in some cases and with some interruptions—hours or
    days. Such an experience is the occasional •brilliant flash
    of enjoyment, not its •permanent and steady flame. The
    philosophers who have taught that happiness is the end of
    life were as fully aware of this as those who taunt them. The
    ‘happiness’ that they meant was not a life of rapture; but

    a life containing some moments of rapture, a few brief
    pains, and many and various pleasures; a life that is
    much more active than passive; a life based on not
    expecting more from life than it is capable of providing.

    A life made up of those components has always appeared
    worthy of the name of ‘happiness’ to those who have been
    fortunate enough to obtain it. And even now many people
    have such an existence during a considerable part of their
    lives. The present wretched education and wretched social
    arrangements are the only real hindrance to its being attain-

    able by almost everyone. [In Mill’s day ‘education’ tended to have a

    broader meaning than it does today, and to cover every aspect of a young

    person’s upbringing.]

    ‘If human beings are taught to consider happiness as
    the end of life, they aren’t likely to be satisfied with such a
    moderate share of it.’ On the contrary, very many people
    have been satisfied with much less! There seem to be two
    main constituents of a satisfied life, and each of them has
    often been found to be, on its own, sufficient for the purpose.
    They are tranquillity and excitement. Many people find that
    when they have much tranquillity they can be content with
    very little pleasure; and many find that when they have much
    excitement they can put up with a considerable quantity of
    pain. It is certainly possible that a man—and even the mass
    of mankind—should have both tranquillity and excitement.
    So far from being incompatible with one another, they are
    natural allies: prolonging either of them is a preparation
    for the other, and creates a wish for it. The only people
    who don’t desire excitement after a restful period are those
    in whom laziness amounts to a vice; and the only ones
    who dislike the tranquillity that follows excitement—finding
    it •dull and bland rather than •pleasurable in proportion
    to the excitement that preceded it—are those whose need
    for excitement is a disease. When people who are fairly
    fortunate in their material circumstances don’t find sufficient
    enjoyment to make life valuable to them, this is usually
    because they care for nobody but themselves. If someone
    has neither public nor private affections, that will greatly
    reduce the amount of excitement his life can contain, and
    any excitements that he does have will sink in value as the
    time approaches when all selfish interests must be cut off
    by death. On the other hand, someone who leaves after him
    objects of personal affection, especially if he has developed a
    fellow-feeling with the interests of mankind as a whole, will

    9

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    retain as lively an interest in life on the eve of his death as
    he had in the vigour of youth and health. Next to selfishness,
    the principal cause that makes life unsatisfactory is lack of
    mental cultivation [= ‘mental development’]. I am talking here
    not about minds that are cultivated as a philosopher’s is,
    but simply minds that have been open to the fountains
    of knowledge and have been given a reasonable amount
    of help in using their faculties. A mind that is cultivated
    in that sense will find inexhaustible sources of interest in
    everything that surrounds it—in the objects of nature, the
    achievements of art, the imaginations of poetry, the incidents
    of history, human events in the past and present as well
    as their prospects in the future. It is possible to become
    indifferent to all this, even when one hasn’t yet exhausted a
    thousandth part of it; but that can happen only to someone
    who from the beginning has had no •moral or human interest
    in these things, and has looked to them only to •satisfy his
    curiosity.

    ·These two prime requirements of happiness—•mental
    cultivation and •unselfishness—shouldn’t be thought of as
    possible only for a lucky few·. There is absolutely no reason
    in the nature of things why an amount of •mental culture
    sufficient to give an intelligent interest in science, poetry, art,
    history etc. should not be the inheritance of everyone born
    in a civilised country; any more than there’s any inherent
    necessity that any human being should be a •selfish egotist
    whose only feelings and cares are ones that centre on his
    own miserable individuality. Something far superior to this
    is, even now, common enough to give plenty of indication
    of what the human species may become. Genuine private
    affections and a sincere interest in the public good are possi-
    ble, though to different extents, for every rightly brought up
    human being. In a world containing so much to interest us,
    so much for us to enjoy, and so much needing to be corrected

    and improved, everyone who has a moderate amount of
    these moral and intellectual requirements—·unselfishness
    and cultivation·—is •capable of an existence that may be
    called enviable; and such a person will certainly •have this
    enviable existence as long as

    •he isn’t, because of bad laws or conditions of servitude,
    prevented from using the sources of happiness that
    are within his reach; and

    •he escapes the positive evils of life—the great sources
    of physical and mental suffering—such as poverty,
    disease, and bad luck with friends and lovers (turning
    against him, proving to be worthless, or dying young).

    So the main thrust of the problem lies in the battle against
    these calamities. In the present state of things, poverty
    and disease etc. can’t be eliminated, and often can’t even
    be lessened much; and it is a rare good fortune to escape
    such troubles entirely. Yet no-one whose opinion deserves
    a moment’s consideration can doubt that most of the great
    positive evils of the world are in themselves removable, and
    will (if human affairs continue to improve) eventually be
    reduced to something quite small. Poverty, in any sense
    implying suffering, could be completely extinguished by the
    wisdom of society combined with the good sense and gen-
    erosity of individuals. Even that most stubborn of enemies,
    •disease, could be indefinitely reduced in scope by good
    physical and moral education and proper control of noxious
    influences [= ‘air- and water-pollution’]; while the progress of
    science holds out a promise of still more direct conquests
    over •this detestable foe. And every advance in that direction
    reduces the probability of events that would cut short our
    own lives or —more important to us—the lives of others
    in whom our happiness is wrapped up. As for ups and
    downs of fortune, and other disappointments connected with
    worldly circumstances, these are principally the effect of

    10

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    gross foolishness, of desires that got out of control, or of bad
    or imperfect social institutions.

    In short, all the large sources of human suffering are
    to a large extent —and many of them almost entirely—
    conquerable by human care and effort. Their removal is
    grievously slow, and a long succession of generations will
    perish in the battle before the conquest is completed and
    this world becomes what it easily could be if we had the will
    and the knowledge to make it so. Yet despite this, every mind
    that is sufficiently intelligent and generous to play some part
    (however small and inconspicuous) in the effort will draw a
    noble enjoyment from the contest itself—an enjoyment that
    he couldn’t be induced to give up by any bribe in the form of
    selfish indulgence.

    And this leads to the right response to the objectors
    who say that we can, and that we should, do without
    happiness. It is certainly possible to do without happiness;
    nineteen-twentieths of mankind are compelled to do without
    it, even in those parts of our present world that are least deep
    in barbarism. And it often happens that a hero or martyr
    forgoes it for the sake of something that he values more than
    his individual happiness. But what is this ‘something’ if
    it isn’t the happiness of others or something required for
    ·their· happiness? It is noble to be capable of resigning
    entirely one’s own share of happiness, or the chances of it;
    but no-one engages in self-sacrifice just so as to engage in
    self-sacrifice! He must have some end or purpose. You may
    say: ‘The end he aims at in his self-sacrifice is not ·anyone’s·
    happiness; it is virtue, which is better than happiness.’ In
    response to this I ask: Would the sacrifice be made if the hero
    or martyr didn’t think it would spare others from having to
    make similar sacrifices? Would it be made if he thought that
    his renunciation of happiness for himself would produce
    no result for any of his fellow creatures except to make

    their situation like his, putting them in also in the position of
    persons who have renounced happiness? All honour to those
    who can give up for themselves the personal enjoyment of life,
    when by doing this they contribute worthily to increasing the
    amount of happiness in the world; but someone who does
    it, or claims to do it, for any other purpose doesn’t deserve
    admiration any more than does the ascetic living on top of
    his pillar. He may be a rousing proof of what men can do,
    but surely not an example of what they should do.

    ·Self-Sacrifice·

    Only while the world is in a very imperfect state can it
    happen that anyone’s best chance of serving the happiness of
    others is through the absolute sacrifice of his own happiness;
    but while the world is in that imperfect state, I fully admit
    that the readiness to make such a sacrifice is the highest
    virtue that can be found in man. I would add something
    that may seem paradoxical: namely that in this ·present
    imperfect· condition of the world •the conscious ability to do
    without happiness gives the best prospect of bringing about
    such happiness as is attainable. For nothing except that
    •consciousness can raise a person above the chances of life
    by making him feel that fate and fortune—let them do their
    worst!—have no power to subdue him. Once he feels that, it
    frees him from excessive anxiety about the evils of life and
    lets him (like many a Stoic in the worst times of the Roman
    Empire) calmly develop the sources of satisfaction that are
    available to him, not concerning himself with the uncertainty
    regarding how long they will last or the certainty that they
    will end.

    Meanwhile, let utilitarians never cease to claim that they
    have as much right as the Stoic or the Transcendentalist to
    maintain the morality of devotion to a cause as something

    11

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    that belongs to them. The utilitarian morality does recognise
    that human beings can sacrifice their own greatest good
    for the good of others; it merely refuses to admit that the
    sacrifice is itself a good. It regards as wasted any sacrifice
    that doesn’t increase, or tend to increase, the sum total
    of happiness. The only self-renunciation that it applauds
    is devotion to the happiness, or to some of the means to
    happiness, of others. . . .

    I must again repeat something that the opponents of
    utilitarianism are seldom fair enough to admit, namely that
    the happiness that forms the utilitarian standard of what
    is right in conduct is not •the agent’s own happiness but
    •that of all concerned. As between his own happiness and
    that of others, utilitarianism requires him to be as strictly
    impartial as a disinterested and benevolent spectator. [Here

    and everywhere Mill uses ‘disinterested’ in its still-correct meaning = ‘not

    self -interested’ = ‘not swayed by any consideration of how the outcome

    might affect one’s own welfare’.] In the golden rule of Jesus of
    Nazareth we read the complete spirit of the ethics of utility.
    To

    do as you would be done by, and to
    love your neighbour as yourself

    constitute the ideal perfection of utilitarian morality. As
    the ·practical· way to get as close as possible to this ideal,
    ·the ethics of· utility would command two things. (1) First,
    laws and social arrangements should place the happiness
    (or what for practical purposes we may call the interest) of
    every individual as much as possible in harmony with the
    interest of the whole. (2) Education and opinion, which
    have such a vast power over human character, should use
    that power to establish in the mind of every individual an
    unbreakable link between •his own happiness and •the good
    of the whole; especially between •his own happiness and
    •the kinds of conduct (whether doing or allowing) that are

    conducive to universal happiness. If (2) is done properly,
    it will tend to have two results: (2a) The individual won’t
    be able to conceive the possibility of being personally happy
    while acting in ways opposed to the general good. (2b) In
    each individual a direct impulse to promote the general good
    will be one of the habitual motives of action, and the feelings
    connected with it will fill a large and prominent place in
    his sentient existence. This is the true character of the
    utilitarian morality. If those who attack utilitarianism see it
    as being like this, I don’t know •what good features of some
    other moralities they could possibly say that utilitarianism
    lacks, •what more beautiful or more elevated developments
    of human nature any other ethical systems can be supposed
    to encourage, or •what motivations for action that aren’t
    available to the utilitarian those other systems rely on for
    giving effect to their mandates.

    ·Setting the Standard too High?·

    The objectors to utilitarianism can’t be accused of always
    representing it in a •discreditable light. On the contrary,
    objectors who have anything like a correct idea of its disin-
    terested character sometimes find fault with utilitarianism’s
    standard as being •too high for humanity. To require people
    always to act from the •motive of promoting the general
    interests of society—that is demanding too much, they say.
    But this is to mistake the very meaning of a standard of
    morals, and confuse the •rule of action with the •motive for
    acting. It is the business of ethics to tell us what are our
    duties, or by what test we can know them; but no system of
    ethics requires that our only motive in everything we do shall
    be a feeling of duty; on the contrary, ninety-nine hundredths
    of all our actions are done from other motives, and rightly

    12

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    so if the •rule of duty doesn’t condemn them. It is especially
    unfair to utilitarianism to object to it on the basis of this
    particular misunderstanding, because utilitarian moralists
    have gone beyond almost everyone in asserting that the
    motive has nothing to do with the morality of the action
    though it has much to do with the worth of the agent. He
    who saves a fellow creature from drowning does what is
    morally right, whether his motive is duty or the hope of being
    paid for his trouble; he who betrays a friend who trusts him
    is guilty of a crime, even if his aim is to serve another friend
    to whom he is under greater obligations.

    Let us now look at actions that are done from the motive
    of duty, in direct obedience to ·the utilitarian· principle: it
    is a misunderstanding of the utilitarian way of thinking to
    conceive it as implying that people should fix their minds on
    anything as wide as the world or society in general. The great
    majority of good actions are intended not for •the benefit of
    the world but for parts of the good of the world, namely •the
    benefit of individuals. And on these occasions the thoughts
    of the most virtuous man need not go beyond the particular
    persons concerned, except to the extent that he has to assure
    himself that in benefiting those individuals he isn’t violating
    the rights (i.e. the legitimate and authorised expectations)
    of anyone else. According to the utilitarian ethics the object
    of virtue is to multiply happiness; for any person (except
    one in a thousand) it is only on exceptional occasions that
    he has it in his power to do this on an extended scale, i.e.
    to be a public benefactor; and it is only on these occasions
    that he is called upon to consider public utility; in every
    other case he needs to attend only to private utility, the
    interest or happiness of some few persons. The only people
    who need to concern themselves regularly about so large
    an object as society in general are those ·few· whose actions
    have an influence that extends that far. ·Thoughts about the

    general welfare do have a place in everyone’s moral thinking·
    in the case of refrainings—things that people hold off from
    doing, for moral reasons, though the consequences in the
    particular case might be beneficial. The thought in these
    cases is like this: ‘If I acted in that way, my action would
    belong to a class of actions which, if practised generally,
    would be generally harmful, and for that reason I ought not
    to perform it.’ It would be unworthy of an intelligent agent
    not to be consciously aware of such considerations. But the
    amount of regard for the public interest implied in this kind
    of thought is no greater than is demanded by every system of
    morals, for they all demand that one refrain from anything
    that would obviously be pernicious to society; ·so there is no
    basis here for a criticism of utilitarianism in particular·.

    ·Is Utilitarianism Chilly?·

    The same considerations dispose of another reproach against
    the doctrine of utility, based on a still grosser misunderstand-
    ing of the purpose of a standard of morality and of the very
    meanings of the words ‘right’ and ‘wrong’. It is often said
    that utilitarianism •makes men cold and unsympathising;
    that it •chills their moral feelings towards individuals; that it
    •makes them attend only to

    •the dry and hard consideration of the consequences
    of actions,

    leaving out of their moral estimate
    •the ·personal· qualities from which those actions
    emanate.

    If this means that they don’t allow their judgment about the
    rightness or wrongness of an action to be influenced by their
    opinion of the qualities of the person who does it, this is
    a complaint not against •utilitarianism but against •having
    any standard of morality at all; for certainly no known ethical

    13

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    standard declares that an action is good or bad because it
    is done by a good or a bad man, still less because it is done
    by a lovable, brave or benevolent man, or by an unfriendly,
    cowardly or unsympathetic one. These considerations ·of
    personal virtue· are relevant to how we estimate persons,
    not actions; and the utilitarian theory in no way conflicts
    with the fact that there are other things that interest us
    in persons besides the rightness and wrongness of their
    actions. The Stoics, indeed, with the paradoxical misuse
    of language which was part of their system and by which
    they tried to raise themselves to a level at which their only
    concern was with virtue, were fond of saying that he who
    has virtue has everything; that it is the virtuous man, and
    only the virtuous man, who is rich, is beautiful, is a king.
    But the utilitarian doctrine doesn’t make any such claim on
    behalf of the virtuous man. Utilitarians are well aware that
    there are other desirable possessions and qualities besides
    virtue, and are perfectly willing to allow to all of them their
    full worth. They are also aware that •a right action doesn’t
    necessarily indicate a virtuous character, and that •actions
    that are blamable often come from ·personal· qualities that
    deserve praise. When this shows up in any particular case,
    it modifies utilitarian’s estimation not of the act but of the
    agent. They do hold that in the long run the best proof of
    a good character is good actions; and they firmly refuse to
    consider any mental disposition as good if its predominant
    tendency is to produce bad conduct. This, which I freely
    grant, makes utilitarians unpopular with many people; but
    this is an unpopularity that they must share with everyone
    who takes seriously the distinction between right and wrong;
    and the criticism is not one that a conscientious utilitarian
    need be anxious to fend off.

    If the objection means only this:
    Many utilitarians look on the morality of actions, as
    measured by the utilitarian standard, in too exclusive
    a manner, and don’t put enough emphasis on the
    other beauties of character that go towards making a
    human being lovable or admirable,

    this may be admitted. Utilitarians who have cultivated their
    moral feelings but not their sympathies or their artistic
    perceptions do fall into this mistake; and so do all other
    moralists under the same conditions. What can be said in
    excuse of other moralists is equally available for utilitarians,
    namely that if one is to go wrong about this, it is better to
    go wrong on that side, ·rather than caring about lovability
    etc. and ignoring the morality of actions·. As a matter of fact,
    utilitarians are in this respect like the adherents of other
    systems: there is every imaginable degree of rigidity and of
    laxity in how they apply their standard ·of right and wrong·:
    some are puritanically rigorous, while others are as forgiving
    as any sinner or sentimentalist could wish! But on the whole,
    a doctrine that highlights the interest that mankind have
    in the repression and prevention of conduct that violates
    the moral law is likely to do as good a job as any other in
    turning the force of public opinion again such violations. It
    is true that the question ‘What does violate the moral law?’
    is one on which those who recognise different standards
    of morality are likely now and then to differ. But ·that
    isn’t a point against utilitarianism·; difference of opinion
    on moral questions wasn’t first introduced into the world by
    utilitarianism! And that doctrine does supply a tangible and
    intelligible way—if not always an easy one—of deciding such
    differences.

    14

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    ·Utilitarianism as ‘Godless’·

    It may be worthwhile to comment on a few more of the
    common misunderstandings of utilitarian ethics, even those
    that are so obvious and gross that it might appear impossible
    for any fair and intelligent person to fall into them. ·It might
    appear impossible but unfortunately it isn’t·: the crudest
    misunderstandings of ethical doctrines are continually met
    with in the deliberate writings of persons with the greatest
    claims both to high principle and to philosophy. That
    is because people—even very able ones—often take little
    trouble to understand the likely influence of any opinion
    against which they have a prejudice, and are unaware of
    this deliberate ignorance as a defect. We quite often hear the
    doctrine of utility denounced as a godless doctrine. If this
    mere assumption needs to be replied to at all, we may say
    that the question depends on what idea we have formed of
    the moral character of the Deity. If it is true that God desires
    the happiness of his creatures above all else, and that this
    was his purpose in creating them, then utilitarianism, far
    from being a godless doctrine, is the most deeply religious
    of them all. If the accusation is that utilitarianism doesn’t
    recognise the revealed will of God as the supreme law of
    morals, I answer that a utilitarian who believes in the perfect
    goodness and wisdom of God has to believe that whatever
    God has thought fit to reveal on the subject of morals must
    fulfil the requirements of utility in a supreme degree. Others
    besides utilitarians have held this:

    The Christian revelation was intended (and is fitted)
    to bring into the hearts and minds of mankind a spirit
    that will enable them to find for themselves what is
    right, and incline them to do right when they have
    found it; rather than to tell them —except in a very
    general way—what it is. And we need a doctrine of

    ethics, carefully followed out, to know what the will of
    God is.

    We needn’t discuss here whether this is right; because what-
    ever aid religion—either natural or revealed—can provide to
    ethical investigation is as open to the utilitarian moralist as
    to any other. He is as entitled to cite it as God’s testimony to
    the usefulness or hurtfulness of a course of action as others
    are to cite it as pointing to a transcendental law that has no
    connection with usefulness or happiness.

    ·Expediency·

    Again, utilitarianism is often slapped down as an immoral
    doctrine by giving it the name ‘Expediency’, and taking
    advantage of the common use of that term to contrast it
    with ‘Principle’. But when ‘expedient’ is opposed to ‘right’,
    it usually means what is expedient for the particular interest
    of the agent himself, as when a high official sacrifices the
    interests of his country in order to keep himself in place.
    When it means anything better than this, it means what is
    expedient for some immediate temporary purpose, while vio-
    lating a rule whose observance is much more expedient. The
    ‘expedient’ in this sense, instead of being the same thing as
    the •useful, is a branch of the •hurtful. For example, telling
    a lie would often be expedient for escaping some temporary
    difficulty or getting something that would be immediately
    useful to ourselves or others. But (1) the principal support
    of all present social well-being is people’s ability to trust
    one another’s assertions, and the lack of that trust does
    more than anything else to keep back civilisation, virtue,
    everything on which human happiness on the largest scale
    depends. Therefore (2) the development in ourselves of a
    sensitive feeling about truthfulness is one of the most useful
    things that our conduct can encourage, and the weakening of

    15

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    that feeling is one of the most harmful. Finally, (3) any devia-
    tion from truth—even an unintentional one—does something
    towards weakening the trustworthiness of human assertion.
    For these reasons we feel that (4) to obtain an immediate
    advantage by violating such an overwhelmingly expedient
    rule is not expedient, and that someone who acts in that
    way does his bit towards depriving mankind of the good,
    and inflicting on them the harm, involved in the greater or
    less reliance that they can place in each other’s word, thus
    acting as though he were one of mankind’s worst enemies.
    Yet all moralists agree that even this rule ·about telling the
    truth·, sacred as it is, admits of possible exceptions. The
    chief one is the case where the withholding of some fact
    from someone would save an individual (especially someone
    other than oneself) from great and undeserved harm, and
    the only way of withholding it is to lie about it. (Examples:
    keeping information ·about the whereabouts of a weapon·
    from a malefactor, keeping bad news from a person who
    is dangerously ill.) But in order that this exception ·to the
    truth-telling rule· doesn’t extend itself beyond the need for
    it, and has the least possible effect of weakening reliance
    on truth-telling, it ought to be recognised, and if possible its
    limits should be defined; and if the principle of utility is good
    for anything, it must be good for weighing these conflicting
    utilities against one another, and marking out the region
    within which one or the other dominates.

    ·Time to Calculate?·

    Again, defenders of utility often find themselves challenged
    to reply to such objections as this: ‘Before acting, one doesn’t
    have time to calculate and weigh the effects on the general
    happiness of any line of conduct.’ This is just like saying:
    ‘Before acting, one doesn’t have time on each occasion to read

    through the Old and New Testaments; so it is impossible
    for us to guide our conduct by Christianity.’ The answer to
    the objection is that there has been plenty of time, namely,
    the whole past duration of the human species. During all
    that time, mankind have been learning by •experience what
    sorts of consequences actions are apt to have, this being
    something on which all the morality of life depends, as well
    as all the prudence [= ‘decisions about what will further one’s own

    interests’]. The objectors talk as if the start of this course of
    •experience had been put off until now, so that when some
    man feels tempted to meddle with the property or life of
    someone else he has to start at that moment considering
    for the first time whether murder and theft are harmful to
    human happiness! Even if that were how things stand, I
    don’t think he would find the question very puzzling. . . .

    If mankind were agreed in considering utility to be the
    test of morality, they would of course—it would be merely
    fanciful to deny it—reach some agreement about what is
    useful, and would arrange for their notions about this to
    be taught to the young and enforced by law and opinion.
    Any ethical standard whatever can easily be ‘shown’ to work
    badly if we suppose •universal idiocy to be conjoined with
    it! But on any hypothesis short of •that, mankind must by
    this time have acquired positive beliefs as to the effects of
    some actions on their happiness; and the beliefs that have
    thus come down ·to us from the experience of mankind· are
    the rules of morality for the people in general—and for the
    philosopher until he succeeds in finding something better. I
    admit, or rather I strongly assert, that

    •philosophers might easily find something better, even
    now, on many subjects; that

    •the accepted code of ethics is not God-given; and that
    •mankind have still much to learn about how various
    kinds of action affect the general happiness.

    16

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 2: What utilitarianism is

    The corollaries from the principle of utility, like the rules
    of every practical art, can be improved indefinitely, and
    while the human mind is progressing they are constantly
    improving.

    But to consider the intermediate rules of morality as
    unprovable is one thing; to pass over them entirely, trying to
    test each individual action directly by the first principle, is
    another. It is a strange notion that having a •first principle is
    inconsistent with having •secondary ones as well. When you
    tell a traveller the location of the place he wants to get to, you
    aren’t forbidding him to use landmarks and direction-posts
    along the way! The proposition that happiness is the end
    and aim of morality doesn’t mean that no road ought to be
    laid down to that goal, or that people going to it shouldn’t be
    advised to take one direction rather than another. Men
    really ought to stop talking a kind of nonsense on this
    subject –nonsense that they wouldn’t utter or listen to with
    regard to any other practically important matter. Nobody
    argues that the art of navigation is not based on astronomy
    because sailors can’t wait to calculate the Nautical Almanack.
    Because they are rational creatures, sailors go to sea with
    the calculations already done; and all rational creatures
    go out on the sea of life with their minds made up on the
    common questions of right and wrong, as well as on many of
    the much harder questions of wise and foolish. And we can
    presume that they will continue to do so long as foresight
    continues to be a human quality. Whatever we adopt as
    the fundamental principle of morality, we need subordinate
    principles through which to apply it; the absolute need for
    them is a feature of all ·moral· systems, so it doesn’t support
    any argument against any one system in particular. To argue
    solemnly in a manner that presupposes this:

    No such secondary principles can be had; and
    mankind never did and never will draw any general

    conclusions from the experience of human life
    is as totally absurd, I think, as anything that has been
    advanced in philosophical controversy.

    ·Bad Faith·

    The remainder of the standard arguments against utilitarian-
    ism mostly consist in blaming it for •the common infirmities
    of human nature and •the general difficulties that trouble
    conscientious persons when they are shaping their course
    through life. We are told that a utilitarian will be apt to make
    his own particular case an exception to moral rules; and
    that when he is tempted ·to do something wrong· he will see
    more utility in doing it than in not doing it. But is utility the
    only morality that can provide us with excuses for evil doing,
    and means of cheating our own conscience? ·Of course not·!
    Such excuses are provided in abundance by •all doctrines
    that recognise the existence of conflicting considerations as
    a fact in morals; and this is recognized by every doctrine
    that any sane person has believed. It is the fault not •of any
    creed but •of the complicated nature of human affairs that
    rules of conduct can’t be formulated so that they require
    no exceptions, and hardly any kind of action can safely be
    stated to be either always obligatory or always condemnable.

    Every ethical creed softens the rigidity of its laws by
    giving the morally responsible agent some •freedom to adapt
    his behaviour to special features of his circumstances; and
    under every creed, at the •opening thus made, self-deception
    and dishonest reasoning get in. Every moral system allows
    for clear cases of conflicting obligation. These are real
    difficulties, knotty points both in the •theory of ethics and
    in the •practical personal matter of living conscientiously.
    In practice they are overcome, more or less successfully,
    according to the person’s intellect and virtue; but it can’t

    17

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 3: What will motivate us?

    be claimed that having an ultimate standard to which con-
    flicting rights and duties can be referred will make one less
    qualified to deal with them! If utility is the basic source of
    moral obligations, utility can be invoked to decide between
    obligations whose demands are incompatible. The ·utility·
    standard may be hard to apply, but it is better than having
    no standard. In other systems, the moral laws all claim
    independent authority, so that there’s no common umpire
    entitled to settle conflicts between them; when one of them is

    claimed to have precedence over another, the basis for this is
    little better than sophistry, allowing free scope for personal
    desires and preferences (unless the conflict is resolved by the
    unadmitted influence of considerations of utility). It is only
    in these cases of conflict between secondary principles that
    there is any need to appeal to first principles. In every case
    of moral obligation some secondary principle is involved; and
    if there is only one, someone who recognizes that principle
    can seldom be in any real doubt as to which one it is.

    Chapter 3: What will motivate us to obey the principle of utility?

    The question is often asked, and it is a proper question in
    relation to any supposed moral standard,

    What is its sanction? [= ‘What is the reward for conforming

    to it and/or the punishment for not doing so?’]
    What are the motives to obey it?

    or more specifically,
    What is the source of its obligation? Where does it get
    its binding force from?

    It is a necessary part of moral philosophy to provide the
    answer to this question. It often takes the shape of an
    objection to the utilitarian morality in particular, as though
    it were specially applicable to that; but really it arises in
    regard to all standards. It arises, in fact, whenever someone
    is called on to adopt a standard ·that is new to him·, or
    to put morality on some basis on which he hasn’t been
    accustomed to rest it. The only morality that presents itself
    to the mind with the feeling of being in itself obligatory is the
    customary morality, the one that education and opinion have

    •consecrated; and when a person is asked to believe that this
    morality derives its obligation from some general principle
    around which custom has not thrown the same •halo, he
    finds the demand paradoxical; the supposed corollaries seem
    to have a more binding force than the original theorem; the
    superstructure seems to stand better without its supposed
    foundation than with it. He says to himself, ‘I feel that I
    am bound not to rob or murder, betray or deceive; but why
    am I bound to promote the general happiness? If my own
    happiness lies in something else, why may I not give that the
    preference?’

    If the utilitarian philosophy’s view of the nature of the
    moral sense is correct, this difficulty will always present
    itself, until the influences that form moral character have
    taken the same hold of the •principle that they have taken
    of some of its •consequences. That will be the time when
    the improvement of education brings about something that
    Christ certainly intended should come about, namely that

    18

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 3: What will motivate us?

    the •feeling of unity with our fellow-creatures should be
    as deeply rooted in our character, and feel to us to be as
    completely a part of our nature as the •horror of crime is in
    an ordinarily well brought up young person. While we are
    waiting for that day to come, the difficulty has no special
    application to the doctrine of utility, but is inherent in every
    attempt to analyse morality and organize it under principles.
    Unless the first principle already has in men’s minds as
    much sacredness as any of its applications, this process
    always seems to deprive the applications of a part of their
    sanctity.

    The principle of utility either has, or perfectly well could
    have, all the sanctions that belong to any other system of
    morals. Those sanctions are either external or internal. I
    needn’t spend long on the external sanctions. They are

    the hope of favour and the fear of displeasure from
    •our fellow creatures or from •the ruler of the universe,

    and also
    whatever sympathy or affection we may have for •them,
    or whatever love and awe we may have towards •Him,
    inclining us to do ·what they want or· what He wants,
    independently of selfish consequences.

    Obviously there is no reason why all these motives for
    conforming to moral principles shouldn’t attach themselves
    to the utilitarian morality as completely and as powerfully
    as to any other. Indeed, the motives that refer to our fellow
    creatures are sure to do so, insofar as people are intelligent
    enough ·to make the connection·. Here is why. Whether
    or not there is any basis of moral obligation other than the
    general happiness, men do want happiness; and however
    imperfect a particular person’s conduct may be, he does
    desire and commend all conduct by others that promotes his
    happiness. With regard to the religious motive: if men believe
    in the goodness of God (as most of them say they do), those

    who think that conduciveness to the general happiness is
    the essence of good, or even just the criterion of good, must
    believe that general happiness is also what God approves.
    So

    •the whole force of external reward and punishment,
    whether physical or moral and whether coming from
    God or from our fellow men,

    together with
    •everything that human nature is capable of in the way
    of disinterested devotion to God or to man,

    become available ·as sanctions· to enforce ·obedience to·
    the utilitarian morality, in proportion as that morality is
    recognised. And the more the techniques of education and
    general cultivation are put to work on this, the stronger the
    sanctions will be.

    That’s enough about external sanctions. The internal
    sanction of duty is one and the same, whatever our standard
    of duty may be. It is a feeling in our own mind, a more
    or less intense pain that comes with violations of duty;
    and in properly cultivated moral natures it rises in the
    more serious cases into shrinking from the violation as
    an impossibility. When this feeling is disinterested, and
    connected with the pure idea of duty and not with some
    particular form of it or with any of the merely accessory
    circumstances, it is the essence of •conscience; though in
    •that complex phenomenon as it actually exists the simple
    fact ·of pure conscience· is usually all encrusted over with
    associated feelings derived

    from sympathy,
    from love and even more from fear;
    from all the forms of religious feeling;
    from memories of childhood and of all our past life;
    from self-esteem, desire for the esteem of others, and

    occasionally even self-abasement.

    19

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 3: What will motivate us?

    It seems to me that this extreme complicatedness is the
    origin of the sort of mystical character which is apt to be
    attributed to the idea of moral obligation and which leads
    people to think that the idea ·of moral obligation· can’t
    possibly attach itself to any objects except the ones that,
    by a supposed mysterious law, are found in our present
    experience to arouse it. Its binding force, however, consists
    in the existence of a mass of feeling that must be broken
    through in order to do what violates our standard of right;
    and if we do nevertheless violate that standard, the feelings
    will probably have to be encountered afterwards in the form
    of remorse. Whatever theory we have of the nature or origin
    of conscience, this is what it essentially consists of.

    Since the ultimate sanction of all morality (external mo-
    tives apart) is a subjective feeling in our own minds, I see
    nothing awkward for the utilitarian in the question ‘What
    is the sanction of the utilitarian standard?’ We can answer,
    ‘It is the same as of all other moral standards—namely
    the conscientious feelings of mankind.’ Undoubtedly this
    sanction has no binding force for those who don’t have
    the feelings it appeals to; but these people won’t be more
    obedient to any other moral principle than to the utilitarian
    one. No morality of any kind has any hold on them except
    through external sanctions. Meanwhile the feelings do exist,
    a fact in human nature; and experience shows that they are
    real and that they can act with great power on people in
    whom they have been duly developed. No reason has ever
    been shown why they can’t be developed to as great intensity
    in connection with the utilitarian rule of morals as with any
    other.

    I realize that some people are inclined to believe that a
    person who sees in moral obligation

    a transcendental fact, an objective reality belonging
    to the province of ‘things in themselves’

    is likely to be more obedient to moral obligation than one
    who believes it to be

    entirely subjective, being rooted purely in human
    consciousness.

    But whatever a person’s opinion may be on this metaphysical
    point, the force he is really urged by is his own subjective
    feeling, and the •power of the force is exactly measured by
    the •strength of the feeling. No-one’s belief that

    duty is an objective reality
    is stronger than the belief that

    God is an objective reality;
    yet the belief in God, apart from the expectation of actual re-
    ward and punishment, operates on conduct only through the
    subjective religious feeling, and the power of the operation is
    proportional to the strength of the feeling. The sanction, so
    far as it is disinterested, is always in the mind itself; so the
    thought of the transcendental moralists ·I am discussing·
    must be this:

    This sanction won’t exist in the mind unless it is
    believed to have its root outside the mind. If a person
    can say to himself ‘What is now restraining me—what
    is called my conscience—is only a feeling in my own
    mind’, he may draw the conclusion that when the
    feeling ceases the obligation also ceases, and that if
    he finds the feeling inconvenient he may disregard it
    and try to get rid of it.

    But is this danger confined to the utilitarian morality? Does
    the belief that moral obligation has its seat outside the mind
    make the feeling of it too strong for you to get rid of it? The
    facts are otherwise—so much so that all moralists admit
    and lament how easy it is for conscience to be silenced or
    stifled in most people’s minds. People who never heard
    of the principle of utility ask themselves ‘Need I obey my
    conscience?’ just as often as do utilitarians. Those whose

    20

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 3: What will motivate us?

    conscientious feelings are so weak as to allow them to ask
    this question, if they answer ‘Yes’ they will do so not because
    •they believe in the transcendental theory but because of
    •the external sanctions.

    It isn’t necessary for present purposes to decide whether
    the feeling of duty is innate or implanted [i.e. whether it is part

    of our natural birthright or is acquired along the way through education

    or whatever]. Assuming it to be innate, the question remains
    as to what duties the feeling naturally attaches itself to;
    for the philosophic supporters of the innateness theory are
    now agreed that ·what is given to us innately·—what we
    have an intuitive perception of—is the •principles of morality
    and not its •details. If there is anything innate in all this,
    I don’t see why the feeling that is innate shouldn’t be the
    feeling of •concern for the pleasures and pains of others. If
    any principle of morals is intuitively obligatory, I should say
    it must be •that one. If so, intuitive ·innatist· ethics would
    coincide with utilitarian ethics, and there would be no further
    quarrel between them. Even as things stand, although the
    intuitive moralists believe that there are other intuitive moral
    obligations, they do already believe that this —·the obligation
    to seek the welfare of others·—is one; for they all hold that
    a large portion of morality turns on the consideration that
    should be given to the interests of our fellow-creatures. So
    if the belief in the transcendental origin of moral obligation
    does give any additional force to the internal sanction, it
    appears to me that the utilitarian principle already has the
    benefit of it.

    On the other hand, if the moral feelings are not innate
    but acquired (as I think they are), that doesn’t make them
    any less natural. It is natural for man to speak, to reason,
    to build cities, to cultivate the ground, though these are
    acquired abilities. The moral feelings are indeed not ‘a part
    of our nature’ in the sense of being detectably present in all

    of us; but this is a sad fact admitted by the most strenuous
    believers in the transcendental origin of those feelings. Like
    the other acquired capacities I have referred to, the moral
    faculty, if not a part of our nature, is a natural outgrowth
    from it. Like them, it can to a certain small extent spring
    up spontaneously and can be brought by cultivation to a
    high degree of development. Unfortunately, it can —by a
    sufficient use of external sanctions and of the force of early
    impressions—be cultivated in almost any direction; so that
    there is hardly anything so absurd or so mischievous that
    these influences can’t make it act on the human mind with
    all the authority of conscience. To doubt that the same power
    might be given by the same means to the principle of utility,
    even if it had no foundation in human nature, would be
    flying in the face of all experience.

    But while the culture of the intellect continues, purely
    artificial moral associations gradually give way through the
    dissolving force of analysis. If this were the case:

    •The feeling of duty when associated with utility seems
    as arbitrary ·as any of those others·;

    •There is no prominent part of our make-up, no pow-
    erful class of feelings, with which that association
    harmonizes, making us feel it as congenial and inclin-
    ing us not only to encourage it in others (for which we
    have abundant ·self·-interested motives), but also to
    value it in ourselves; in short,

    •Utilitarian morality has no natural basis in our feel-
    ings,

    —in that case it might well happen that this association ·of
    duty with utility· was analysed away, even after it had been
    implanted by education. But there is this basis of powerful
    natural sentiment; and this will constitute the strength of
    the utilitarian morality once general happiness is recognised
    as the ethical standard. This firm foundation is that of

    21

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 3: What will motivate us?

    the social feelings of mankind; the desire to be in unity
    with our fellow creatures. It is already a powerful force in
    human nature, and fortunately one of those that tend to be
    made stronger—even without being explicitly taught —by
    the influences of advancing civilisation. The social state is
    at once so natural, so necessary and so habitual to a man
    that, except in some unusual circumstances or an effortful
    thought-experiment, he never thinks of himself as anything
    but a member of a group; and this association becomes
    stronger and stronger as mankind moves further from the
    state of savage independence. Thus, any condition that is
    essential to a state of society becomes more and more an
    inseparable part of each person’s conception of the state of
    things that he is born into and that is the destiny of a human
    being.

    Now society between human beings—except in the re-
    lation of master to slave—is obviously impossible on any
    other basis than that the interests of all are to be consulted.
    Society between •equals can only exist on the understanding
    that the interests of all are to be regarded •equally. And
    since in all states of civilisation every person except an
    absolute monarch has equals, everyone is obliged to live on
    these terms with somebody; and in every age some advance
    is made towards a state in which it will be impossible to
    live permanently with anybody except on terms of equality.
    In this way people grow up unable to think of a state of
    total disregard of other people’s interests as one they could
    possibly live in. They have to conceive of themselves as at
    least refraining from all the most harmful crimes and (if
    only for their own protection) living in a state of constant
    protest against them. They are also familiar with the fact of
    co-operating with others and of acting (at least for the time
    being) in the interests of a group rather than of themselves
    as individuals. So long as they are co-operating, their

    purposes are identified with those of others; there is at
    least a temporary feeling that the interests of others are their
    own interests. All strengthening of social ties and all healthy
    growth of society gives to each individual a stronger personal
    interest in •acting with regard for the welfare of others; and
    it also leads him to identify his •feelings more and more with
    their good, or at least with an even greater degree of concern
    for it in his actions. He comes, as though instinctively,
    to be conscious of himself as a being who pays regard to
    others as a matter of course. The good of others becomes
    to him a thing naturally and necessarily to be attended to,
    like any of the physical conditions of our existence. Now,
    however •much or little of this feeling a person has, he has
    the strongest motives both of ·self·-interest and of sympathy
    to express this feeling in his behaviour, and to do all he can
    to encourage it in others; and even if he has •none of it
    himself, it is as much in his interests as in anyone else’s that
    others should have it. Consequently the smallest seeds of the
    feeling are laid hold of and nourished by the •contagion of
    sympathy and the •influences of education; and a complete
    web of supporting association is woven around it by the
    powerful force of the external sanctions. [Regarding ‘contagion’:

    Mill means merely that through sympathy a feeling can be passed on

    from one person to another.]
    As civilisation goes on, this way of thinking about our-

    selves and about human life is increasingly felt to be natural.
    Every step in political improvement makes it more so, by

    •removing the sources of conflicts of interest, and
    •removing the inequalities in legal status between
    individuals or classes, because of which it is still prac-
    ticable to disregard the happiness of large portions of
    mankind.

    As the human mind improves, there is a steady increase
    in the influences that tend to generate in each individual a

    22

    Utilitarianism John Stuart Mill 3: What will motivate us?

    feeling of unity with all the rest; a feeling which in its perfect
    state would make him never think of or want any benefit for
    himself if it didn’t also involve benefits for all the rest. Now
    suppose this were the case:

    This feeling of unity is taught as a religion. The whole
    force of education, of institutions and of opinion is
    directed—as it used to be in the case of religion—
    to making every person grow up from infancy sur-
    rounded on all sides both by people who have the
    feeling of unity, who say they have it, and who act on
    it.

    I don’t think that anyone who can realize this conception
    [= ‘make it real to himself in his mind’] will have any doubts about
    the sufficiency of the ultimate sanction for the happiness
    morality. To any student of ethics who finds the realization
    difficult [i.e. who can’t get a real sense of what it would be like if the

    above scenario came true], I recommend that he get help from
    the second of M. Comte’s two principal works, the Traité
    de politique positive. I have the strongest objections to the
    system of politics and morals presented in that book; but I
    think it has more than adequately shown the possibility of

    •giving to the service of humanity, even without help
    from a belief in God, both the psychological power and
    the social effectiveness of a religion; and •making it
    take hold of human life and colour all thought, feeling
    and action far more thoroughly than any religion has
    ever done; the danger being not that it might be insuf-
    ficient but that it might be so excessive as to interfere
    unduly with human freedom and individuality.

    This feeling ·of unity· that constitutes the binding force
    of the utilitarian morality on those who accept it doesn’t
    have to wait until . . . .everyone has it. It’s true that in the
    comparatively early state of human advancement in which
    we now live, a person can’t feel such total sympathy with

    everyone else that he couldn’t do anything that would work
    against their interests; but even now a person in whom the
    social feeling is at all developed can’t bring himself to think
    of the rest of his fellow creatures as struggling rivals with
    him for the means of happiness, rivals whom he must want
    to see defeated in their aims so that he can succeed in his.
    The deeply rooted conception that every individual has of
    himself as a social being, even now, tends to make him feel it
    as one of his natural wants that his feelings and aims should
    harmonize with those of his fellow creatures. (If differences
    of opinion and of mental culture make it impossible for him
    to share many of their actual feelings—perhaps even make
    him denounce and defy those feelings—he still needs to be
    aware that his real aim doesn’t conflict with theirs, and that
    he isn’t •opposing but •promoting what they really wish for,
    namely their own good.) In most individuals this feeling ·of
    unity· is much weaker than their selfish feelings, and is often
    entirely lacking. But to those who have it, it bears all the
    marks of a natural feeling. It doesn’t present itself to their
    minds as •a superstition they were brought up in or •a law
    forced on them by the power of society, but as •an attribute
    that it would be bad for them to lack. This conviction is
    the ultimate sanction of the greatest happiness morality. It
    is this that •makes any mind with well-developed feelings
    work with rather than against the outward motives to care
    for others, the motives provided by what I have called ‘the
    external sanctions’; and when those sanctions are absent or
    act in an opposite direction, •constitutes in itself an internal
    binding force that is strong in proportion to the sensitiveness
    and thoughtfulness of the ·person’s· character. Apart from
    people whose mind is a moral blank, few could bear to lay
    out their course of life on the plan of paying no regard to
    others except in ways that would serve their own interests.

    23

      Chapter 1: General Remarks

      Chapter 2: What utilitarianism is

      ·Higher and Lower Pleasures·

      ·Happiness as an Aim·

      ·Self-Sacrifice·

      ·Setting the Standard too High?·

      ·Is Utilitarianism Chilly?·

      ·Utilitarianism as `Godless’·

      ·Expediency·

      ·Time to Calculate?·

      ·Bad Faith·

      Chapter 3: What will motivate us to obey the principle of utility?

    38
    THE TELEOLOGICAL

    ARGUMENT
    Robin Collins

    Introduction

    Design arguments have a long history, probably being the most commonly cited
    argument for believing in a deity

    .

    In ancient India, for instance, the argument from
    design was advanced by the so-called Nyaya (or logical-atomist) school (100–1000
    ce), which argued for the existence of a deity based on the order of the world, which
    they compared both to human artifacts and to the human body (Smart 1964: 153–4).
    In the West, the design argument goes back to at least Heraclitus (500 bce). It
    reached its highpoint with the publication of Paley’s Natural Theology (1802), which
    primarily appealed to the intricate structure of plants and animals as evidence for
    design. With the advent of Darwin’s theory of evolution, this version of the argument
    underwent an almost fatal blow, although it has gained a small following since the
    1990s among advocates of the so-called intelligent design movement. By far the
    most widely cited evidence for design, however, is that from findings in physics and
    cosmology during the twentieth century. In this chapter we will mainly focus on the
    evidence from the so-called fine-tuning of the cosmos for conscious, embodied life
    (CEL), although we will briefly look at other evidence from the beauty and elegance
    of the laws of nature.

    the evidence of fine-tuning

    Many examples of this fine-tuning can be given, a few of which we will briefly recount
    here. One particularly important category of fine-tuning is that of the constants of
    physics. The constants of physics are a set of fundamental numbers that, when plugged
    into the laws of physics, determine the basic structure of the universe. An example of
    such a constant is the gravitational constant G that is part of Newton’s law of gravity,
    F 5 GM1M2/r

    2. G essentially determines the strength of gravity between two masses.
    If one were to double the value of G, for instance, then the force of gravity between
    any two masses would double.

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    ROBIN COLLINS

    412

    So far, physicists have discovered four forces in nature: gravity, the weak nuclear
    force, electromagnetism, and the strong nuclear force that binds protons and neutrons
    together in an atom. As measured in a certain set of standard dimensionless units
    (Barrow and Tipler 1986: 292–5), gravity is the least strong of the four forces, and the
    strong nuclear force is the strongest, being a factor of 1040 – or ten thousand billion,
    billion, billion, billion – times stronger than gravity.
    Various calculations show that the strength of each of the forces of nature must
    fall into a very small CEL-permitting region for CEL to exist. As just one example,
    consider gravity. Compared to the total range of forces, the strength of gravity must
    fall in a relatively narrow range in order for CEL to exist. If we increased the strength
    of gravity a billion-fold, for instance, the force of gravity on a planet with the mass
    and size of the earth would be so great that organisms anywhere near the size of human
    beings, whether land-based or aquatic, would be crushed. (The strength of materials
    depends on the electromagnetic force via the fine-structure constant, which would
    not be affected by a change in gravity.) Even a much smaller planet of only 40 feet in
    diameter – which is not large enough to sustain organisms of our size – would have a
    gravitational pull of one thousand times that of earth, still too strong for organisms of
    our brain size, and hence level of intelligence, to exist. As astrophysicist Martin Rees
    notes, ‘In an imaginary strong gravity world, even insects would need thick legs to
    support them, and no animals could get much larger’ (Rees 2000: 30). Other calcula-
    tions show that if the gravitational force were increased by more than a factor of 3000,
    the maximum lifetime of a star would be a billion years, thus severely inhibiting the
    probability of CEL evolving (Collins 2003). Of course, a three-thousand-fold increase
    in the strength of gravity is a lot, but compared to the total range of the strengths of
    the forces in nature (which span a range of 1040, as we saw above), it is very small,
    being one part in a billion, billion, billion, billion.
    There are other cases of the fine-tuning of the constants of physics besides the
    strength of the forces, however. Probably the most widely discussed (and esoteric)
    among physicists and cosmologists is the fine-tuning of what is known as the
    cosmological constant. This is a number in Einstein’s theory of general relativity that
    influences the expansion rate of the universe. If the cosmological constant were not
    fine-tuned to within an extremely narrow range – one part in 1053 or even 10120 of its
    ‘theoretically possible’ range of values – the universe would expand so rapidly that all
    matter would quickly disperse, and thus galaxies, stars, and even small aggregates of
    matter could never form (see, e.g., Rees 2000: 95–102, 154–5; Collins 2003).
    Besides the constants of physics, however, there is also the fine-tuning of the laws.
    If the laws of nature were not just right, CEL would probably be impossible. For
    example, consider again the four forces of nature. If gravity (or a force like it) did
    not exist, masses would not clump together to form stars or planets and hence the
    existence of complex CEL would be seriously inhibited, if not rendered impossible;
    if the electromagnetic force didn’t exist, there would be no chemistry; if the strong
    force didn’t exist, protons and neutrons could not bind together and hence no atoms
    with atomic numbers greater than hydrogen would exist; and if the strong force were
    a long-range force (like gravity and electromagnetism) instead of a short-range force

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

    413

    that only acts between protons and neutrons in the nucleus, all matter would either
    almost instantaneously undergo nuclear fusion and explode or be sucked together
    forming a black hole.
    Similarly, other laws and principles are necessary for CEL. As the prominent
    Princeton physicist Freeman Dyson points out (1979: 251), if the Pauli-exclusion
    principle did not exist, which dictates that no two fermions can occupy the same
    quantum state, all electrons would occupy the lowest atomic orbit, eliminating
    complex chemistry; and if there were no quantization principle, which dictates that
    particles can only occupy certain discrete allowed quantum states, there would be no
    atomic orbits and hence no chemistry since all electrons would be sucked into the
    nucleus.
    Finally, in his book Nature’s Destiny, the biochemist Michael Denton extensively
    discusses various higher-level features of the natural world, such as the many unique
    properties of carbon, oxygen, water, and the electromagnetic spectrum, that are
    conducive to the existence of complex biochemical systems. As one of many examples
    Denton presents, both the atmosphere and water are transparent to electromagnetic
    radiation in a thin band in the visible region, but are transparent nowhere else except
    to radio waves. If, instead, either of them absorbed electromagnetic radiation in the
    visible region, the existence of terrestrial CEL would be seriously inhibited, if not
    rendered impossible (Denton 1998: 56–7). These higher-level coincidences indicate a
    deeper level fine-tuning of the fundamental laws and constants of physics.
    As the above examples indicate, the evidence for fine-tuning is extensive, even
    if one has doubts about some individual cases. As the philosopher John Leslie has
    pointed out, ‘clues heaped upon clues can constitute weighty evidence despite doubts
    about each element in the pile’ (Leslie 1988: 300). At the very least, these cases of
    fine-tuning show the truth of Freeman Dyson’s observation that there are many ‘lucky
    accidents in physics’ (1979: 251) without which CEL would be impossible.

    the argument formulated

    Now it is time to consider the way in which the existence of a fine-tuned universe
    supports theism. In this section, I will argue that the evidence of fine-tuning primarily
    gives us a reason for preferring theism over what could be called the naturalistic
    single-universe hypothesis (NSU): the hypothesis that there is only one universe, and
    it exists as a brute fact. (We will examine the typical alternative explanation of the
    fine-tuning offered by many atheists – what I call the ‘many-universes hypothesis’ – in
    a section below.) We will present our argument for the case of the fine-tuning of the
    constants, but with some modifications it will apply to the other types of fine-tuning
    for CEL mentioned above.
    Although the fine-tuning argument against the NSU can be cast in several different
    forms – such as inference to the best explanation – I believe the most rigorous way
    of formulating the argument is in terms of what is often called the likelihood principle,
    a standard principle of confirmation theory (e.g., see Sober 2002). Simply put, the
    principle says that whenever we are considering two competing hypotheses, an observation

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    ROBIN COLLINS

    414

    counts as evidence in favor of the hypothesis under which the observation has the highest
    probability (or is the least improbable). Since the type of probability in the likelihood
    principle is what is known as epistemic probability (see below), the likelihood principle
    can be reworded more intuitively in terms of what could be called the surprise principle:
    namely, whenever we are considering two competing hypotheses, an observation
    counts as evidence in favor of the hypothesis under which it is least surprising.
    Moreover, the degree to which the observation counts in favor of one hypothesis over
    another is proportional to the degree to which the observation is more probable (or
    less surprising) under the one hypothesis than the other.
    Using this principle, we can develop the fine-tuning argument in a two-step form
    as follows:

    Premise (1) The existence of a fine-tuned universe with CEL is not highly
    improbable (or surprising) under theism.

    Premise (2) The existence of a fine-tuned universe with CEL is very
    improbable (surprising) under the NSU.

    Conclusion: From premises (1) and (2) and the likelihood principle, it follows
    that the fine-tuning data provides significant evidence to favor the design
    hypothesis over the NSU.

    At this point, we should pause to note two features of this argument. First, the
    argument does not say that the fine-tuning evidence proves that the universe was
    designed, or even that it is likely that the universe was designed. Indeed, of itself it
    does not even show that we are epistemically warranted in believing in theism over
    the NSU. In order to justify these sorts of claims, we would have to look at the full
    range of evidence both for and against the design hypothesis – something I am not
    doing in this chapter. Rather, the argument merely concludes that the fine-tuning
    significantly supports theism over the NSU. (I say ‘significantly supports’ because
    presumably the ratio of probabilities for the fine-tuning under theism versus the NSU
    is quite large.)
    In this way, the evidence of the fine-tuning argument is much like a defendant’s
    DNA being found on the murder weapon, in a trial. By the ‘likelihood’ or ‘surprise
    principle,’ the DNA on the murder weapon provides significant evidence that
    the defendant is guilty because its existence would be much more surprising if the
    defendant were innocent than if he were guilty. Yet one could not conclude merely
    from the DNA alone that the defendant is guilty, for there could be other counter-
    vailing evidence, such as the testimony of reliable witnesses that he was not at the
    scene of the crime. The DNA would still count as significant evidence of guilt, but
    this evidence would be counterbalanced by the testimony of the witnesses. Similarly
    the evidence of fine-tuning significantly supports theism over the NSU, though it does
    not itself show that, everything considered, theism is the most plausible explanation
    of the existence of a universe with CEL.

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

    415

    Support for the premises

    Support for Premise (1): Premise (1) is easy to support and somewhat less controversial
    than premise (2). The argument in support of it can be simply stated as follows: since
    God is an all-good being, and in and of itself it is good for intelligent, conscious beings to
    exist, it is not highly surprising or highly improbable that God would create a world that could
    support CEL. Thus, the fine-tuning is not highly improbable under theism.
    Support for Premise (2): Upon looking at the data, many people find it very obvious
    that the fine-tuning is highly improbable under the NSU. And it is easy to see why
    when we think of the fine-tuning in terms of various analogies. In the ‘dart-board
    analogy,’ for example, the theoretically possible values for fundamental constants of
    physics can be represented as a dart-board that fills the whole galaxy, and the condi-
    tions necessary for CEL to exist as a small inch-wide target. Accordingly, from this
    analogy it seems obvious that it would be highly improbable for the fine-tuning to
    occur under the NSU – that is, for the dart to hit the target by chance.
    Now some philosophers, such as Keith Parsons (1990: 182), object to the claim
    that the fine-tuning is highly improbable under the NSU by arguing that since we
    only have one universe, the notion of the fine-tuning of the universe being probable
    or improbable is meaningless.
    Although I do not have space to provide a full-scale response to this objection, I
    will briefly sketch an answer. The first is to note that the relevant notion of probability
    occurring in the fine-tuning argument is a widely recognized type of probability called
    epistemic probability (e.g., see Hacking 1975; Plantinga 1993: chs. 8 and 9). Roughly,
    the epistemic probability of a proposition can be thought of as the degree of confi-
    dence or belief we rationally should have in the proposition. Further, the conditional
    epistemic probability of a proposition R on another proposition S – written as P(R/S)
    – can be defined as the degree to which the proposition S of itself should rationally lead
    us to expect that R is true. Under the epistemic conception of probability, therefore,
    the statement that the fine-tuning of the cosmos is very improbable under the NSU is to
    be understood as making a statement about the degree to which the NSU would or
    should, of itself, rationally lead us to expect cosmic fine-tuning.
    The notion of itself is important here. The rational degree of expectation should
    not be confused with the degree to which one should expect the constants of physics
    to fall within the CEL range if one believed the NSU. For even those who believe in
    this hypothesis should expect the constants of physics to be CEL-permitting since this
    follows from the fact that we are alive. Rather, the conditional epistemic probability in
    this case is the degree to which the NSU of itself should lead us to expect constants of
    physics to be CEL-permitting. This means that in assessing the conditional epistemic
    probability in this and other similar cases, one must exclude contributions to our
    expectations arising from other information we have, such as that we are alive. In
    the case at hand, one way of doing this is by means of the following sort of thought
    experiment. Imagine a disembodied being with mental capacities and a knowledge
    of physics comparable to that of the most intelligent physicists alive today, except
    that the being does not know whether the values of the constants of physics allow

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    ROBIN COLLINS

    416

    for CEL to arise. Further, suppose that this disembodied being believed in the NSU.
    Then, the degree that being should rationally expect the constants of physics to be
    CEL-permitting will be equal to our conditional epistemic probability, since its expec-
    tation is solely a result of its belief in the NSU, not other factors such as its awareness
    of its own existence.
    Given this understanding of the notion of conditional epistemic probability, it is not
    difficult to see that the conditional epistemic probability of a constant of physics having
    a CEL-permitting value under the NSU will be much smaller than under theism. The
    reason is simple when we think about our imaginary disembodied being. If such a being
    were a theist, it would have some reason to believe that the values of constants would
    fall into the CEL-permitting region (see the argument in support of premise (1) above).
    On the other hand, if the being were a subscriber to the NSU, it would have no reason
    to think the value would be in the CEL-permitting region instead of any other part of
    the ‘theoretically possible’ region R. Thus, the being has more reason to believe the
    constants would fall into the CEL-permitting region under theism than the NSU; that
    is, the epistemic probability under theism is larger than under the NSU, or put differ-
    ently, the existence of a CEL-permitting universe is more surprising under the NSU
    than theism. How much more surprising? That depends on the degree of fine-tuning.
    Here, I will simply note that it seems obvious that in general the higher the degree
    of fine-tuning – that is, the smaller the width of the CEL-permitting range is to the
    ‘theoretically possible’ range – the greater the surprise under the NSU, and hence the
    greater the ratio of the two probabilities. To go beyond these statements and to assign
    actual epistemic probabilities (or degrees of surprise) under the NSU – or to further
    justify these claims of improbability – would require defending a version of the proba-
    bilistic principle of indifference, which is beyond the scope of this chapter.

    Objections to the argument

    As powerful as the fine-tuning argument against the NSU is, several major objections
    have been raised to it by both atheists and theists. In this section, we will consider
    some of these objections in turn.

    Objection 1: more fundamental law objection

    One criticism of the fine-tuning argument is that, as far as we know, there could be a
    more fundamental law under which the constants of physics must have the values they
    do. Thus, given such a law, it is not improbable that the known constants of physics
    fall within the CEL-permitting range. Besides being entirely speculative, the problem
    with postulating such a law is that it simply moves the improbability of the fine-
    tuning up one level, to that of the postulated physical law itself. As the astrophysicists
    Bernard Carr and Martin Rees note, ‘even if all apparently anthropic coincidences
    could be explained [in terms of some grand unified theory], it would still be remarkable
    that the relationships dictated by physical theory happened also to be those propitious
    for CEL’ (Carr and Rees 1979: 612).

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

    417

    For the theist, then, the development of a grand unified theory would not undercut
    the case for design, but would only serve to deepen our appreciation of the ingenuity
    of the creator. Instead of separately fine-tuning each individual parameter, in this view,
    the designer simply carefully chose those laws that would yield CEL-permitting values
    for each parameter.

    Objection 2: other forms of CEL objection

    Another objection commonly raised against the fine-tuning argument is that as far as
    we know, other forms of CEL could exist even if the constants of physics were different.
    So, it is claimed, the fine-tuning argument ends up presupposing that all forms of CEL
    must be like us. One answer to this objection is that many cases of fine-tuning do not
    make this presupposition. If, for example, the cosmological constant were much larger
    than it is, matter would disperse so rapidly that no planets, and indeed no stars, could
    exist. Without stars, however, there would exist no stable energy sources for complex
    material systems of any sort to evolve. So, all the fine-tuning argument presupposes
    in this case is that the evolution of CEL requires some stable energy source. This is
    certainly a very reasonable assumption.

    Objection 3: the ‘Who Designed God?’ objection

    Perhaps the most common objection that atheists raise to the argument from design,
    of which the fine-tuning argument is one instance, is that postulating the existence
    of God does not solve the problem of design but merely transfers it up one level,
    to the question of who designed God. One response to the above argument is that
    it only relies on comparison of the epistemic probabilities of fine-tuning under the
    two different hypotheses, not on whether the new hypothesis reduces the overall
    complexity of one’s worldview. As an analogy, if complex, intricate structures (such
    as aqueducts and buildings) existed on Mars, one could conclude that their existence
    would support the hypothesis that intelligent, extraterrestrial beings existed on Mars
    in the past, even if such beings are much more complex than the structures to be
    explained.
    Second, however, for reasons entirely independent of the argument from design,
    God has been thought to have little, if any internal complexity. Indeed, medieval
    philosophers and theologians often went as far as advocating the doctrine of divine
    simplicity, according to which God is claimed to be absolutely simple, without any
    internal complexity. So, atheists who push this objection have a lot of arguing to do to
    make it stick. (For a more detailed treatment of the ‘Who Designed God?’ objection,
    see Collins 2005.)

    the many-universes hypothesis

    Another objection to considering fine-tuning as evidence for design is one that takes
    us almost into the realm of science fiction: the proposal that there are a very large

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    ROBIN COLLINS

    418

    number of universes, each with different values for the fundamental parameters of
    physics. If such multiple universes exist, it would be no surprise that the parameters in
    one of them would have just the right values for the existence of CEL, just as in the
    case where if enough lottery tickets were generated, it would be no surprise that one
    of them turned out to be the winning number.
    How did these universes come into existence? Typically, the answer is to postulate
    some kind of physical process, what I will call a ‘universe generator.’ Against the
    naturalistic version of the universe-generator hypothesis, one could argue that the
    universe generator itself must be ‘well designed’ to produce even one CEL-sustaining
    universe. After all, even a mundane item such as a bread-making machine, which
    only produces loaves of bread instead of universes, must be well-designed as an
    appliance and have just the right ingredients (flour, yeast, gluten, and so on) in just
    the right amounts to produce decent loaves of bread. Indeed, as I have shown in detail
    elsewhere (Collins 2009), if one carefully examines the most popular and most well-
    developed universe-generator hypothesis – that arising out of inflationary cosmology
    – one finds that it contains just the right fields and laws to generate CEL-permitting
    universes. Eliminate or modify one of the fields or laws by just a little bit, and no
    CEL-sustaining universes would be produced. If this is right, then invoking some sort
    of universe generator as an explanation of fine-tuning only pushes the issue of design
    up one level to the question of who or what designed it.
    Besides the universe generator hypothesis, a very small minority of scientists
    and philosophers have proposed what could be called a metaphysical many-universe
    hypothesis, according to which universes are thought to exist on their own without
    being generated by any physical process. Typically, advocates of this view – such as
    the late Princeton University philosopher David Lewis (1986) and the University of
    Pennsylvania astrophysicist Max Tegmark (1998) – claim that every possible set of
    laws is instantiated in some universe or another. One problem with this hypothesis
    is that it cannot explain why we inhabit a universe that is so orderly and has such
    low initial entropy: it is much more likely for there to exist local islands with the
    sort of order necessary for CEL than for the entire universe to have such an ordered
    arrangement. Thus, their hypothesis cannot explain the highly ordered character of
    the universe as a whole.
    Among others, George Schlesinger has raised this objection against Lewis’s
    hypothesis (1984). This sort of objection was raised against a similar explanation
    of the high degree of order in our universe offered by the famous physicist Ludwig
    Boltzmann, and has generally been considered fatal to Boltzmann’s explanation
    (Davies 1974: 103).
    Despite these objections and the fact that the multiple-universe hypothesis
    typically has been advanced by naturalists as an alternative explanation to design, I
    am not objecting to the notion of many universes itself. I actually believe that theists
    should be open to the idea that God created our universe by means of a universe
    generator. It makes some sense that an infinitely creative deity would create other
    universes, not just our own.

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

    419

    Other evidences for design

    Besides the fine-tuning for CEL, there are other significant evidences for design
    based on the findings of physics and cosmology, such as the extraordinary degree
    of beauty, elegance, harmony, and ingenuity exhibited by the fundamental mathe-
    matical structure of the universe. For instance, Nobel Prize-winning physicist Steven
    Weinberg, himself an atheist, devotes a whole chapter of his book, Dreams of a Final
    Theory (ch. 6, ‘Beautiful theories’), to explaining how the criteria of beauty and
    elegance are commonly used to guide physicists in formulating the right laws. Because
    this beauty and elegance has been so successful in guiding physicists in developing
    highly successful theories, it is difficult to claim that this beauty and elegance is
    merely in the eye of the beholder. Today, this use of beauty and elegance as a guide is
    particularly evident in the popularity of superstring theory, which is widely considered
    the most feasible candidate for a truly fundamental theory in physics. Yet, it is almost
    entirely motivated by considerations of elegance, having no direct experimental
    support in its favor (Greene 1999: 214).
    Now such beauty, elegance, and ingenuity make sense if the universe was designed
    by God. I would contend, however, that apart from some sort of design hypothesis,
    there is no reason to expect the fundamental laws to be elegant or beautiful. The
    metaphysical many-universes hypothesis, for example, cannot in any obvious way
    explain why our universe has such an elegant and beautiful fundamental structure,
    since under this hypothesis there would be many, many universes that contained
    observers in which the underlying mathematical structure would not be beautiful.
    Thus theism makes more sense of this aspect of the world than atheism, whether that
    atheism is of the single-universe or many-universe variety (see Collins 2009). Similar
    things could be said about the fact that the world is arranged in just the right way so
    that we can understand its underlying structure, something which could be called the
    ‘discoverability’ of the laws of physics, as for example discussed by Eugene Wigner
    (1960) and Mark Steiner (1998).

    Conclusion

    In this chapter, I have argued that the fine-tuning of the cosmos for CEL provides
    strong evidence for preferring theism over the NSU. I then argued that although one
    can partially explain the fine-tuning of the constants of physics by invoking some
    sort of many-universes generator, we have good reasons to believe that the many-
    universe generator itself would need to be well designed, and hence that hypothesizing
    some sort of many-universes generator only pushes the case for design up one level. I
    further argued that other features of the structure of the universe, such as the beauty
    and elegance of the laws of nature, also suggest design. When all the evidence is
    considered, I believe, one has a good cumulative case argument for a designer – that is,
    an argument in which many lines of evidence point to the same conclusion. Of course,
    one would need additional arguments, such as those offered by Richard Swinburne
    (2004: ch. 5), to conclude that the designer is the theistic God.

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    ROBIN COLLINS

    420

    See also David Hume (Chapter 15), Immanuel Kant (Chapter 16), Creation and
    divine action (Chapter 35), The cosmological argument (Chapter 37), Problems with
    theistic arguments (Chapter 45), Science and the improbability of God (Chapter 46),
    Religion and science (Chapter 71).

    References
    Barrow, J. and F. Tipler (1986) The Anthropic Cosmological Principle, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Carr, B. J. and M. J. Rees (1979) ‘The Anthropic Cosmological Principle and the structure of the physical

    world,’ Nature 278 (12 April): 605–12.
    Collins, R. (2003) ‘The evidence for fine-tuning,’ in N. Manson (ed.) God and Design, London: Routledge.
    —— (2005) ‘Hume, fine-tuning and the Who Designed God? objection,’ in J. Sennett and D. Groothius

    (eds) In Defense of Natural Theology: A Post-Humean Assessment, Downers Grove, IL: InterVarsity Press.
    —— (2009) ‘A theistic perspective on the Multiverse Hypothesis,’ in B. Carr (ed.) Universe or Multiverse?,

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Davies, P. (1974) The Physics of Time Asymmetry, Berkeley, CA: University of California Press.
    Denton, M. (1998) Nature’s Destiny: How the Laws of Biology Reveal Purpose in the Universe, New York:

    Free Press.
    Dyson, F. (1979) Disturbing the Universe, New York: Harper & Row.
    Greene, B. (1999) The Elegant Universe: Superstrings, Hidden Dimensions, and the Quest for the Ultimate

    Theory, New York: W. W. Norton.
    Hacking, I. (1975) The Emergence of Probability: A Philosophical Study of Early Ideas About Probability,

    Induction and Statistical Inference, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
    Leslie, J. (1988) ‘How to draw conclusions from a fine-tuned cosmos,’ in R. Russell, W. R. Stoeger, and

    G. V. Coyne (eds) Physics, Philosophy and Theology: A Common Quest for Understanding, Vatican City
    State: Vatican Observatory Press.

    Lewis, D. (1986) On the Plurality of Worlds, New York: Blackwell.
    Parsons, K. (1990) ‘Is there a case for Christian theism?’, in J. P. Moreland and K. Nielsen (eds) Does God

    Exist? The Great Debate, Nashville, TN: Thomas Nelson.
    Plantinga, A. (1993) Warrant and Proper Function, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
    Rees, M. (2000) Just Six Numbers: The Deep Forces that Shape the Universe, New York: Basic Books.
    Schlesinger, G. (1984) ‘Possible worlds and the mystery of existence,’ Ratio 26: 1–18.
    Smart, N. (1964) Doctrine and Argument in Indian Philosophy, London: Allen & Unwin.
    Sober, E. (2002) ‘Bayesianism – its scope and limits,’ in R. Swinburne (ed.) Bayes’s Theorem, Oxford:

    Oxford University Press.
    Steiner, M. (1998) The Applicability of Mathematics as a Philosophical Problem, Cambridge, MA: Harvard

    University Press.
    Swinburne, R. (2004) The Existence of God, 2nd edn, Oxford: Clarendon Press.
    Tegmark, M. (1998) ‘Is “the theory of everything” merely the ultimate ensemble theory?’, Annals of Physics

    270: 1–51. Preprint at http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9704009.
    Weinberg, S. (1992) Dreams of a Final Theory, New York: Vintage Books.
    Wigner, E. (1960) ‘The unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in the natural sciences,’ Communications

    on Pure and Applied Mathematics 13: 1–14. Available at http://www.dartmouth.edu/~matc/MathDrama/
    reading/Wigner.html.

    Further reading
    Holder, R. (2004) God, the Multiverse, and Everything: Modern Cosmology and the Argument from

    Design, Aldershot, and Burlington, VT: Ashgate. (Argues that the evidence of fine-tuning supports
    theism.)

    Leslie, J. (1989) Universes, London: Routledge. (Explores the question of multiple universes as an alter-
    native to a design explanation of fine-tuning.)

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    http://arxiv.org/abs/gr-qc/9704009

    http://www.dartmouth.edu/~matc/MathDrama/reading/Wigner.html

    http://www.dartmouth.edu/~matc/MathDrama/reading/Wigner.html

    THE TELEOLOGICAL ARGUMENT

    421

    —— (ed.) (1998) Modern Cosmology and Philosophy, Amherst, NY: Prometheus. (Articles exploring the
    implications of modern cosmology for philosophy and teleology.)

    Manson, N. (ed.) (2003) God and Design: The Teleological Argument and Modern Science, New York:
    Routledge. (Twenty-one authors vigorously debate the merits of divine teleology, from the realm of
    biology to cosmology.)

    Manson, N. and J. Richards (eds) (2005) Philosophical Issues in Intelligent Design, Special Issue of
    Philosophia Christi ns 7/2 (December). (Contains a debate about whether the fine-tuning can be
    considered improbable.)

    Robson, J. (ed.) (1987) Origin and Evolution of the Universe: Evidence for Design? Montreal: McGill Queen’s
    University Press. (Explores whether biology and cosmology provide evidence for design.)

    Susskind, L. (2005) The Cosmic Landscape: String Theory and the Illusion of Intelligent Design, New York:
    Little, Brown & Co. (A leading physicist presents the many-universes hypothesis based on superstring
    theory, claiming that it eliminates the need to appeal to a design explanation of the fine-tuning.)

    Routledge Companion to Philosophy of Religion, edited by Chad Meister, and Paul Copan, Taylor & Francis Group, 2012. ProQuest Ebook
    Central, http://ebookcentral.proquest.com/lib/tccd-ebooks/detail.action?docID=1114699.
    Created from tccd-ebooks on 2020-07-09 09:57:51.

    C
    op

    yr
    ig

    ht
    ©

    2
    01

    2.
    T

    ay
    lo

    r
    &

    F
    ra

    nc
    is

    G
    ro

    up
    . A

    ll
    rig

    ht
    s

    re
    se

    rv
    ed

    .

    7

    The Ontological Argument

    The Ontological Argument was first thought of by St Anselm almost a thousand
    years ago.1 The essence of the argument can be stated very briskly.

    1. God, by definition, is a perfect being.
    2. It is better to exist than not to exist.

    Therefore, God exists.

    In an argument, one may define terms however one wishes, and premise 1 just
    reports one aspect—indeed, I have argued, the central one—of the theistic
    definition of God. So if anything goes wrong with the argument, then it must be
    in premise 2. But premise 2 looks pretty obviously right as well. Consider the
    question: which of these would be better for you: that you be vaporized now with
    a ray gun and thus that you cease to exist or that you continue to exist?
    However small an amount of benefit or enjoyment you’re receiving from

    reading this, I doubt if you’ll really think you’d be better off if you didn’t exist.
    Of course, we can all imagine a situation where someone’s life was so bad that it
    would be better for them if they ceased to exist—maybe the Spartan boy I told
    you about in an earlier chapter was in such a situation. However, if the person in
    question was in all other ways well off, it would certainly be better for him or her
    if he or she existed rather than not; and God is obviously going to be maximally
    well off in all other respects, so it’s obviously going to be better for him (and
    indeed us) if he exists. The claim that it’s better to exist than not to exist seems
    then—minor and irrelevant quibbling aside—right.
    Both the premises of the Ontological Argument seem to be obviously true; taken

    together they seem to lead in an obviously deductively valid way to the conclusion
    that God exists, which was something not so obviously true. If God’s by definition
    perfect, then of course—given that it’s better to exist than not to exist—he’ll have
    to exist. It’s impossible for the premises to both be true and yet the conclusion false
    and it’s obvious that both the premises are true. So it seems as if we’ve got a
    deductively sound argument for the existence of God the soundness of which is
    more obvious than is the existence of God. The Ontological Argument then seems
    to satisfy our criteria for being a good argument. It seems to, but does it?

    ♦ ♦ ♦

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    It’s easier to spot that something has gone wrong with the Ontological Argument
    than it is to describe what it is that has gone wrong with it. One way of seeing that
    something has gone wrong with the Ontological Argument is to consider that if
    it worked, one could generate parallel arguments ad infinitum that proved the
    existence of any sort of entity one cared to mention. Allow me to introduce one
    such parallel argument.

    The Senior Common Room butler at my college is pretty good at keeping us
    all in order. For example, there was one occasion, early on in my membership of
    the Senior Common Room, when I was dining at High Table. The main course
    arrived—to be served silver-service style by the butler. I was one of the first to be
    served, and scooted one slice of whatever it was off the salver, then prepared to
    take a second. The butler leaned forward slightly and sotto voce advised me, ‘One
    is usually considered sufficient, sir.’ I was a bit miffed at this, but left the second
    portion on the salver, which proceeded in his hands down the table towards the
    end, where the Senior Tutor was sitting. As it arrived there, I noticed that there
    had been exactly the right number of portions on the salver to mean that the
    Senior Tutor—the last to be served—took the last one. Had I taken a second
    portion earlier on, then the Senior Tutor would have been left without any main
    course; the assembled eyes of the Senior Common Room would have then
    worked their way back along the table, unerringly seeking out where this prob-
    lem had originated. Ultimately, they would have fallen on me, merrily munching
    my way through two portions. Were it not for the timely intervention of the
    butler, my career at my college might have been cut rather short.

    So, as you can tell, my college’s butler is pretty good at keeping people out of
    scrapes. But even he isn’t the best possible butler; even he can’t quite be a Jeeves
    to my Wooster, which is—one might reasonably hypothesize—more of a sign of
    how much of a Wooster I am than how little a Jeeves he is. In any case, reflection
    on this incident prompts me to think that it would certainly be rather handy to
    have a butler at one’s side throughout one’s life, ready to assist one in making
    one’s way through the world with wise sotto voce advice. Let me define the term
    ‘Jeeves’ to mean the best possible butler for you. So, Jeeves will—by definition—
    always be on hand for you whenever you might need him.

    1. Jeeves I define as the best possible butler for you.
    2. If there is a better analysis of the Ontological Argument than this, it

    would be better for Jeeves to be right by your side now, handing you this
    better analysis.

    Therefore, Jeeves must be right by your side now, handing you a better
    analysis of the Ontological Argument than this one.

    This argument seems as good as the Ontological Argument for the existence of
    God. The first premise simply reports my definition of ‘Jeeves’, so there’s
    nothing to be argued with there. The second premise reports the fact that if there

    The Existence of God126

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    were such a thing as a better analysis of the Ontological Argument than this,
    then, as it would be better if you were reading this better analysis, so a better
    butler would be one who was by your side with such an analysis. That seems to
    follow pretty obviously. Yet from these two premises it follows that Jeeves must
    be right by your side with a better analysis than this. Look for him. Is he there?
    No. The only way to escape the conclusion that he must be there seems to be to
    claim that this is the best possible analysis that one might attempt of the
    Ontological Argument. I might be happy to rest content with this conclusion,
    but I doubt that you are.
    The objection that if the Ontological Argument worked, then my Jeeves

    argument and similar sorts of arguments would also work is sometimes called the
    ‘Overload Objection’ to the Ontological Argument; if the Ontological Argument
    worked, then we could overload the universe with all sorts of entities like Jeeves.

    ♦ ♦ ♦

    So, something’s gone wrong with the Ontological Argument. What exactly?
    First, premise one is rather ambiguous. Is this premise using the term ‘God’ to

    pick something out and then attributing a property, albeit an essential one, to it,
    just as you might say that this book here—waving it around—is by definition
    something that has pages? Well, if so, we could not know that the term ‘God’
    had secured reference without already knowing the conclusion of this argument,
    that there is a God, so premise 1 would not be one that could be known to be
    true with more certainty than we knew the conclusion, that there is a God. This
    would be sufficient to undercut any claim that the Ontological Argument—
    however deductively sound—is good. However, if premise 1 is not using the
    term ‘God’ to pick out something and then attribute a property to that thing,
    then it must mean something like ‘If there is a God, then he is by definition
    perfect’, but if that’s what premise 1 really means, then although it can be known
    to be true without first needing to know that there is a God, it cannot support
    the conclusion that God exists but only—at best—the conclusion that if there is
    a God, then he exists. This conclusion is a rather unexciting one. We all knew
    that anyway. So premise 1, despite my initial enthusiasm for it, is in fact deeply
    questionable.
    Despite this being a sufficient reason to reject the Ontological Argument, for

    the sake of completeness if nothing else we must look at the second premise. The
    second premise is also the one on which most philosophical criticism has
    focused. The second premise is ‘It is better to exist than not to exist.’ What can
    be said against this second premise?

    ♦ ♦ ♦

    One can beat around the bush for quite a long time here, but eventually one gets
    to the point that was first made by Kant: existence is not a predicate. Let me
    explain what Kant meant.

    The Ontological Argument 127

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    I talked earlier about this book and a couple of the properties that it had: one
    of these properties was that it was, I guessed, then being held by you. I’m
    guessing it’s got that property again now. Kant’s point would be that while it is
    indeed a bona fide property of this book that it is being held by you, it’s not a
    bona fide property of it that it exists; saying that existence isn’t a predicate is a
    way of saying that existence isn’t a property that objects have. So, the following
    sentences as spoken by me are true (I’m supposing): ‘This book is being held by
    you’ and ‘This book exists,’ but—according to Kant—there’s a crucial difference
    between these two sentences. The first really does predicate something of the
    book. It picks out the book and asserts of it that it has a property, the property of
    being held by you. The second sentence, despite its grammatical similarity with
    the first, does not—according to Kant—do this. It doesn’t pick out the book and
    assert of it that it has a property, the property of existence. What does it do then?
    Answering that question is a bit more tricky. To do so I have to augment what
    Kant said with something said by a later philosopher, Gottlob Frege, and it’s
    going to take a moment or two for me to set out all the ideas we need if we are to
    understand what Frege said.

    First then, I want to introduce a distinction between what I’m going to call
    concrete objects and what I’m going to call abstract objects. Examples of con-
    crete objects would be things like this book; the chair you’re currently sitting on;
    and your right hand. Examples of abstract objects would be things like the nature
    of education; the current government’s misconception of the nature of education;
    its consequent policies with respect to universities; and—to move away from my
    particular concerns—the number five. On what basis do we decide whether a
    given thing is a concrete or an abstract object; or indeed do we decide on any
    basis at all? (It may be that the distinction is a brute one—incapable of explica-
    tion in terms of anything else.) This question is not an easy one to answer, but
    fortunately for my present purposes we don’t need to answer it, assuming as
    I think it safe to assume that we all have a pretty good grasp on the distinction
    through the examples I’ve just given.

    Armed then with the distinction between concrete and abstract objects, let’s
    consider the concrete objects that are the chairs in the room in which you sit. Let
    me suppose for the sake of argument that there are three of them. It’s natural for
    you to group the chairs in the room together in your mind for the purposes of
    discussion into one set, the set of chairs in the room. The set of chairs in the
    room is an abstract object the members of which are concrete objects. The
    abstract object that is the set of chairs in the room has properties that its concrete
    members do not have. It has the property of having a quarter of the number of
    members as the abstract object that is the set of chair legs in the room has (I’m
    assuming). The individual concrete objects that are the chairs in the room could
    not be said to have a quarter of the number of members as the set of chair legs in
    the room; that wouldn’t make sense. The individual concrete objects that are the
    chairs in the room have properties that the abstract object that is the set of chairs

    The Existence of God128

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    in the room does not have; they each have upholstered seats (I’m assuming). The
    abstract object that is the set of chairs in the room could not be said to have an
    upholstered seat; that would not make sense either.
    Now, consider the following two sentences as they might be spoken by you:

    ‘The chairs in this room have upholstered seats’ and ‘The chairs in this room
    are three in number.’ If one wasn’t thinking too carefully, one might say that
    each of these sentences had the same subject—the chairs in the room in which
    you sit—and predicated different things of that subject, having upholstered seats
    and being three in number. But with Frege’s help we can now see that the real
    subject of these two sentences is actually different, despite their similar grammar.
    The first sentence takes the concrete objects that are the chairs in the room as its
    subject; the second takes the abstract object that is the set of chairs in the room as
    its subject. The first is saying that the chairs in the room have a certain property,
    the property of having upholstered seats; the second is saying that the set of
    chairs in this room has a certain property, the property of having three members.
    With this in hand, we now have the tools to understand Frege’s interpretation of
    existence.
    Consider the sentence as uttered by you, ‘The chairs in this room exist.’ What

    is the true subject of this sentence? Is it the concrete objects that are the chairs in
    the room? No. Is it the set of chairs in this room? Yes. Saying that the chairs in
    the room exist is saying that the set of chairs in the room does not have zero
    members. Saying ‘X exists’ is not then actually saying anything about X. It’s
    saying something of the abstract object that is the set of those things that’s picked
    out by the concept of X and it’s saying of it that it’s not the set with zero
    members. So, according to Kant and Frege, existence is not a property of con-
    crete objects; existence isn’t something that objects do, like breathing, only
    quieter. Rather, when one says that X exists one asserts something, not about X,
    but about the set of Xs and what one asserts is that the set of Xs is not the empty
    set, the empty set being the set with zero members. If there is a God, then the set
    of Gods is not the empty set, but the fact that the set of Gods is not then the
    empty set is not a fact about God; it isn’t a property of the concrete object that is
    God that the abstract object that is the set of Gods is not empty.
    Once we’ve shown with Kant and Frege’s help that existence is not a property

    of God even if he does exist, premise 2 of the Ontological Argument can be seen
    to collapse. If existence is not a property of God even if he does exist, then it
    cannot be a property that it is better for him if he has.
    How then to explain our intuition that one’s ceasing to exist would be bad?

    We have seen already that what would make one’s permanently ceasing to exist
    bad for one is that it would frustrate one’s flourishing and one’s desires. Never
    having existed would not have frustrated any flourishing or desires, so even
    though it is not good for one that one was brought into existence, death would
    be bad for one if it was permanently ceasing to exist, which is why—as we’ve
    seen—if there’s a God, he’ll ensure that our deaths are not our permanently

    The Ontological Argument 129

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    ceasing to exist. It’s not bad for the brother that I never had that he never existed;
    it would be bad for the sisters that I do have if they permanently ceased to exist.

    So, to sum up my conclusions with regard to the Ontological Argument: the
    first premise is true—on both interpretations of it—if and only if theism is true;
    it is false on the interpretation of it that would be necessary for the argument to
    be a deductively valid one for theism if theism is false. This is a sufficient reason
    for us to conclude that the Ontological Argument is not a good argument for
    theism. The second premise is false if existence is not a predicate, which it is not.
    This too is sufficient for us to conclude that the Ontological Argument is not a
    good argument for theism. The Ontological Argument fails in two ways then as a
    deductive argument and—starting as it does from pure categories a priori—it
    cannot be turned into an inductive argument. I therefore conclude that the
    Ontological Argument does not provide any reasons for believing that ‘There is a
    God’ is true.

    ♦ ♦ ♦

    This is the ‘classic’ version of the Ontological Argument and one so central to the
    tradition that other ‘versions’, in so far as they differ from it, run the risk of not
    counting as versions simply by virtue of their doing so. However, if we think of
    the essence of the Ontological Argument as simply its proceeding ‘from pure
    categories a priori’, then there are arguments that are recognizably different from
    the classic version and yet deserve to be considered versions of the Ontological
    Argument. I’ll close this chapter by discussing such arguments in terms of a
    rather generalized instance of them. It will be helpful, before I do this, to say a
    word or two about the notion of possible worlds as it is used in the presentation
    of arguments of this sort.

    I began the book by using the word ‘world’ to refer to the physical universe as
    a whole, so that I might describe the perplexity that I claimed we have all felt at
    some moment in our lives when contemplating the world as a whole; the world
    as a whole raises in some sense a question to which we think God might be the
    answer. ‘World’ in this sense means ‘universe’; in this sense of ‘world’, God
    himself could not then be a resident of the world; if he exists, he exists outside the
    world; he has to in order to explain it. The important point to note now is that
    the notion of worlds in play when we talk of possible worlds in this context is
    different. Possible worlds in this context are to be understood as ways that
    everything might be or might have been. Thus, at least prima facie, it seems
    logically possible both that there’s a God of the sort we’ve been discussing in the
    first half of this book and also logically possible that there’s not. Neither involves
    a contradiction in terms. If that’s right, then—using this new notion of world—
    we might say that there’s a possible world in which the physical universe (the
    world in my original sense) is as it is and there’s a God on top and there’s a
    possible world in which the physical universe is as it is and there’s no God on
    top. God’s a resident of the first world and not of the second. Theists think that

    The Existence of God130

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    the actual world is the first—the physical universe plus God (and perhaps various
    other supernatural beings)—and physicalists think that the actual world is the
    second—simply the physical universe as a whole.2

    Consider then this argument:

    1. It is possible that God exists, i.e. he does exist in some possible world.
    2. If God exists in some possible world, then he exists in every possible world.

    Therefore, God exists in every possible world, including the actual world,
    i.e. he actually exists.

    The premises of this argument seem right. After all, we’ve just said that it is
    possible that God exists, which is the same as saying that he does exist in some
    possible world. And, even if it wasn’t one of God’s essential properties, given that
    it’s obviously going to be better to exist necessarily rather than merely con-
    tingently, then, if there is a God, he’s going to have that form of existence, he’s
    going to exist in every possible world. So the premises seem right and the
    conclusion seems to follow deductively from them.
    Again, perhaps the best way to see that something has gone wrong with this

    argument is to see that if this argument worked, then a parallel argument would
    also work, one that we won’t want to say works. In this case, the reason we won’t
    want to say that the parallel argument works is not because its working would
    ‘overload’ the universe but because we can’t say that both arguments work as the
    second one working is incompatible with the first one working. This is the
    parallel argument:

    1. It is possible that God does not exist, i.e. he does not exist in some
    possible world.

    2. If God does not exist in some possible world, then he doesn’t exist in
    every possible world.

    Therefore, God doesn’t exist in every possible world, including the actual
    world, i.e. he doesn’t actually exist.

    Surely we have no less (non-question-begging) reason to believe premise 1 of
    the parallel argument than we do premise 1 of the original argument. The first
    five chapters have established that the concept of God is internally consistent; it
    describes an entity that it is logically possible exists and that it is logically possible
    does not exist. So something’s gone wrong with this version of the ontological
    argument. What?
    The answer lies in the ambiguity of the word ‘possible’ and the notion of

    possible worlds. The first five chapters have established that the concept of God
    is consistent, so God’s existence is logically possible, which amounts to there
    being no inconsistency in saying that God exists. This, we may say, is indeed
    equivalent to God’s existing in some logically possible world, so let’s take
    premise 1 of the original argument in this way: it is logically possible that God

    The Ontological Argument 131

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    exists, i.e. he does exist in some logically possible world. As such, we may agree
    with premise 1. But that God exists in some logically possible world (indeed in
    an infinite number of them) does not entail that he exists in all logically possible
    worlds, as suggested by premise 2. Rather, God’s non-existence is also logically
    possible; there is no inconsistency in saying that God does not exist. So God does
    not exist in some logically possible world, indeed he doesn’t exist in an infinite
    number of them. So we may reject premise 2 and thus the argument. If
    we take the word ‘possible’ to mean metaphysically possible, then we must accept
    the second premise. If God does exist in some metaphysically possible world,
    then he exists in every metaphysically possible world because if there is a God,
    he’s that on which everything else metaphysically depends. But then of course we
    have no (non-question-begging) reason to accept the first premise, that it’s
    metaphysically possible that God exists. Whether or not we think that this is true
    depends on whether or not we believe there’s a God. So this version of the
    Ontological Argument also fails as a good argument.

    All versions of the Ontological Argument then fail to respect the categorical
    difference between manœuvring within a concept and discovering whether that
    concept, however understood, does or does not have an instantiation.3 If we’re
    going to find evidence of God’s existence—a reason to believe that there’s a
    God—we’ll have to consider more than the mere concept of God. Where shall
    we look? The only place we can: the world that he’s supposed to have created.
    We must see if he’s left any evidence of his existence there. It has seemed to many
    that it’s obvious that he has. Let us turn then to the Argument to Design.

    The Existence of God132

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    2
    00
    5.
    C
    la
    re
    nd
    on
    P
    re
    ss
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re

    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or

    ap
    pl
    ic
    ab
    le
    c
    op
    yr
    ig
    ht
    l
    aw
    .

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/17/2017 4:18 PM via TARRANT COUNTY
    COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 186624 ; Mawson, T. J..; Belief in God : An Introduction to the Philosophy of Religion
    Account: tarrant

    David Hume’s Design Argument

    • Cleanthes is the advocate for the design
    argument: “The order and arrangement of
    nature, the intricate adjustment of things to
    their purposes, the plain use and intended
    purpose of every part and organ of a plant or
    animal… all these announce in the clearest
    language an intelligent cause or author” (part
    4).

    • Like effects prove like causes – the basis for
    empirical arguments.

    – (Similar effects have similar causes.)

    – If there are two different effects that are similar
    then we can infer that the causes are also similar.

    – Water quenches my thirst and gatorade quenches
    my thirst; therefore drinking gatorade seems to be
    a similar cause as drinking water.

    1. A house has an architect.

    1. The universe has a designer.

    – Cleanthes claims that the universe and a house
    have similar effects, therefore they have similar
    causes.

    Objections to Design Argument

    • Philo claims that Cleanthes argument has the
    following negative consequences:

    1. In our experiences with the universe we have
    not experienced infinity; hence the cause of
    the universe cannot be infinite.

    2. Nature contains many imperfections such as
    illnesses, natural disasters, etc. So we cannot
    attribute perfection to the cause of the
    universe.

    • It is possible that there could be more than
    one designer; that is, the existence of a well-
    designed universe is consistent with multiple
    designers.

    • Let us concede that the universe is designed,
    the following three scenarios are all just as
    plausible:

    1. This world was only the first rough attempt of
    some infant god, who afterwards abandoned it,
    ashamed of his poor performance.

    2. This universe is the work of some dependent,
    inferior god, whose superiors hold it up for
    ridicule.

    3. This universe was produced by some god in his
    old age and near-senility, and ever since his
    death the world has continued without further
    guidance, activated by the first shove he gave to
    it and the active force that he built into it.

    The Argument from a First Cause

    • This argument presents us with a divine being
    of classical theism.

    • God’s attributes include:

    – All-powerful

    – All-knowing

    – All-loving

    – Eternal

    – Infinite

    – Necessarily exists (which implies that it is
    impossible for God to not exist) – if God
    necessarily exists, then this is the explanation for
    God’s existence.

    • The argument stated:

    1. Either the universe has always existed for an
    infinite amount of time without cause or
    there is an ultimate cause for the universe.

    2. It is incoherent to suggest that the universe
    could exist uncaused.

    3. Therefore there must be a necessary ultimate
    cause for the universe.

    • To claim that the universe could exist without
    a cause is absurd because we are suggesting
    that there is not a reason for the existence of
    the universe.

    – The universe is uncaused.

    • Objections to the argument from a first cause:

    – If God necessarily exists, then to conceive of God’s
    non-existence is incoherent; take the following
    two statements

    1. God does not exist.

    2. 2 + 2 = 5

    – (1) is coherent whereas (2) is incoherent: if God
    necessarily exists, then (1) should not be possible.

    • Other objections
    1. Perhaps matter itself is necessary and needs no

    explanation for its existence.

    2. An eternal universe needs no explanation for its
    existence, because cause implies a previous
    time. If the universe is eternal there was no
    previous time to the existence of the universe.

    The Ontological Argument

    1. God, by definition is a perfect being.

    2. It is better to exist than not to exist.

    3. Therefore, God exists.

    • Both premises (1) and (2) seem correct.

    • First objection: Overload Objection

    1. Sally, by definition is a perfect unicorn.

    2. It is better to exist than not to exist.

    3. Therefore, Sally exists.

    • The Overload Objection suggests that our
    argument for Sally the Unicorn’s existence
    works if the ontological argument works.

    • Hence, if the ontological argument is correct
    then the universe is overloaded with entities
    like Sally

    – The biggest problem with the Overload Objection
    is that there may not be any agreement on the
    definition of a perfect unicorn

    – Whereas there is a general consensus about the
    definition for a perfect being.

    • Second objection: premise (1) is ambiguous:

    – Does ‘God’ pick out an actual being or is ‘God’
    simply referring to the concept of ‘God’?

    • Third objection: existence is not a predicate

    – Existence is not a property that objects have

    – We distinguish between concrete objects and
    abstract objects.

    – Concrete objects: your right hand; the chair you
    are sitting on, etc.

    – Abstract objects: the number five; the color red,
    etc.

    – Is God a concrete object or abstract object?

    – Asserting that something exists implies that we
    are discussing an abstract object. (The concept of
    God.)

    – Even if God does exist, existence cannot be a
    property.

    • Objection 4: the existence of God is not
    necessary.

    – It is logically possible that God exists.

    – It is logically possible that God does not exist.

    Contemporary Virtue Ethics

    By Karen Stohr

    Types of Virtue Ethics

    • Agent-based: a right-action is defined in
    terms of a virtuous agent. This is a fully agent-
    centered ethical theory.

    • Agent-prior: agent-evaluations are not the
    most fundamental concept, but derive
    evaluations by evaluating agents.

    • Agent-focused: emphasizes character traits
    over rules and principles

    Aristotle’s Influence

    • Aristotle’s virtue ethics are perhaps agent-
    prior.

    • For Aristotle virtue requires particular actions
    and particular emotional responses.

    – Emotions should allows the virtuous person to
    correctly view the world and understand it.

    • The doctrine of the mean: a virtuous action is
    the mean between excess and deficienty.

    • Practical wisdom is necessary to acquire the
    virtues and the virtues are necessary to
    acquire practical wisdom.

    • In order to live well humans must fulfill their
    natural purpose.

    – Fulfilling one’s purpose means that one is acting in
    accordance with one’s design.

    Virtue & Flourishing

    • The question is whether one who acts
    virtuously will flourish? Or can one flourish
    despite not acting virtuously?

    – According to Aristotle the virtuous individual will
    live well and flourish.

    • Some theories of virtue identify virtue with
    empathy towards other persons.

    – There is not a connection between virtue and
    living well.

    Some General Issues

    • Virtue ethics do not supply rules or
    procedures for ethical deliberation.

    • Virtue ethics suggests that some moral
    dilemmas might be irresolvable.

    – Moral luck might be a fundamental feature of
    morality.

    Three Contemporary Trends

    1. Separating virtuous individuals from living
    well; that is, someone can be virtuous and
    not flourish.

    2. The prevalence of virtue ethics in medical
    ethics, environmental ethics, and business
    ethics.

    3. The development of a conception of
    character and how that relates to virtue.

    Contemporary Virtue Ethics

    By Karen Stohr

    Types of Virtue Ethics

    • Agent-based: a right-action is defined in
    terms of a virtuous agent. This is a fully agent-
    centered ethical theory.

    • Agent-prior: agent-evaluations are not the
    most fundamental concept, but derive
    evaluations by evaluating agents.

    • Agent-focused: emphasizes character traits
    over rules and principles

    Aristotle’s Influence

    • Aristotle’s virtue ethics are perhaps agent-
    prior.

    • For Aristotle virtue requires particular actions
    and particular emotional responses.

    – Emotions should allows the virtuous person to
    correctly view the world and understand it.

    • The doctrine of the mean: a virtuous action is
    the mean between excess and deficienty.

    • Practical wisdom is necessary to acquire the
    virtues and the virtues are necessary to
    acquire practical wisdom.

    • In order to live well humans must fulfill their
    natural purpose.

    – Fulfilling one’s purpose means that one is acting in
    accordance with one’s design.

    Virtue & Flourishing

    • The question is whether one who acts
    virtuously will flourish? Or can one flourish
    despite not acting virtuously?

    – According to Aristotle the virtuous individual will
    live well and flourish.

    • Some theories of virtue identify virtue with
    empathy towards other persons.

    – There is not a connection between virtue and
    living well.

    Some General Issues

    • Virtue ethics do not supply rules or
    procedures for ethical deliberation.

    • Virtue ethics suggests that some moral
    dilemmas might be irresolvable.

    – Moral luck might be a fundamental feature of
    morality.

    Three Contemporary Trends

    1. Separating virtuous individuals from living
    well; that is, someone can be virtuous and
    not flourish.

    2. The prevalence of virtue ethics in medical
    ethics, environmental ethics, and business
    ethics.

    3. The development of a conception of
    character and how that relates to virtue.

    Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion

    David Hume

    Copyright ©

    2

    0

    1

    0–

    20

    1

    5

    All rights reserved. Jonathan Bennett

    [Brackets] enclose editorial explanations. Small ·dots· enclose material that has been added, but can be read as
    though it were part of the original text. Occasional •bullets, and also indenting of passages that are not quotations,
    are meant as aids to grasping the structure of a sentence or a thought. Every four-point ellipsis . . . . indicates the
    omission of a brief passage that seems to present more difficulty than it is worth. Longer omissions are reported
    with square brackets in normal-sized type.

    First launched: July 200

    4

    Last amended: November 200

    7

    Contents

  • Letter from Pamphilus to Hermippus
  • 1

  • Part 1
  • 2

  • Part 2
  • 9

    Part

    3

    1

    6

  • Part 4
  • 20

  • Part 5
  • 24

  • Part 6
  • 27

  • Part 7
  • 30

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part

    8

    34

  • Part 9
  • 38

    Part

    10

    40

    Part

    11

    47

    Part

    12

    54

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Pamphilus to Hermippus

    Letter from Pamphilus to Hermippus

    It has been remarked that though the ancient philosophers
    mostly taught through dialogues, the dialogue form hasn’t
    been much used in recent times, and has seldom succeeded
    when people have tried it. ·There is a good reason for this·.
    Philosophical enquirers these days are expected to produce
    precise and orderly arguments; and someone aiming at those
    will naturally proceed with a methodical exposition in which
    he can, right at the outset, explain the point he wants to
    establish, and then proceed without interruption to present
    his proofs of it. It hardly seems natural to present a system
    in conversation. And ·there is also another disadvantage
    of the dialogue form·. By departing from the direct style
    of composition the dialogue-writer hopes to give a freer air
    to his performance, and to avoid the appearance of Author
    and Reader; but he risks running into something worse,
    conveying the image of Teacher and Pupil. And if he avoids
    that by conducting the dispute in the natural spirit of good
    company, throwing in a variety of arguments, and preserving
    a proper balance among the speakers, he often spends so
    much time setting things up, and moving from one line of
    thought to another, that the reader will hardly think that the
    order, brevity, and precision which have been lost are made
    up for by all the graces of dialogue.

    There are some subjects, however, for which dialogue-
    writing is especially suitable, and preferable to the direct
    and simple method of composition. ·I shall describe two of
    them; apart from their suitability for the dialogue form they
    are utterly unalike, though it will turn out that one big topic
    includes both·.

    Any point of doctrine that is •so obvious that it can hardly
    be questioned, but at the same time •so important that it

    deserves to be taught repeatedly, seems to require some
    such method of handling it. In a dialogue, the novelty of the
    manner of presentation may make up for •the triteness of the
    subject; and the liveliness of the conversation may •reinforce
    the teaching. Also, the variety of different angles from which
    the characters in the dialogue approach the subject may
    appear neither tedious nor redundant.

    On the other hand, any question of philosophy that is
    so obscure and uncertain that human reason can’t reach a
    secure conclusion about it seems to lead us naturally into
    the style of dialogue and conversation. Reasonable men may
    be allowed to differ on a topic regarding which no-one can
    reasonably be confident. And opposing views, even without
    any decision as to which is right, provide an agreeable way
    of passing the time; and if the subject is challenging and
    interesting, the dialogue puts us (in a way) into the company
    of the characters in it. Thus a dialogue can unite the two
    greatest and purest pleasures of human life, study and the
    company of others.

    Fortunately, all those features are to be found in the
    subject of NATURAL RELIGION. What truth is so obvious, so
    certain, as that there exists a God? People in the most igno-
    rant ages have believed this, and the most refined geniuses
    have worked to produce new proofs and arguments for it.
    And what truth is so important as this? It is the ground of
    all our hopes, the surest foundation of morality, the firmest
    support of society, and the only principle that ought never
    to be a moment absent from our thoughts and meditations.
    But when we dig into this obvious and important truth, we
    run into obscure questions about the nature of that divine
    being, his attributes, his decrees, his plan of providence.

    1

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 1

    Men have always disagreed about these matters, and human
    reason hasn’t definitely settled them. But these topics are
    so important that we can’t restrain our restless enquiry
    into them, even though our most accurate researches have
    yielded nothing but doubt, uncertainty, and contradiction.

    I recently had a chance to observe this—·that is, the
    suitability of natural religion as a theme for dialogue·—when
    I was spending part of the summer season with Cleanthes,
    as I usually do, and was present at the conversations he
    had with Philo and Demea—the ones I recently sketched to
    you. My sketch made you so curious to know more (you
    said) that I can’t forbear to give you a more detailed report

    on their reasonings, and to display the various systems that
    they defended relating to this delicate subject of natural
    religion. The characters of the three men are remarkably
    different, and this raised your expectations even higher. You
    contrasted the careful philosophical methods of Cleanthes
    with the casual scepticism of Philo, and contrasted each of
    those with the rigid inflexible orthodoxy of Demea. Being
    young, I listened but didn’t speak; and my intense youthful
    interest in the whole conversation imprinted on my memory
    the whole chain and connection of their arguments. I hope
    and think that my account of the conversation won’t omit or
    muddle any considerable part of it.

    Part 1

    After I joined the group whom I found sitting in Cleanthes’
    library, Demea paid Cleanthes some compliments on the
    great care he took of my education, and on his unwearied
    perseverance and constancy in all his friendships. Pam-
    philus’s father, he said, was your intimate friend; the son is
    your pupil, and we might think him to be your adopted son
    if we judged by the trouble you take in bringing to him every
    useful branch of literature and science. I am sure that you
    are as prudent as you are hard-working; so I shall tell you a
    maxim that I have followed with regard to my own children,
    wanting to know how far it agrees with your upbringing
    of Pamphilus. The method I follow in the education of my
    children is based on the saying of an ancient: Students of
    philosophy ought first to learn logic, then ethics, next physics,
    last of all the nature of the gods. Because this science of

    natural theology is the most profound and abstruse of any,
    he held, students of it need mature judgment, and it can’t
    safely be entrusted to a mind that isn’t already enriched
    with all the other sciences. [In this work ‘science’ means something

    like ‘systematic, disciplined, theoretical treatment’. It covers more than

    ‘science’ does today.]
    Do you leave it as late as that, Philo asked, to teach your

    children the principles of religion? Isn’t there a risk that
    they will neglect or even outright reject those religious views
    of which they have heard so little during the whole of their
    education?

    Demea replied: I postpone the study of natural theology
    as a science that is open to human reasoning and contro-
    versy, but only as a science. My chief concern with my
    children is to bring piety into their minds while they are

    2

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 1

    young. By continual teaching (and also by example, I hope), I
    imprint deeply on their young minds a habitual reverence for
    all the principles of religion. While they pass through every
    other branch of knowledge, I comment on the uncertainty
    of each branch, on the eternal controversies of men, on the
    obscurity of all philosophy, and on the strange, ridiculous
    conclusions that some of the greatest geniuses have derived
    from the principles of mere human reason. Having thus
    tamed their mind to a proper submission and distrust of
    their own abilities, I no longer hesitate to open to them the
    greatest mysteries of religion; and I see no risk that the
    presumptuous arrogance of philosophy will lead them to
    reject the most established doctrines and opinions.

    Your precaution of bringing piety into your children’s
    minds early on, said Philo, is certainly very reasonable; it
    is indeed needed in this profane and irreligious age. But
    what I admire most in your plan of education is your way
    of getting advantage from the very principles of philosophy
    and learning which, by inspiring pride and self-sufficiency,
    have often throughout the centuries been found to be so
    destructive to the principles of religion. ·They are not so with
    everyone, admittedly·. Common folk with no experience of
    science and profound enquiry, when they see how learned
    people are endlessly disputing, often have a thorough con-
    tempt for philosophy; and that makes them hold even more
    firmly to the great points of theology that they have been
    taught. People who enter a little way into study and enquiry
    •think they find evidence to support new and extraordinary
    doctrines; •come to think that nothing is too difficult for
    human reason; and presumptuously •break through all
    fences and •profane the holiest places in the temple. Our
    best protection ·against such arrogance in religious matters·
    is ignorance; but after we have abandoned that we still
    have—as I hope Cleanthes will agree—one way remaining to

    us to prevent this profane liberty ·of laying down the law in
    religious matters·. What we should do is to adopt improved
    and cultivated versions of Demea’s principles ·concerning our
    proneness to error and confusion·. Let us become thoroughly
    aware of the weakness, blindness, and narrowness of human
    reason, paying proper attention to its uncertainty and its
    endless contradictions, even in ordinary everyday subjects;
    let the errors and deceits of our senses be kept in mind;
    the insuperable difficulties surrounding the basic principles
    of every intellectual system; the contradictions involved in
    the very ideas of matter, cause and effect, extension, space,
    time, motion—in short, all kinds of ideas of quantity of all
    kinds, though quantity is the topic of ·mathematics·, the
    only science that has any claim to certainty or self-evidence.
    When these topics are displayed in their full light, as they
    are by some philosophers and almost all religious writers,
    who can remain confident enough of his frail reason to give
    heed to anything it tells him on topics that are so sublime,
    so abstruse, and so remote from common life and experience
    ·as the existence and nature of God·? When ·we realize
    that· really familiar things—like the holding-together of the
    parts of a stone, or even the structure of it that makes it
    an extended thing—are so inexplicable and involve such
    contradictions, how confidently can we reach conclusions
    about the origin of worlds, or trace their history from eternity
    to eternity?

    As Philo spoke, I noticed that both Demea and Cleanthes
    were smiling. Demea’s smile seemed to express total satisfac-
    tion with what Philo was saying; but, in Cleanthes’ features
    I discerned an air of knowing amusement, as though he saw
    in Philo’s reasonings some kind of teasing or trap-setting.

    You propose then, Philo, said Cleanthes, to erect reli-
    gious faith on ·a basis of· philosophical scepticism; and you
    think that if certainty is expelled from every other subject of

    3

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 1

    enquiry it will retreat into these theological doctrines, where
    it will be stronger and more authoritative than ever. Whether
    your scepticism is as absolute and sincere as you claim is
    something we shall learn later on, when we end this little
    meeting: we’ll see then whether you leave the room through
    the door or the window; and whether you really doubt that
    your body has gravity and can be injured by its fall—which is
    what people in general think on the basis of their fallacious
    senses and more fallacious experience. And I think that this
    consideration ·of the test of scepticism in everyday life· can
    fairly serve to make us less angry with this whimsical sect of
    the sceptics. If they are wholly sincere, they won’t trouble
    the world for much longer with their doubts, niggles, and
    disputes; and if they are only joking, they may perhaps be
    bad comedians but they can never be very dangerous to the
    state, to philosophy, or to religion.

    In reality, Philo, he went on, it seems certain that even if
    a man entirely renounces all beliefs and opinions, doing this
    in a rush of blood to the head after intense thought about
    the contradictions and imperfections of human reason, he
    can’t persevere in this total scepticism, or make it show in
    his conduct for more than a short time. External objects will
    press in on him; his passions will call to him; his philosophi-
    cal gloom will dissipate; and he won’t be able to preserve his
    poor appearance of scepticism—however hard he works on
    himself to do so. And what reason has he to work on himself
    in that way? He’ll never be able to answer that question
    satisfactorily, consistently with his sceptical principles. So
    that on the whole nothing could be more ridiculous than the
    principles of the ancient Pyrrhonians [= extreme sceptics], if they
    really did try—as it has been claimed that they did—to apply
    to the whole of life the same scepticism that they learned
    from class-room lectures, which is where they ought to have
    confined it.

    From this angle the Stoics seem to be very like their
    perpetual antagonists the Pyrrhonians. Each sect seems
    to be based on this erroneous maxim: What a man can
    do sometimes and in some moods he can do always and in
    every mood. When Stoical reflections raise the mind into a
    frenzy of virtue, and impress it with a sense of some kind of
    honour or public good, extreme bodily pain and sufferings
    won’t prevail over such a high sense of duty; and it may even
    be possible for someone to smile and rejoice in the middle
    of being tortured. If this sometimes actually happens, how
    much more can a philosopher in his classroom or study work
    himself up to such a frenzy, and imagine himself bearing
    the acutest pain he can conceive! But how is he to maintain
    the frenzy itself? His frame of mind relaxes, and he cannot
    brace it up again just by wanting to do so; other activities
    lead him astray; misfortunes attack him unawares; and the
    philosopher gradually sinks into being an ordinary person.

    I accept your comparison between the Stoics and Sceptics,
    replied Philo. Still, although the Stoic mind can’t maintain
    the highest flights of philosophy, even when it sinks lower
    it still retains something of its former disposition; and the
    effects of the Stoic’s reasoning will appear in his conduct
    in everyday life, flavouring all of his actions. The ancient
    schools of philosophy, particularly that of Zeno, produced
    examples of virtue and steadfastness which seem astonishing
    to us today:

    Vain Wisdom all and false Philosophy.
    Yet with a pleasing sorcery could charm
    Pain, for a while, or anguish; and excite
    Fallacious Hope, or arm the obdurate breast
    With stubborn Patience, as with triple steel.

    (Milton, Paradise Lost ii)

    4

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 1

    Similarly, if a man has accustomed himself to sceptical
    thoughts about the uncertainty and narrowness of reason,
    he won’t entirely forget them when he turns his thought
    onto other subjects. In all his philosophical principles and
    reasoning—though I daren’t say in his everyday conduct!—he
    will be found to be different from those who never formed
    any opinions on this topic and from those who have thought
    about it and taken a more favourable view of human reason.

    [In this paragraph, Philo uses ‘philosophy’ to mean ‘philosophy or

    science’, apparently with his eye mainly on science. For ease of reading,

    ‘philosophy’ and its cognates are replaced by ‘science’ and its cognates

    throughout the paragraph.] However far anyone pushes his
    speculative principles of scepticism, he must—I admit—act
    and live and talk like other men; but the only reason he needs
    to give for this conduct is that it is absolutely necessary
    for him behave thus. If he goes further in this direction
    than he needs to for sheer survival, and engages in scientific
    enquiries into various non-human and human subjects, ·this
    doesn’t show that he is insincere in his scepticism; because
    his reason for this scientific theorizing is just that· he is
    drawn to it by a certain pleasure and satisfaction that he
    finds in employing himself in that way. He’s also aware •that
    everyone, even in common life, is forced to conduct himself
    in greater or lesser degree like a scientist: •that from our
    earliest infancy we make continual advances in forming more
    general principles of conduct and reasoning; •that as our
    experience widens and our reason strengthens, we make our
    principles more general and comprehensive; and •that what
    we call ‘science’ is nothing but a more regular and methodical
    process of the same kind. To engage in scientific enquiry
    into such subjects is essentially the same as reasoning about
    common life; and we may only expect greater stability, if not
    greater truth, from our science, on account of its more exact
    and careful method of proceeding.

    But when we look beyond human affairs and the prop-
    erties of the material things around us—when we carry our
    speculations into

    •the two eternities, before and after the present state
    of things,

    •the creation and formation of the universe,
    •the existence and properties of spirits,
    •the powers and operations of one universal spirit ex-
    isting without beginning and without end, omnipotent,
    omniscient, unchanging, infinite, and incomprehen-
    sible

    —when we consider any of this, we would have to be very
    unsceptical not to worry that we have here gone quite
    beyond the reach of our faculties! So long as we confine
    our theorizing to trade, or morals, or politics, or criticism, we
    make continual appeals to common sense and experience;
    these appeals strengthen our philosophical and scientific
    conclusions, and at least partly remove the suspicion that
    we rightly have regarding any reasoning that is very subtle
    and delicate. But in theological reasonings we don’t have
    this advantage ·of being able to appeal to common experience
    just when we have most need of it·, while we are thinking
    about objects which—we must be aware—are too large for
    our grasp, and need more than any others to be presented
    to our minds in a way that will make them familiar to us. We
    are like foreigners in a strange country, to whom everything
    must seem suspicious, and who are in danger every moment
    of breaking the laws and customs of the people with whom
    they live and talk. We don’t know how far we ought to
    trust our ordinary vulgar methods of reasoning in such a
    ·theological· subject, because even in everyday life—in the
    area that is specially suited to them—we can’t explain or
    justify them, and are entirely guided by a kind of instinct or
    necessity in employing them.

    5

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 1

    All sceptics claim that if reason is considered abstractly,
    it provides invincible arguments against itself, and that
    we could never retain any opinion or confidence on any
    subject if it were not that the sceptical reasonings ·in which
    reason discredits itself· are so refined and subtle that they
    can’t outweigh the more solid and more natural arguments
    derived from the senses and experience. But it is obvious
    that when our arguments lose this advantage ·of solidity and
    naturalness·, and run wide of everyday life, the most refined
    scepticism comes to be on an equal footing with them and
    can oppose and counterbalance them. Neither side has more
    weight than the other. The mind must remain suspended
    between them; and that suspense or balance is the triumph
    of scepticism.

    But I observe with regard to you, Philo, and to all theoret-
    ical sceptics, says Cleanthes, that your doctrine is at odds
    with your behaviour—just as much in the most abstruse
    points of theory as in the conduct of everyday life. Wherever
    evidence is found, you adhere to it, despite your supposed
    scepticism; and I can observe, too, that some of your fellow-
    sceptics are as decisive as those who claim higher levels of
    certainty and assurance. Really, wouldn’t it be ridiculous
    for someone to say that he rejected Newton’s explanation
    of the wonderful phenomenon of the rainbow, because that
    explanation gives a minute anatomy of the rays of light—‘a
    subject’ (says this absurd sceptic) ‘too refined for human
    comprehension’? And what would you say to someone
    who, finding no fault with the arguments of Copernicus and
    Galileo for the motion of the earth, nevertheless withheld
    his assent on the general ground that these subjects are too
    magnificent and remote to be explained by the narrow and
    deceitful reason of mankind?

    There is indeed a kind of •crude and ignorant scepticism,
    as you rightly remarked, that gives common people a general

    prejudice against things they can’t easily understand, and
    makes them reject every principle that requires elaborate
    reasoning to prove and establish it. This sort of scepticism
    is fatal to knowledge, not to religion; for we find that many
    of those who most strenuously profess it give their assent
    not only to the great truths of theism and natural theology,
    but even to the most absurd doctrines that traditional su-
    perstition has recommended to them. They firmly believe in
    witches, though they refuse to believe or attend to the most
    simple proposition in Euclid’s geometry. But the •refined
    and philosophical sceptics fall into an inconsistency of an
    opposite kind. They push their researches into the most
    abstruse corners of science, and at every step they accept
    propositions in proportion to the evidence for them that
    they meet with. They are even obliged to admit that the
    most abstruse and remote objects are the ones that are best
    explained by science. •Light is in reality anatomized. •The
    true system of the heavenly bodies is discovered. But •the
    nourishment of bodies by food is still a mystery that we
    can’t explain. The •holding together of the parts of matter is
    still incomprehensible. ·Light is abstruse, and the heavenly
    bodies are remote; but nourishment and the firmness of
    pebbles are neither. So the refined sceptics cannot draw a
    general line in those terms·. These sceptics, therefore, are
    obliged in every enquiry to consider each particular bit of
    evidence separately, and to proportion their assent to the
    precise strength of the evidence they find. This is what
    they actually do in all natural, mathematical, moral, and
    political science. And why not the same, I ask, in theological
    and religious studies? Why should we confine to them
    the practice of rejecting conclusions, without looking into
    the evidence that has been offered, on the general ground
    that human reason is insufficient? Isn’t this discriminatory
    attitude a plain proof of prejudice and passion?

    6

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 1

    Our senses, you say, are fallacious; our understanding
    is erroneous; our ideas—even of the most familiar objects:
    extension, duration, motion—are full of absurdities and
    contradictions. You defy me to solve the difficulties or
    reconcile the inconsistencies that you find in them. I haven’t
    the skill for so great an undertaking; I haven’t leisure for
    it; I see that there’s no need for it. Your own conduct, in
    every circumstance, refutes your principles, and shows the
    firmest reliance on all the received maxims of science, morals,
    prudence, and behaviour.

    I shall never accept the celebrated Arnauld’s extravagant
    statement that the sceptics are not a sect of philosophers—
    only a sect of liars! But I will say—no offence meant—that
    they are a sect of comedians or teasers. For my part,
    though, whenever I find myself wanting fun and amusement,
    I shall certainly choose for my entertainment something less
    puzzling and abstruse ·than sceptical philosophy·. A comedy,
    a novel, or at most a history, seems a more natural recreation
    than such metaphysical subtleties and abstractions.

    It is no use for the sceptic to distinguish science from com-
    mon life, or one science from another. The arguments that he
    uses, if they are sound, hold good in each of these areas and
    have just as much force in one as in another. Or if there is
    any difference among them, the advantage lies entirely on the
    side of theology and natural religion—·the advantage, that is,
    of having the strength to resist scepticism·. Many principles
    of mechanics are based on very abstruse reasoning, yet
    nobody with any degree of scientific competence claims to be
    in the least doubt concerning to them—nor indeed does any
    theoretical sceptic. The Copernican system contains ·the
    thesis that the sun doesn’t go around the earth, which is·
    the most surprising paradox, and the one most contrary
    to our natural conceptions, to appearances, and to our
    very senses; yet even monks and inquisitors have had to

    withdraw their opposition to it. Then we have the religious
    hypothesis, which is based on the simplest and most obvious
    arguments, and is easily accepted by the mind of man unless
    it is blocked by artificial obstacles. Will Philo, a thoughtful
    and knowledgeable man, cast doubt on it because of the
    supposed unreliability of the human faculties in general, with
    no special reference to the religious hypothesis in particular?

    And here we may observe (he went on, turning towards
    Demea) a rather curious fact in the history of the sciences.
    After philosophy was joined to the religion of the people,
    when Christianity was first established, religious teachers
    commonly denounced reason, the senses, and every principle
    derived merely from human research and enquiry. The
    Fathers of the Church took up all the themes of the ancient
    Academics [here = ‘sceptics’], which then spread from them
    down the years into every school and pulpit in Christendom.
    The Reformers embraced the same principles of reasoning, or
    rather denunciation, and all flowery praise of the excellency
    of •faith was sure to be spiced with some cutting jibes against
    natural •reason. A celebrated Roman Catholic bishop, too, a
    man of the most extensive learning who wrote a demonstra-
    tion of Christianity, has also written a book containing all the
    fault-finding of the boldest and most determined Pyrrhon-
    ism. ·It took centuries for this contempt for reason to die
    down·. Locke seems to have been the first Christian to risk
    saying openly •that faith is nothing but a species of reason,
    •that religion is only a branch of philosophy, and •that the
    arguments that have always been used in discovering all
    the principles of theology, natural and revealed, are just
    like those that have been used to establish truths in morals,
    politics, or physics. The miserable use that Bayle and other
    free-thinkers made of the philosophical scepticism of the
    Church Fathers and first reformers—·namely, their use of it
    as a weapon against religion·—had the effect of widening the

    7

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 1

    acceptance of Locke’s sensible opinion; and now all those
    who claim to be thinkers assert, in a way, that ‘atheist’ and
    ‘sceptic’ are almost synonymous. And just as it is certain
    that no man would sincerely declare himself a sceptic, I
    venture to hope that there are as few who seriously maintain
    atheism.

    Don’t you remember, said Philo, the excellent saying of
    Lord Bacon on this topic? That a little philosophy, replied
    Cleanthes, makes a man an atheist: a great deal converts
    him to religion. That’s a very sensible remark too, said
    Philo. But what I have in mind is another passage where,
    having mentioned David’s ‘fool who said in his heart that
    there is no God’, this great philosopher observes that the
    atheists nowadays are double fools; for they aren’t contented
    to say in their hearts that there is no God but also utter that
    impiety with their lips, which makes them guilty of multiplied
    indiscretion and imprudence. Such people, however serious
    and sincere they are, cannot be much of a threat, I think.

    But even at the risk of your counting me as one of this
    class of fools, I can’t forbear to say something that occurs
    to me, arising out of the history of religious and irreligious
    scepticism with which you have entertained us. It seems
    to me that there are strong symptoms of priestcraft in that
    whole course of events. During ignorant ages, such as those
    following the abolition of the ancient schools, the priests
    saw that atheism, deism [= a thin belief in a higher power, not

    necessarily a personal one], or heresy of any kind could only come

    from the presumptuous questioning of common opinions,
    and from the belief that human reason is equal to every
    task. In those times •education had a great influence over
    the minds of men, and was almost equal in power to •the
    suggestions of the senses and common understanding, by
    which the most determined sceptic must admit that he is
    governed. But these days, when education has much less
    influence, and men’s increased contacts throughout the
    world have taught them to compare the principles that are
    accepted in different nations and ages, our cunning divines
    have changed their whole system of philosophy, and talk
    the language of Stoics, Platonists, and Aristotelians, not
    that of Pyrrhonians and Academics. If we distrust human
    reason, we have now no other principle to lead us into
    religion. These reverend gentlemen can be depended on to
    identify the system that best suits their purpose of keeping
    an ascendancy over mankind—it may be scepticism in one
    age, dogmatism in another—and making it their favourite
    principle and established doctrine.

    It is very natural, said Cleanthes, for men to embrace
    the principles by which they find they can best defend their
    doctrines; we can account for this reasonable behaviour
    without dragging priestcraft into the story. And, surely
    nothing can afford a stronger support for the truth of a
    set of principles than to observe that they tend to confirm
    true religion, and serve to silence the complaints of atheists,
    libertines, and freethinkers of all kinds.

    8

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 2

    Part 2

    I must admit, Cleanthes, said Demea, that nothing could
    surprise me more than the light in which you have all
    along put this argument. By the whole trend and tone
    of your remarks, one would think you were maintaining
    the existence of a God against the objections of atheists
    and infidels; and that you felt a need to stand up for that
    fundamental principle of all religion. But I hope there is no
    question here about the existence of a God. I am sure that
    no man—or anyway no man of common sense—ever had a
    serious doubt regarding such a certain and self-evident truth.
    The question is not about the existence but about the nature
    of God. Because of the infirmities of human understanding, I
    contend, the nature of God is entirely incomprehensible and
    unknown to us. The •essence of that supreme mind, •his
    attributes, •his way of existing, •his way of lasting through
    time—all these are mysterious to men, as is everything else
    concerning such a divine being. Finite, weak, and blind
    creatures such as we are ought to humble ourselves in his
    august presence; and, conscious of our frailties, stand in
    silent wonder at his infinite perfections, which eye has not
    seen, ear has not heard, neither has it entered into the heart
    of man to conceive. They are hidden from human curiosity
    by a deep cloud. It is insulting to God to try to penetrate
    these sacred obscurities. The audacity of prying into God’s
    nature and essence, his decrees and attributes, is second
    only to the impiety of denying his existence.

    Lest you should think that my piety has here overpowered
    my philosophy, I shall support my opinion—if it needs any
    support—by a very great authority. I could cite ·in my sup-
    port· almost any writer since the foundation of Christianity
    who has ever treated this or any other theological subject;

    but for now I shall confine myself to just one, who is equally
    famous for piety and philosophy. It is Father Malebranche,
    whom I remember as expressing himself thus:

    One ought to call God a spirit not so much to express
    positively what he is as to signify that he is not matter.
    He is an infinitely perfect being; this we cannot doubt.
    But just as we oughtn’t to imagine, even supposing
    him corporeal, that he has a human body (as the
    anthropomorphites asserted, on the grounds that
    the human shape is the most perfect of any), so we
    oughtn’t to imagine that the spirit of God has human
    ideas, or bears any resemblance to our spirit, on the
    grounds that we know nothing more perfect than a
    human mind. We ought rather to believe that just as
    he includes within himself the perfections of matter
    without being material, he includes within himself
    also the perfections of created spirits without being
    spirit according to our conception of spirit. We ought
    to believe that his true name is He that is, or in other
    words Being without restriction, All being, the being
    infinite and universal.

    After so great an authority as that, Demea, replied Philo,
    and a thousand more that you could produce, it would
    appear ridiculous in me to add my own view or express my
    approval of your doctrine. But, surely, when reasonable men
    discuss these subjects their topic is never the existence of
    God but only his nature. That he exists is, as you well ob-
    serve, unquestionable and self-evident. Nothing exists with-
    out a cause; and the original cause of this universe (whatever
    it may be) we call ‘God’, and piously ascribe to him every kind
    of perfection. Whoever questions this fundamental truth

    9

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 2

    deserves every punishment that philosophers can inflict on
    one another, namely, the greatest ridicule, contempt, and
    disapproval. But all perfection is entirely relative, so we
    ought never to imagine that we understand the attributes of
    this divine being, or to suppose that his perfections are in
    any way analogous or similar to the perfections of a human
    creature. Wisdom, thought, design, knowledge—it is proper
    for us to ascribe these to him, because those words are
    honourable among men, and we have no other language
    or other conceptions by which to express our wonder at
    his glory. But let us be careful not to think that our ideas
    ·of wisdom, thought, etc.· in any way correspond to his
    perfections, or that his attributes have any resemblance
    to these qualities of men. He is infinitely superior to our
    restricted view and limited understanding, and is more the
    object of worship in the temple than of debate in the schools.

    In reality, Cleanthes, he went on, we can arrive at this
    position without help from the pretend-scepticism that you
    so dislike. ·Here is how·:

    Our ideas reach no further than our experience.
    We have no experience of divine attributes and opera-
    tions.

    I needn’t conclude my syllogism: you can draw the inference
    yourself. And it is a pleasure to me (and I hope to you too)
    that valid reasoning and sound piety here work together
    to the same conclusion, and both of them establish the
    wondrously mysterious and incomprehensible nature of the
    supreme being.

    I shan’t beat about the bush, said Cleanthes, addressing
    himself to Demea. Still less shall I reply to Philo’s pious
    speeches. What I shall do is to explain briefly how I conceive
    this matter. Look round the world, contemplating the whole
    thing and every part of it; you’ll find that it is nothing
    but one big machine subdivided into an infinite number

    of smaller ones, which in their turn could be subdivided to a
    degree beyond what human senses and faculties can trace
    and explain. All these various machines, and even their
    most minute parts, are adjusted to each other so precisely
    that everyone who has ever contemplated them is filled with
    wonder. The intricate fitting of means to ends throughout
    all nature is just like (though more wonderful than) the
    fitting of means to ends in things that have been produced
    by us—products of human designs, thought, wisdom, and
    intelligence. Since the effects resemble each other, we are
    led to infer by all the rules of analogy that the causes are
    also alike, and that the author of nature is somewhat similar
    to the mind of man, though he has much larger faculties to
    go with the grandeur of the work he has carried out. By this
    argument a posteriori, and by this argument alone, do we
    prove both that there is a God and that he resembles human
    mind and intelligence.

    I have to tell you, Cleanthes, said Demea, that from the
    beginning, I could not approve of your conclusion about the
    similarity of God to men; still less can I approve of your
    ways of trying to establish it. What! No demonstration that
    God exists! No abstract arguments! No a priori proofs! [An

    a priori argument is one that proceeds by sheer thinking, making no use

    of contingent facts about what the world is like. An argument that does

    appeal to such facts is called a posteriori, which is what Cleanthes says

    that his argument is.] What about the ones that have in the
    past been so much insisted on by philosophers—are they
    all fallacious, all mere tricks? Do experience and probability
    mark the limit to how far we can go in this subject? I
    won’t say that this is betraying the cause of a God; but,
    surely, by this show of even-handedness you provide atheists
    with advantages that they could never have obtained purely
    through argument and reasoning.

    10

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 2

    My main reservation about what Cleanthes has said,
    Philo remarked, is not so much that he bases all religious
    arguments on experience as that his arguments seem not
    to be the most certain and unbreakable even of that inferior
    ·experience-based· kind. That a stone will fall, that fire
    will burn, that the earth has solidity, we have observed
    thousands of times; and when any new instance of this sort
    is presented we don’t hesitate to draw the usual conclusion—
    ·this stone will fall, this fire will burn, the earth that I
    am about to put my right foot on is solid·. The exact
    similarity of the cases gives us a perfect assurance of a
    similar outcome; and we never want or look for stronger
    evidence than that. But the evidence is less strong when
    the cases are less than perfectly alike; any reduction in
    similarity, however tiny, brings a corresponding reduction
    in the strength of the evidence; and as we move down
    that scale we may eventually reach a very weak analogy,
    ·leading to a conclusion· that is confessedly liable to error
    and uncertainty. After having observed •the circulation of
    the blood in human creatures, we have no doubt that •it
    circulates in Titius and Maevius. But from •its circulation in
    frogs and fishes it is only a presumption—though a strong
    one, from analogy—that •blood circulates in men and other
    animals. The analogical reasoning is even weaker when we
    infer •the circulation of the sap in plants from our experience
    that •the blood circulates in animals; and those who hastily
    followed that imperfect analogy between plants and animals
    have been found by more accurate experiments to have been
    mistaken.

    If we see a house, Cleanthes, we conclude with the
    greatest certainty that it had an architect or builder; because
    this is precisely the kind of effect that we have experienced
    as coming from that kind of cause. But surely you won’t say
    •that the universe is so like a house that we can with the

    same certainty infer a similar cause, or •that the analogy is
    here entire and perfect. The unlikeness in this case is so
    striking that the most you can offer ·on the basis of it· is a
    guess, a conjecture, a presumption about a similar cause;
    and I leave it to you to consider how that offering will be
    received in the world!

    If I granted that the proofs of the existence of a God
    amount to no more than a guess or conjecture, replied Clean-
    thes, that wouldn’t be well received, and I would deservedly
    be blamed and detested. But is it such a slight resemblance
    between how means are fitted to ends in a house and how
    they are fitted in the universe? The way things are fitted to
    their purposes? The order, proportion, and arrangement of
    every part? Steps of a staircase are plainly designed so that
    human legs can use them in climbing; and this inference
    ·from how the steps can be used to their purpose· is certain
    and infallible. Human legs are also designed for walking and
    climbing; and this inference ·from how legs can be used to
    their purpose·, I admit, is not quite so certain, because of the
    dissimilarity you have pointed out; but does that downgrade
    it to mere presumption or conjecture?

    Good God! exclaimed Demea, interrupting him, what
    have we come to? Earnest defenders of religion admitting
    that the proofs of a God fall short of being perfectly evident!
    And you, Philo, whose help I depended on in proving the
    worshipful mysteriousness of God’s nature—do you assent
    to all these extreme opinions of Cleanthes? For how else can
    I describe them? And why should I tone down my criticism
    when such principles are advanced, supported by such an
    authority ·as Cleanthes·, in the presence of such a young
    man as Pamphilus?

    You seem not to grasp, replied Philo, that I argue with
    Cleanthes in his own way: I hope that by showing him the
    dangerous consequences of his views I shall finally bring him

    11

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 2

    to share our opinion. But what bothers you most, I notice,
    is Cleanthes’ account of the argument a posteriori. You find
    that that argument ·in his version of it· is likely to slip out of
    your grasp and vanish into thin air; you think Cleanthes has
    so disguised it that you can hardly believe he has presented
    it properly. Now, however much I may disagree in other ways
    with the dangerous principles of Cleanthes, I must admit
    that he has fairly presented that argument; and I shall try to
    set it out for you in such a way that you will no longer view
    it with suspicion.

    If a man were to set aside everything he knows or has
    seen, he would be entirely unable to work out, merely from
    his own ideas, what the universe must be like, or to think one
    state of affairs to be more likely than another. Nothing that
    he clearly conceives could be thought to be impossible or to
    imply a contradiction, so every fanciful story his imagination
    comes up with would be on an equal footing with every other;
    and he could give no valid reason for sticking to one idea or
    system and rejecting the others that are equally possible.

    Next step in the argument: after he opens his eyes and
    sees the world as it really is, he can’t at first tell what the
    cause was of any one event, much less of the totality of
    things or of the universe. He might start his imagination
    rambling, and it might bring in to him an infinite variety of
    reports and stories. These would all be possible, but because
    they would all be equally possible he could never from his
    own resources explain satisfactorily why he prefers one of
    them to the rest. Experience alone can point out to him the
    true cause of anything that happens.

    Now, Demea, this method of reasoning leads to something
    that Cleanthes himself has tacitly admitted, namely: order,
    arrangement, or the suitability of things for various purposes
    (like the suitability of legs for walking) is not of itself any
    proof that a designer has been at work, except in cases where

    experience has shown us that such order, arrangement, etc.
    is due to a designer. For all we can know a priori, matter
    may have a source of order within it, just as mind does,
    having it inherently, basically, ·not acquired from somewhere
    else·. [The interpolation in this next bit is longer than most. To make it

    easier to recognize, it is flagged by *asterisks rather than ·small dots·.]
    When a number of elements come together in an exquisite
    arrangement, *you may think it harder to conceive that
    •they do this of their own accord than to conceive that
    •some designer put them into that arrangement. But that
    is too quick and careless. Think about what is involved in
    a designer’s arranging them: it means that he creates the
    arrangement in his mind, assembling in the appropriate way
    the ideas of the elements in question. But, then, how does
    that happen? I put it to you*, it is no harder to conceive that

    •the elements are caused to come together into this
    arrangement by some unknown cause that is internal
    to them,

    than it is to conceive that
    •the ideas of these elements come together in that ar-
    rangement in the great universal mind, being caused
    to do so by a similarly unknown cause that is internal
    to that mind.

    These two suppositions are agreed to be equally possible;
    but according to Cleanthes experience shows us a difference
    between them. Throw several pieces of steel together, without
    shape or form: they will never arrange themselves so as to
    compose a watch. Stone, and mortar, and wood, without an
    architect, never erect a house. But we see that the ideas in
    a human mind arrange themselves so as to form the plan
    of a watch or house, though we haven’t the faintest notion
    of how they do this. So experience shows that minds—and
    not matter—have a built-in principle of order. From similar
    effects we infer similar causes. The way means are fitted to

    12

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 2

    ends in the universe at large is like the way means are fitted
    to ends in a machine designed by a human being. The cause
    of the machine, therefore, must be similar to the cause of
    the universe.

    I was, I admit, shocked by this assertion of a resemblance
    between God and human creatures. I can’t help seeing
    it as implying such a lowering of the supreme being that
    no right-thinking Theist could put up with it. With your
    assistance, therefore, Demea, I shall try to defend what you
    justly call the worshipful mysteriousness of God’s nature,
    and shall refute this reasoning of Cleanthes, provided he
    agrees that I have presented it fairly.

    When Cleanthes had agreed to this, Philo, after a short
    pause, proceeded in the following manner.

    In the meantime I shan’t disagree much with your theses
    •that all inferences concerning matters of fact are based on
    experience, and •that all experimental reasoning is based
    on the supposition that similar causes prove similar effects,
    and similar effects prove similar causes. But please notice
    how extremely cautious good thinkers are in transferring a
    discovered result to a similar case. These thinkers are not
    perfectly confident in applying their past observation to some
    other particular phenomenon, unless the ·old and new· cases
    are exactly similar. Every alteration in the circumstances
    ·of the cause· raises a doubt about the outcome; and it
    requires new experiments to prove for sure that the new
    circumstances have no causal significance. A change in
    size, position, arrangement, age, disposition of the air or
    of surrounding bodies—any of these may bring with it the
    most unexpected consequences. Unless the objects are quite
    familiar to us, it is much too bold to expect confidently
    that when a cause has been found to have a certain effect
    another cause, differing from the earlier one in one of these
    ways, will have the same effect. The slow and deliberate

    steps of scientists, here if anywhere, are in contrast with the
    precipitate march of common men who, hurried along by the
    smallest similarity, are incapable of pondering or making
    distinctions.

    ·Which group, Cleanthes, have you just shown yourself
    to belong to?· You are usually cool and philosophical in
    these matters, but has your usual attitude been preserved
    in the stride you have taken in likening •the universe to
    •houses, ships, furniture, and machines, inferring from
    their similarity in some respects a similarity in their causes?
    Thought, design, intelligence, such as we discover in men
    and other animals, is just one of the springs and forces of the
    universe, along with heat and cold, attraction and repulsion,
    and a hundred others that we observe daily. It is an active
    cause through which (we find) certain particular parts of
    nature produce alterations in other parts. But can it be
    proper to argue from parts to the whole? Doesn’t the great
    disproportion ·between part and whole· bar all comparison
    and inference? From observing the growth of a hair, can we
    learn anything about how men come into being? Would the
    way a leaf blows—even if we knew this perfectly—teach us
    anything about how a tree grows?

    Anyway, even if we do take the operations of one part of
    nature on another as our basis for a judgment about the
    origin of the whole (which is something we should never do),
    why would we select as our basis such a tiny, weak, limited
    cause as the reason and design of animals on this planet
    seems to be? This little agitation of the brain that we call
    ‘thought’—what special privilege does it have that entitles
    it to serve as the model of the whole universe? It looms
    large for us because we are always in the presence of it; but
    sound philosophy ought carefully to guard against this kind
    of natural illusion.

    13

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 2

    So far from admitting, continued Philo, that •the opera-
    tions of a part entitle us to draw any conclusion about •the
    origin of the whole, I won’t even allow •any one part to justify
    conclusions about •another part, if the two are very unlike
    one another. Is there any reasonable ground to conclude that
    the inhabitants of other planets have thought, intelligence,
    reason, or anything similar to these faculties that men have?
    When nature has operated in such a wide variety of ways
    on this small planet, can we think that she incessantly
    copies herself throughout the rest of this immense universe?
    Also, it seems likely enough that thought occurs only in this
    narrow corner, and even here its sphere of action is very
    limited—·namely, to affecting the movements of the bodies
    of some animals·. So what can justify taking thought to be
    the original cause of everything? Such a jump is worse than
    that of a peasant whose idea of the government of kingdoms
    is based on how he runs his own household!

    But even if we were perfectly sure that thought and reason
    similar to ours is to be found throughout the whole universe,
    and even if its activity elsewhere in the universe is vastly
    greater in scope and more powerful than it appears to be
    on this planet, still I cannot see that the operations of •a
    world that is fully constituted, arranged and adjusted can
    properly be extended to •a world that is in its embryo state,
    and is still moving towards that finished constitution and
    arrangement. By observation we know a certain amount
    about how a finished animal moves, is nourished, stays
    alive; but we should be cautious about transferring that
    knowledge speculatively to the growth of a foetus in the
    womb, and still more to the formation of an animalcule
    in the testes of its male parent. [‘animalcule’ = ‘tiny animal’. It

    was commonly thought that the animal is formed in miniature in the

    father’s body, the mother’s contribution being merely to provide it with

    somewhere to grow.] Even our limited experience shows us that

    nature has an infinite number of causes and principles which
    incessantly reveal themselves as circumstances change. It
    would be absurdly rash of us to claim to know what new and
    unknown principles would be at work in such a new and
    unknown situation as that of the formation of a universe.

    A very small part of this great system of the universe,
    during a very short time, is very imperfectly revealed to us,
    Do we then pronounce confidently about the origin of the
    whole?

    Admirable conclusion! At this time on this little planet
    stone, wood, brick, iron, brass are not ordered or arranged
    except through human artifice and contrivance; therefore the
    universe couldn’t originally attain its order and arrangement
    without something similar to human artifice. But is one part
    of nature a rule for another part that is very different from
    it? Is it a rule for the whole? Is a very small part a rule for
    the universe? Is nature in one situation a certain rule for
    nature in another situation vastly different from the former?
    ·Is nature at work in our considerably developed universe a
    certain rule for nature at work in starting a universe?·

    And can you blame me, Cleanthes, if I here imitate the
    wise caution of Simonides? According to the famous story,
    Hiero asked him ‘What is God?’, and Simonides asked for a
    day to think about it, and then two days more; and in that
    way he continually prolonged his time for thinking about it,
    without ever producing a definition or description. Could
    you even blame me if I answered straight off that I didn’t
    know what God is, and was aware that this subject lies
    vastly beyond the reach of my faculties? You might cry
    ‘Sceptic!’ and ‘Tease!’ as much as you pleased; but having
    found the imperfections and even contradictions of human
    reason when it is exercised on so many other subjects that
    are much more familiar than this one, I would never expect
    any success from reason’s feeble conjectures concerning a

    14

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 2

    subject that is so elevated and so remote from the sphere
    of our observation. When two sorts of objects have always
    been observed to be conjoined together, custom leads me
    to infer the existence of ·an object of· one ·sort· wherever I
    see the existence of ·an object of· the other ·sort·; and I call
    this an argument from experience. But it is hard to see how
    this ·pattern of· argument can be appropriate in our present
    case, where the objects ·we are considering don’t fall into
    sorts, but· are single, individual, without parallel or specific
    resemblance. And will anyone tell me with a straight face
    that an orderly universe must arise from some thought and
    artifice like human thought and artifice, because we have
    experience of it? To make this reasoning secure, we would
    need to have had experience of the origins of worlds; it isn’t
    sufficient, surely, to have seen ships and cities arise from
    human artifice and contrivance.

    Philo was going on in this vigorous manner, somewhere
    between joking and seriousness (it seemed to me), when he
    noticed signs of impatience in Cleanthes, and immediately
    stopped. What I wanted to cut in with, said Cleanthes,
    is only the suggestion that you stop abusing terms, using
    common everyday expressions to subvert philosophical rea-
    sonings. You know that common people often distinguish
    ‘reason’ from ‘experience’, even where the question relates
    only to a matter of fact and existence; though it is found
    that where that kind of ‘reason’ is properly analysed it turns
    out to be nothing but a sort of experience. To prove ‘by
    experience’ that the universe was originated by a mind
    is no more contrary to common speech than to prove ‘by
    experience’ that the earth moves. A fault-finder could raise
    against the Copernican system all the objections that you
    have urged against my reasonings. ‘Have you other earths’,
    he might say, ‘which you have seen to move? Have. . . ’

    Yes! interrupted Philo, we do have other earths. Isn’t
    the moon another earth, which we see to turn round its
    centre? Isn’t Venus another earth, where we see the same
    thing? Aren’t the revolutions of the sun also a confirmation—
    through analogy—of the same theory? Aren’t all the planets
    that revolve around the sun earths? Aren’t the satellites
    of Jupiter and Saturn moons that move around the sun
    along with their primary planets? These analogies and
    resemblances—and others that I haven’t mentioned—are
    the only evidence for the Copernican system. It is for you to
    consider whether you have any analogies of the same kind
    to support your theory.

    In reality, Cleanthes, he went on, the modern system of
    astronomy is now so thoroughly accepted by all enquirers,
    and has become such an essential a part of the education
    even of small children, that we are often not very scrupulous
    about examining the reasons for it. It is now become a matter
    of mere scholarly curiosity to study the first writers on that
    subject—the ones who had the full force of prejudice against
    them, and had to present their arguments in every possible
    light in order to render them popular and convincing. But if
    we peruse Galileo’s famous Dialogues concerning the system
    of the world, we shall find that that great genius—one of
    the greatest who ever existed—first put all his efforts into
    proving that there is no basis for the distinction commonly
    made between ‘elementary’ and ‘celestial’ substances. The
    Aristotelian scientists, relying on sensory illusions, had made
    a great deal of this distinction; they had laid it down that
    ‘celestial’ substances cannot be generated, altered, or in any
    way affected, and they had assigned all the opposite qualities
    to ‘elementary’ substances. But Galileo, beginning with the
    moon, proved its similarity in every detail to the earth—its
    convex shape, its natural darkness when not illuminated
    ·by the sun·, its density, its distinction into solid and liquid,

    15

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

  • Part 3
  • the variations of its phases, the mutual illuminations of the
    earth and moon, their mutual eclipses, the unevenness of
    the moon’s surface, and so on. After many examples of this
    kind relating to all the planets, men saw that these bodies
    were proper objects of experience, and that their similarity to
    one another entitled us to extend the same arguments and
    phenomena from one to another.

    This cautious proceeding of the astronomers implicitly
    condemns your argument, Cleanthes; or, rather, it points to
    the fact that the subject on which you are engaged exceeds

    all human reason and enquiry. Can you claim to show
    any such similarity between the structure of a house and
    the generation of a universe? Have you ever seen nature
    in a situation that resembles the first arrangement of the
    elements ·at the beginning of the universe·? Have worlds
    ever been formed under your eye; and have you had leisure
    to observe the whole progress of world-making, from the first
    appearance of order to its final consummation? If you have,
    then cite your experience, and deliver your theory.

    Part 3

    In the hands of an ingenious and inventive person, replied
    Cleanthes, even the most absurd argument can be made to
    seem plausible! Don’t you realize, Philo, •that Copernicus
    and his first disciples had to prove the similarity of terrestrial
    to celestial matter because various scientists—blinded by old
    systems, and supported by some empirical evidence—had
    denied that similarity? but •that theists don’t in the same
    way have to prove the similarity of the works of nature to
    those of human artifice, because this similarity is self-evident
    and undeniable? The works of nature are made of the same
    stuff as are human artifacts, and the two are alike in form
    also; what more is needed to show an analogy between
    their causes, and to show that the origin of all things is
    a divine purpose and intention? Your objections, to put it
    bluntly, are no better than the elaborate arguments used by
    the philosophers who denied that anything moves; and they
    ought to be refuted in the same way as those, by illustrations,

    examples, and instances, rather than by serious argument
    and philosophy. ·That is how I shall oppose your arguments·.

    Suppose •that an articulate voice were heard in the
    clouds, much louder and more melodious than any human
    voice could ever be; suppose further •that this voice were
    heard at the same time in all nations, and that it spoke to
    each nation in its own language and dialect; suppose, finally,
    •that the words spoken from the sky were not only mean-
    ingful but conveyed some instruction that was altogether
    worthy of a benevolent being who was superior to mankind.
    If all that occurred, could you possibly hesitate for a moment
    over the cause of this voice? Wouldn’t you be compelled to
    ascribe it, straight off, to some design or purpose? Yet if you
    did come to that conclusion, your inference would be open
    to all the same objections (if they deserve such a label) that
    are brought against the system of theism.

    16

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 3

    Here’s the position you seem to be committed to:
    All conclusions about matters of fact are based on
    experience: when we hear an articulate voice in the
    dark and infer that a man has spoken, it is only the
    resemblance of the effects which leads us to conclude
    that there is a similar resemblance in the causes.
    But this extraordinary voice from the sky is loud and
    wide-ranging and flexible as to languages, which no
    human voice is; so we have no reason to suppose
    its cause is like the cause of human speech. So this
    rational, wise, coherent speech came from we know
    not where—perhaps an accidental whistling of the
    winds—and not from any divine reason or intelligence.

    You can see clearly your own objections in these objections;
    and I hope you also see clearly that one lot is no better than
    the other.

    But to bring the case still nearer our present topic of the
    universe, I shall make two suppositions, which—·though
    they are weird and not true·—don’t involve any absurdity or
    impossibility. Suppose •that there is a natural, universal, in-
    variable language, common to every individual of the human
    race; and •that books are natural products which perpetuate
    themselves in the same way as animals and plants do, by
    descent and propagation. ·These suppositions aren’t as
    wildly far from fact as you might think·. •We do have a
    kind of universal language, embedded in some expressions
    of our passions; and all the lower animals have a natural
    speech, which, however limited, is very intelligible to their
    own species. And •as the finest and most eloquent text
    is infinitely less complex and intricate than the coarsest
    organism, the propagation of an Iliad or Aeneid is easier to
    suppose than that of any plant or animal.

    Well, now: suppose you enter your library, the shelves
    of which are full of natural volumes, containing the most

    refined reasoning and most exquisite beauty; could you
    possibly open one of them and doubt that its original cause
    bore the strongest analogy to mind and intelligence? When
    it reasons and discourses; when it expostulates, argues,
    and enforces its views and lines of thought; when it appeals
    sometimes to the pure intellect, sometimes to the feelings;
    when it takes up every consideration suited to the subject,
    decorates it and deals with it; could you still say that all this
    basically had no meaning, and that thought and planning
    had no role to play when this volume first came into being
    in the loins of its original parent? I know you aren’t as
    obstinate as that; even your irresponsible scepticism would
    be ashamed to assert such a glaring absurdity.

    Furthermore, Philo, if there is any difference between my
    ‘two suppositions’ case and the real state of affairs in the
    universe, it is the latter that suits my argument better. The
    anatomy of an animal presents many stronger instances of
    design than the reading of Livy or Tacitus does; and any
    objection which you start in the ‘real world’ case, demanding
    that we attend to such an unusual and extraordinary scene
    as the first formation of worlds, holds equally in the ‘two
    suppositions’ case with its vegetating library. So choose
    sides, Philo, without ambiguity or evasion; either assert that
    a rational book needn’t have a rational cause, or admit a
    similar cause for all the works of nature.

    Let me add, Cleanthes went on, that this religious argu-
    ment, instead of being weakened by the scepticism that you
    keep parading, is actually strengthened by it, becoming more
    firm and undisputed. To reject all argument and reasoning
    is either affectation or madness. Every reasonable sceptic
    rejects only argumentation that is abstruse, remote, and
    intricate; sticks to common sense and the plain instincts of
    nature; and assents to things the reasons for which strike
    him with so much force that it would take him an enormous

    17

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 3

    effort not to assent. Now the arguments for natural religion
    are plainly of this ·forceful, almost irresistible· kind; and
    nothing but the most perverse and obstinate metaphysics
    can reject them. Think about the anatomy of the eye,
    consider its structure and design, and then tell me—doesn’t
    the idea of a designer immediately come into your mind with
    a force like that of a sensation? The most obvious conclusion,
    surely, is in favour of a designer; and it requires time,
    reflection, and study to bring to mind objections—which
    are frivolous although they are abstruse—which can support
    atheism. Who can see the male and female of each species,
    the fit between their bodies, their instincts, their passions,
    and their whole course of life before and after generation,
    without being aware that the propagation of the species is
    intended by nature? Millions and millions of such instances
    present themselves through every part of the universe; and
    •the intricate fit of things to their purposes conveys an
    intelligible and obvious meaning at least as well as does any
    •language. What level of blind dogmatism would you have to
    reach to reject such natural and convincing arguments?

    However you may carp at it, the argument that likens an
    orderly world to a coherent, articulate speech will still be
    accepted as an incontestable proof of design and intention
    ·in the causation of the world·. If this argument for theism
    conflicts with the principles of logic, as you claim it does,
    its irresistible power over nearly everyone clearly shows that
    there may be arguments that are good although they break
    the rules. ·Don’t dismiss this as special pleading, for we do
    sometimes accept rule-breaking performances as good, even
    as excellent·. We sometimes encounter beauties in writing
    that seem contrary to the rules, and yet gain our affections
    and enliven our imaginations in opposition to all the literary
    doctrines and to the authority of the established literary
    masters.

    It sometimes happens, I admit, that the religious ar-
    guments don’t have the influence they should have on an
    ignorant savage and barbarian; not because they are obscure
    and difficult, but because the savage never asks himself
    any of the questions on which they depend. Where does
    the intricate structure of an animal come from? From the
    copulation of its parents. And where do the parents come
    from? From their parents. Repeat this a few times and the
    objects come to be at such a distance from the savage that
    he loses them in darkness and confusion; and he has no
    curiosity to trace them further. But this is neither dogmatism
    nor scepticism, but stupidity: a state of mind very different
    from your close-arguing, question-raising disposition, my
    ingenious friend! You can trace causes from effects; you
    can compare the most distant and remote objects; and your
    greatest errors proceed not from barrenness of thought and
    invention, but from too luxuriant a fertility, which suppresses
    your natural good sense by a profusion of unnecessary
    doubts and objections.

    Here I could observe that Philo was a little embarrassed
    and confused; but while he hesitated in giving an answer,
    Demea broke in on the conversation—luckily for Philo!

    Your example involving books and language, he said to
    Cleanthes, gets much of its force from being familiar; but
    isn’t there some danger in this very familiarity? May it not
    lead us to get above ourselves, by making us imagine we
    comprehend God and have some adequate idea of his nature
    and attributes? When I read a book I enter into the mind
    and intention of the author: at that moment I become him,
    in a way, and have an immediate feeling and conception
    of the ideas that revolved in his imagination when he was
    writing. But we can never come as close as that to God.
    His ways are not our ways. His attributes are perfect, but
    incomprehensible. And his ‘book’ of nature contains a great

    18

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 3

    and inexplicable riddle, more than any intelligible discourse
    or reasoning.

    The ancient Platonists, you know, were the most religious
    and devout of all the pagan philosophers; yet many of
    them, particularly Plotinus, expressly declare that intellect
    or understanding is not to be ascribed to God, and that our
    most perfect worship of him consists not in acts of vener-
    ation, reverence, gratitude, or love but rather in a certain
    mysterious self-annihilation, or total extinction of all our
    faculties. These ideas are perhaps too far stretched; but still
    ·there is a truth buried in them·: it must be admitted that by
    representing God as so intelligible and comprehensible, and
    so similar to a human mind, we are guilty of the grossest and
    most narrow self-centredness, making ourselves the model
    of the whole universe.

    All the sentiments of the human mind—gratitude, re-
    sentment, love, friendship, approval, blame, pity, imitation,
    envy—clearly involve the state and situation of man, and
    are calculated for preserving the existence and promoting
    the activity of beings like us in circumstances like ours.
    So it seems unreasonable to transfer such sentiments to a
    supreme being, or to suppose that he is moved by them;
    besides which, the phenomena of the universe won’t support

    us in such a theory. All our •ideas derived from the senses
    are confusedly false and deceptive, and so can’t be supposed
    to have a place in a supreme intelligence; and the whole
    stock of the human understanding consists of those together
    with •the ideas of the external senses, ·and we can’t attribute
    the latter to God, who is in no way passive and so doesn’t
    have senses as we do·. We may conclude that none of the
    •materials of thought in the human intelligence are in any
    respect like those of the divine intelligence. Now, as to the
    •manner of thinking: how can we make any comparison
    between them, or suppose them to be in any way alike? Our
    thought is fluctuating, uncertain, fleeting, successive, and
    compounded [= ‘made up of little elements of thought’]; and these
    features of it belong to its essence, so that it would be an
    abuse of words to apply the name of ‘thought’ or ‘reason’ to
    anything that wasn’t fluctuating, uncertain, etc. At least, if
    it seems more pious and respectful (as it really is) still to
    use these words when we speak of the supreme being, we
    should admit that their meaning as applied to him is totally
    incomprehensible, and that the weakness of our nature
    prevents us from having any ideas that correspond in the
    least to the ineffable sublimity of God’s attributes.

    19

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 4

    Part 4

    It seems strange to me, said Cleanthes, that you, Demea,
    who are so sincere in the cause of religion, should still
    maintain the mysterious, incomprehensible nature of God,
    and should insist so strenuously that he in no way resembles
    human creatures. I freely admit that God has many powers
    and attributes that we can’t comprehend; but if our ideas
    of him are not, as far as they go, true and adequate and in
    conformity with his real nature, I don’t know what remains
    that is worth discussing in this subject. Is the name, without
    any meaning, of such vast importance? And how do you
    mystics, who maintain the absolute incomprehensibility of
    God, differ from sceptics or atheists who assert that the first
    cause of everything is unknown and unintelligible? They
    reject the view that the world was produced by a mind, by
    which I mean a mind like the human one (for I don’t know
    of any other kind). They must be •very bold if they then go
    on to claim to know what other specific intelligible cause
    produced the world; and ·if they don’t make that claim, and
    admit that the cause is unknown to them·, they must be
    •very scrupulous indeed if they refuse to call the unknown
    cause of everything a ‘God’ or ‘Deity’, and to bestow on him
    as many high-flown praises and meaningless epithets as you
    may ask them to.

    Who could imagine, replied Demea, that Cleanthes—the
    calm philosophical Cleanthes—would attempt to refute his
    antagonists by sticking a label on them (·namely the label
    ‘mystic’·) and, like the common bigots and inquisitors of our
    time, resort to invective and rhetoric instead of reasoning?
    Doesn’t he realize that his kind of attack can go either way,
    and that ‘anthropomorphite’ is as damaging and threatening
    a label, bringing as much danger with it, as the epithet

    ‘mystic’ with which he has honoured me? [‘Anthropo-morphite’

    comes from Greek meaning ‘human-shaped’. An anthropomorphite is

    someone who holds that God is like a man.] In reality, Cleanthes,
    consider what you are saying when you represent God as
    similar to a human mind and understanding. What is the
    mind of man? It is made up of many different faculties,
    passions, sentiments and ideas; they are indeed united into
    one self or person, but they are still distinct from each
    other. When a man’s mind reasons, the ideas that are
    the parts of its ·mental· discourse arrange themselves in
    a certain form or order; and this is not preserved intact for a
    moment, but immediately makes way for a new arrangement
    ·of ideas·. New opinions, new passions, new affections,
    new feelings arise, which continually diversify the mental
    scene, and produce in it the greatest variety and most rapid
    succession imaginable. How is this compatible with that
    perfect unchangingness and simplicity—·‘simplicity’ in the
    sense of ‘not having parts’·—which all true theists ascribe to
    God? According to them, he sees past, present, and future
    in a single act; his love and hatred, his mercy and justice,
    are one individual operation; he is entirely present at every
    point in space, and exists completely at every instant of time.
    God’s nature doesn’t involve the slightest hint of difference or
    variation: there is no sequence of events in him, he doesn’t
    change, he doesn’t gain or lose anything. What he is now is
    what he has always been, and always will be, without any
    change in what he thinks, feels, or does. He stands fixed
    in one simple, perfect state; and it can never be correct to
    say that this act of his is different from that, or that this
    judgment or idea is one that he had only recently, and that
    it will in time be followed by some other judgment or idea.

    20

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 4

    I can readily allow, said Cleanthes, that those who
    maintain that God is perfectly simple ·in the sense you have
    given to this, and· to the extent that you have just expressed,
    are complete mystics, and are guilty of all the consequences
    that I have derived from their opinion. They are, in a word,
    atheists without knowing it. For though we may grant
    that God has attributes •that we cannot understand, still
    we ought never to ascribe to him any attributes •that are
    absolutely incompatible with the thinking nature that is
    essential to him. A ‘mind’ whose acts and feelings and ideas
    are not distinct and successive, a ‘mind’ that is wholly simple
    and totally unchanging, is a ‘mind’ that has no thought, no
    reason, no will, no sentiment, no love, no hatred. In short, it
    isn’t a mind at all! It is an abuse of words to call it a ‘mind’,
    on a par with speaking of a region of space that has no shape,
    or of number that isn’t composed of smaller numbers.

    Think who your targets are! said Philo. You confer the
    title ‘atheist’ on almost all the sound, orthodox theologians
    who have treated this subject; and you will end up finding
    that by your criteria you are the only sound theist in the
    world. But if idolaters are atheists (as I think they can fairly
    be said to be), and if Christian theologians are also atheists
    (·as you have implied·), what is left of the famous argument
    ·for theism· from the universal consent of mankind?

    But I know that names and authorities don’t carry much
    weight with you, so I’ll try to show you a little more clearly
    the drawbacks of that anthropomorphism that you have
    embraced; and I shall prove that there is no basis for the
    view that a plan of the world was formed in God’s mind,
    consisting of distinct ideas, differently arranged, in the way
    an architect forms in his head the plan of a house that he
    intends to build.

    It isn’t easy to see what is gained by this supposition
    ·that God had such a plan·, whether we steer by reason

    or by experience. You have offered this supposed plan as
    a satisfactory and conclusive cause ·of the world. But we
    cannot leave it at that, for· we still have to raise the further
    question about the cause of this cause. ·Looking for an
    answer, let us first consult •reason, then •experience·.

    If •reason (I mean abstract reason, involving a priori
    thoughts) is not equally silent with regard to all questions
    concerning cause and effect, it will at least venture to say
    this much:

    A mental world (or universe of ideas) stands in as
    much need of a cause as does a material world (or
    universe of objects); and, if the mental world is similar
    in its arrangement to the material one, their causes
    must be similar.

    For there is nothing here to give rise to a different conclusion
    or inference ·regarding one world from what we can conclude
    regarding the other·. Looked at abstractly, they are entirely
    alike; and any problem concerning either of them is equally
    a problem for the other.

    If we turn to •experience, compelling it to say something
    on these subjects that lie beyond its sphere, ·it replies that· it
    can’t see any significant difference between these two kinds
    of worlds, so far as causation is concerned: it finds them to
    be governed by similar principles, and to depend on an equal
    variety of causes in their operations. We have specimens in
    miniature of both sorts of world: our mind resembles the
    one, a plant or animal the other. So let experience judge
    from these samples, ·which are within its sphere·. Nothing
    seems more intricate in its causes than thought is. Because
    these causes never operate in the same way in two people,
    we never find two people who think exactly alike. Indeed,
    one person doesn’t think in exactly the same way at any two
    times. A difference of age, of the disposition of his body,
    of weather, of food, of company, of books, of passions—any

    21

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 4

    of these details, and others that are less conspicuous, are
    sufficient to alter the precise machinery of thought and cause
    very different movements and operations in it. As far as we
    can judge, plants and animal bodies are no more intricate in
    their motions, and don’t depend on a greater variety or more
    precise adjustment of springs and forces.

    Now, as well as the question concerning •the cause of
    the being whom you suppose to be the author of nature,
    your system of anthropomorphism confronts us with another
    question, concerning the cause of •the mental world that
    you see as causing the material world—·that is, the cause
    of •God’s plan·. How can we satisfy ourselves about that?
    Haven’t we the same reason to see that mental world as
    caused by another mental world, or new force of thinking?
    But if we stop there, ·refusing to raise the question about the
    cause of God’s plan·, why do we go as far as God’s plan? Why
    not stop at the material world? How can we satisfy ourselves
    without going on to infinity? Not that there is any satisfaction
    in the infinite sequence ·of causes of causes of. . . ·. Let
    us remember the story of the Indian philosopher and his
    elephant: ·he thought that the earth needed something to
    hold it up, and supposed it rested on an elephant, which he
    then supposed rested on a tortoise. . . ·. The story was never
    more applicable than it is to the present subject, ·switching
    from a spatial to a causal interpretation of ‘rest on’·. If the
    material world rests ·causally· on a mental world that is
    similar to it, this mental world must rest on some other; and
    so on without end. It would be better, therefore, never to
    look beyond the present material world. By supposing it to
    contain within itself the causes of its order, we are really
    taking it to be God; and the sooner we arrive at that divine
    being, the better. When you go one step beyond the system
    of the familiar world, you only stir people up into asking
    questions that can’t possibly be answered.

    You may say ‘The different ideas that make up God’s plan
    fall into order of themselves, and by their own nature’, but
    that has no precise meaning. If it has a meaning, I would
    like to know why it is not equally good sense to say ‘The
    parts of the material world fall into order of themselves, and
    by their own nature’. Can one opinion be intelligible, when
    the other isn’t?

    We do indeed have experience of ideas that fall into order
    of themselves, and without any known cause ·outside them·.
    But I am sure we have much more experience of matter
    that does the same—for example in every case of generation
    and vegetation, where it is beyond our capacities to work
    out what the causes are [in this work ‘generation’ usually = the

    whole process through which animals have offspring, and ‘vegetation’ =

    the corresponding process for plants]. We have also experience
    of particular systems of thought and of matter that have
    no order—of thought in madness, of matter in the decay
    of dead organisms. So why should we think that order
    is more essential to one than to the other? And if order
    requires a cause in both, what advantage does your system
    give us when it takes the ·material· universe of objects to
    be caused by a similar ·mental· universe of ideas? Our first
    step ·beyond the material world· leads us on for ever. So it
    would be wise of us to limit all our enquiries to the present
    world, without looking beyond it. We can get no satisfaction
    from these speculations that so far exceed the narrow limits
    of human understanding.

    As you know, Cleanthes, when the ancient Aristotelians
    were asked about the cause of some phenomenon, they
    usually replied in terms of their concepts of faculty or occult
    quality. Asked why bread nourishes, for instance, they would
    say that bread nourishes by its •‘nutritive faculty’, and that
    senna purges by its •‘purgative faculty’. But it has turned
    out that this device was merely a disguise for ignorance,

    22

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 4

    and that those philosophers were really saying—though less
    openly—the same thing as the sceptics and the plain people
    say when they candidly admit that they don’t know what
    causes these phenomena. Well, now, when we ask what
    causes order in the ideas of God, can you anthropomorphites
    give any answer except that the cause is a •‘rational faculty’,
    and that such is the nature of God? If that is acceptable, then
    it is hard to see why it isn’t equally acceptable to account for
    the world’s order in a similar way—·appealing to ‘faculties’
    and ‘natures’ that material things have·—without having
    recourse to any such thinking creator as you insist on. It
    is only to say that this is the ‘nature’ of material objects,
    and that they all have an inherent ‘faculty’ of order and
    proportion; which are merely more learned and elaborate
    ways of admitting ignorance. The comparable story about
    God’s plan is no better than this one about the material
    world—except in being closer to the prejudices of common
    people.

    You have presented this argument with great emphasis,
    replied Cleanthes, apparently not realizing how easy it is
    to answer it. When in everyday life I assign a cause for
    some event, Philo, is it any objection that I can’t assign the
    cause of that cause, and answer every new question that
    may endlessly be raised? [In reading the next bit, remember that

    in Hume’s day ‘philosopher’ covered scientists as well.] What philoso-
    phers could possibly submit to so rigid a rule? Philosophers
    admit that ultimate causes are totally unknown; and they
    are aware that the most refined principles which they use
    to explain the phenomena are as inexplicable to them as
    the phenomena themselves are to the common people. ·So
    there can be no question of their agreeing that it’s no use

    assigning a cause unless you also assign the cause of the
    cause·. The order and arrangement of nature, the intricate
    adjustment of things to their purposes, the plain use and
    intended purpose of every part and organ ·of a plant or
    animal·—all these announce in the clearest language an
    intelligent cause or author. The heavens and the earth join
    in the same testimony: the whole chorus of nature raises one
    hymn to the praises of its creator. You alone, or almost alone,
    disturb this general harmony. You start abstruse doubts,
    complaints, and objections; you ask me, what is the cause
    of this cause? I don’t know, and I don’t care. I have found
    a God, and with that I stop my enquiry. Let those who are
    wiser or more enterprising go further.

    I don’t claim to be wiser or more enterprising, replied
    Philo: and for that very reason I might never have tried to
    go so far; especially when I’m aware that I must eventually
    settle for the same answer that I might—saving myself all
    that trouble—have settled for from the beginning. If I am
    still to remain in utter ignorance of causes, and can’t give
    a full explanation of anything, I shall never think it is an
    advantage to shove off for a moment a difficulty which (you
    admit) must immediately come back to me with its full force.
    Natural scientists indeed very properly explain particular
    effects by more general causes, even when these general
    causes themselves are in the end totally inexplicable; but
    surely they never think it satisfactory to explain a particular
    effect by a particular cause that is no more explicable than
    the effect itself. A •system of ideas, arranged by itself without
    a prior design, is not a whit more explicable than a •material
    system that attains its order in the same way; there is no
    more difficulty in the latter supposition than in the former.

    23

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 5

    Part 5

    But to show you still more inconveniences in your an-
    thropomorphism, continued Philo, please look again at your
    principles. Like effects prove like causes. This is the ·basis
    for every· •empirical argument, and you say that it is also the
    only ·basis for the· •theological argument. Now, it is certain
    that the more similar the observed effects, and the more
    similar the causes that are inferred, the stronger is the argu-
    ment. Every move away from similarity, between the effects
    or between the causes, lowers the probability and makes
    the empirical argument less conclusive. You can’t doubt the
    principle; so you oughtn’t to reject its consequences.

    According to •the true system of theism, all the new
    discoveries in astronomy, which prove the immense grandeur
    and magnificence of the works of nature, are further ar-
    guments for the existence of a God; according to •your
    hypothesis of empirical theism they become objections, by
    moving the universe still further from all resemblance to the
    effects of human skill and contrivance. If the argument for
    genuine theism had force in earlier times, how much more
    force it must have now, when the bounds of nature are so
    infinitely enlarged and such a magnificent scene is opened
    to us? [As evidence of its support in ancient times, Philo
    quotes (in Latin) from Lucretius and Cicero. Then:] It is still
    more unreasonable to form our idea of the cause of such an
    unlimited effect on the basis of our experience of ·the causes
    of· the narrow products of human design and invention.

    The discoveries by microscopes, as they open a new
    universe in miniature, are arguments ·for theism· according
    to me, whereas to you they are objections to it. The further
    we push our researches of this kind, the more we are led to
    infer that the universal cause of it all is vastly different from

    mankind, and from anything of which we have empirical
    knowledge.

    And what do you have to say about the discoveries in
    anatomy, chemistry, botany?. . .

    Those surely are not objections, interrupted Cleanthes;
    they only reveal new instances of skill and contrivance. It
    is still the image of mind reflected on us from innumerable
    objects. Add, a mind like the human, said Philo. That’s the
    only kind I know, replied Cleanthes. And the more like the
    better, insisted Philo. To be sure, said Cleanthes.

    Now, Cleanthes, said Philo, pouncing with an air of
    triumph, note the consequences! •First, by this method
    of reasoning, you give up all claim to infinity in any of the
    attributes of God. For, as the cause ought to be proportioned
    to the effect, and the effect—so far as we know—is not
    infinite, what right have we (on your theory) to ascribe infinity
    to God? You will still have to say that when we remove him
    so far from similarity to human creatures, we give in to the
    most arbitrary hypothesis and at the same time weaken all
    proofs of his existence.

    •Secondly, your theory gives you no reason to ascribe
    perfection to God even in his capacity as a finite being, or
    to suppose him to be free from every error, mistake, or
    incoherence in his activities. Consider the many inexplicable
    difficulties in the works of nature—·illnesses, earthquakes,
    floods, volcanoes, and so on·. If we think we can prove a
    priori that the world has a perfect creator, all these calamities
    become unproblematic: we can say that they only seem to us
    to be difficulties because we with our limited intellects can’t
    follow all the infinitely complex details of which they are a
    part. But according to your line of argument these difficulties

    24

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 5

    are real; indeed they might be emphasized as new instances
    of the world’s likeness to the products of human skill and
    contrivance! You must, at least, admit that we with our
    limited knowledge can’t possibly tell whether this system con-
    tains any great faults, or deserves any considerable praise,
    when compared to other possible systems and perhaps even
    when compared to real ones. If the Aeneid were read to a
    peasant, could he judge it to absolutely faultless? Could
    he even give it proper place in a ranking of the products
    of human intelligence—he who had never seen any of the
    others?

    Even if this world were a perfect product, we still couldn’t
    be sure whether all the excellences of the work could justly
    be ascribed to the workman. When we survey a ship, we
    may get an exalted idea of the ingenuity of the carpenter
    who built such a complicated, useful, and beautiful machine.
    But then we shall be surprised to find that the carpenter
    is a stupid tradesman who imitated others, and followed
    a trade which has gradually improved down the centuries,
    after multiplied trials, mistakes, corrections, deliberations,
    and controversies. ·Perhaps our world is like that ship·.
    It may be that many worlds were botched and bungled,
    throughout an eternity, before our present system was built;
    much labour lost, many useless trials made, and a slow but
    continued improvement carried on during infinite ages in
    the world-making trade. In such subjects as this, who can
    •determine what is true—who indeed can even •guess what
    is probable—when so many hypotheses can be put forward,
    and even more can be imagined?

    And what shadow of an argument, continued Philo, can
    you produce, from your hypothesis, to prove that God is one
    being? A great many men join together to build a house or
    ship, to found and develop a city, to create a commonwealth;
    why couldn’t several gods combine in designing and making

    a world? This would only serve to make divine activities more
    like human ones. By sharing the work among several gods
    we can reduce still further the attributes of each one of them;
    we can get rid of the extensive power and knowledge that
    we have to suppose the one God to possess (if there is only
    one)—the extent of power and knowledge which, according
    to you, serves merely to weaken the argument for God’s
    existence. And if such foolish, vicious creatures as men can
    often unite in forming and carrying out one plan, think how
    much more could be done by those gods or semi-gods whom
    we may suppose to be quite a lot more perfect than we are!

    To multiply causes without necessity is indeed contrary
    to true philosophy; but that principle doesn’t apply to our
    present case. If your theory had already established that
    there is one God who had every attribute needed for the pro-
    duction of the universe, then, I admit, it would be needless
    (though not absurd) to suppose that any other god existed.
    But while we are still confronting the question:

    Are all these attributes united in one thing that has
    them all, or are they shared out among several inde-
    pendent beings?

    what phenomena in nature can we point to as supplying the
    answer? When we see a body raised in a scale, we are sure
    that in the opposite scale—even if we can’t see it—there is
    some counterbalancing weight equal to it; but we can still
    question whether that weight is •a heap of many distinct
    bodies, or rather •one uniform united mass; ·for example,
    whether it is •a handful of pebbles or •a single lump of
    lead·. And if the weight needed for the counterbalancing
    is very much greater than we have ever seen any single
    body to possess, •the former supposition becomes still more
    probable and natural ·than •the latter. As with weights,
    so with creators·. An intelligent being of such vast power
    and ability as is necessary to produce the universe—or, to

    25

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 5

    speak in the language of ancient philosophy, so prodigious
    an animal—goes beyond any analogy with ourselves, and
    indeed goes beyond what we can understand.

    Furthermore, Cleanthes: men are mortal, and renew their
    species by generation, and so do all living creatures. The
    two great sexes of male and female, says Milton, animate the
    world. Why shouldn’t this universal and essential feature of
    our condition also apply to those numerous and limited gods
    ·that I am saying you should argue for·? And that brings us
    back to the ancient tales about the birth of the gods.

    Indeed, why not become a perfect anthropomorphite?
    Why not assert that God is—or that each god is—corporeal,
    having eyes, a nose, mouth, ears, etc.? Epicurus maintained
    that no man has ever seen reason except in someone of
    human shape, and that therefore the gods must have that
    shape. This inference was deservedly ridiculed by Cicero,
    but by your standards it is solid and philosophical.

    In a word, Cleanthes, someone who follows your hypothe-
    sis can perhaps assert or conjecture that

    The universe at some time arose from something like
    design.

    But beyond that he can’t make a case for any further details,
    and is left to fill in his theology by wildly imagining or
    guessing the rest. For all he knows, the world is very faulty
    and imperfect by certain higher standards, ·which opens

    the doors to all sorts of ‘theologies’, no one of which he can
    refute. Here are just three of them·. This world was only
    •the first rough attempt of some infant god, who afterwards
    abandoned it, ashamed of his poor performance; it is •the
    work of some dependent, inferior god, whose superiors hold
    it up for ridicule; it was •produced by some god in his old
    age and near-senility, and ever since his death the world
    has continued without further guidance, activated by the
    first shove he gave to it and the active force that he built
    into it. You rightly give signs of horror, Demea, at these
    strange suppositions; but these—and a thousand more like
    them—are Cleanthes’ suppositions, not mine. As soon as
    the attributes of God are supposed to be finite, all these
    suppositions get a foot-hold. Speaking for myself, I can’t see
    that having such a wild and unsettled a system of theology
    is in any way preferable to having none at all—·that is, being
    an atheist·.

    I absolutely disown these suppositions! exclaimed Clean-
    thes; but they don’t fill me with horror, especially when put
    forward in the casual way in which you throw them off. On
    the contrary, they give me pleasure when I see that even
    when giving your imagination completely free rein, you don’t
    get rid of the hypothesis of design in the universe, but are
    obliged to rely on it at every turn. That concession is what I
    stick to, and I regard it as a sufficient foundation for religion.

    26

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 6

    Part 6

    It must be a flimsy building, said Demea, that can be
    erected on such a shaky foundation! While we are uncertain
    whether there is one god or many, whether God or the gods
    to whom we owe our existence are perfect or imperfect, sub-
    ordinate or supreme, dead or alive, what trust or confidence
    can we put in them? What devotion or worship can we
    offer them? What veneration or obedience give to them?
    This theory of religion becomes altogether useless for all the
    ·practical· purposes of life, and even when it is considered
    merely as a speculative theological theory, the uncertainty
    you attribute to it must render it totally precarious and
    unsatisfactory,

    To make it still more unsatisfactory, said Philo, I’ve
    thought of another hypothesis that must seem probable
    when evaluated in terms of the method of reasoning that
    Cleanthes insists on so much. He takes the basis for all
    religion to be this:

    Similar effects arise from similar causes.
    But there is another principle of the same kind, equally cer-
    tain and supported in the same way by experience. namely:

    Where several known circumstances are observed to
    be similar, the unknown will also be found similar.

    Example: if we see the limbs of a human body, we conclude
    that it is accompanied by a human head, even if we can’t see
    it. Second example: if we see a small part of the sun through
    a crack in a wall, we conclude that if the wall were removed
    we would see the whole sun, In short, this type of inference
    is so obvious and familiar that there can be no doubts as to
    its soundness.

    Now, if we survey the universe far as we know it, it bears
    a great resemblance to an animal or organic body, and seems

    to be driven by a source of life and motion like the one that
    drives organisms. •A continual circulation of matter in it
    produces no disorder; •a continual waste in every part is
    incessantly repaired; •the different parts of the whole system
    are seen to act in harmony with one another; and •each part
    ·of the world· or member ·of an organism·, in doing its proper
    job, operates both for its own preservation and for that of
    the whole. From all this I infer the the world is an animal,
    and that God is the MIND of the world, driving it and being
    affected by it.

    You have too much learning, Cleanthes, to be at all
    surprised by this opinion, which as you know was main-
    tained by almost all the theists of antiquity, and is the main
    theology that one finds in their discourses and reasonings.
    For though the ancient philosophers sometimes reason from
    final causes, ·pointing to evidence of purpose in the world·,
    as if they thought the world to be something God made, yet
    their favourite idea seems to have been that the world is
    God’s body, which is organized in such a way that it obeys
    his commands (·just as your body is so organized that—for
    example—when you decide to raise your arm it rises·). The
    universe is more like a human body than like the works of
    human skill and planning; so if it is ever appropriate to liken
    the whole of nature to any facts about us, with all our limits,
    it seems that the ancient analogy ·between the universe and
    our body· is sounder than the modern one ·between the
    universe and the things we make·.

    The former theory also has many other advantages that
    recommended it to the ancient theologians. ·Here is one
    important one·. Nothing clashed more with all their notions,
    because nothing clashes more with common experience, than

    27

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 6

    mind without body—the idea of a purely mental substance,
    which they didn’t understand and of which they hadn’t
    observed a single instance throughout all of nature. They
    knew mind and body because they felt both; they also knew
    an order, arrangement, organization, or internal machinery in
    both mind and body, again because they felt both; so it was
    bound to seem reasonable to transfer this experience ·of
    themselves· to the universe. That is to suppose that neither
    the divine mind nor the divine body came first, and that
    each of them has an order and arrangement that is naturally
    inherent in it and inseparable from it.

    So here is a new sort of anthropomorphism, Cleanthes,
    for you to think about; and it’s a theory that doesn’t seem
    to be open to any great difficulties. I’m sure you are above
    such theoretical prejudices as to find any more difficulty
    in supposing an animal body to be ordered and organized
    originally, of itself, or from unknown causes than in suppos-
    ing a mind to be ordered in that way. ·So you might think
    that likening the universe to an animal body doesn’t require
    supposing that is driven by a mind, a divine mind·. But
    the common prejudice that body and mind ought always to
    accompany each other ought not to be entirely neglected, for
    it is based on common experience, which is the only guide
    you claim to follow in all these theological enquiries. If you
    say that our limited experience is an inadequate standard by
    which to form opinions about the unlimited extent of nature,
    then you will be entirely abandoning your own hypothesis,
    and will have to adopt our mysticism (as you call it), and
    admit that God’s nature is absolutely incomprehensible,

    I admit, replied Cleanthes, that this theory had never
    before occurred to me, though it is a pretty natural one. I
    can’t give an opinion about it until I have had more time
    to think it over. You are very scrupulous indeed, said
    Philo—·more scrupulous than I am·: if you had presented

    me with a system of yours, I wouldn’t have been half as
    cautious and reserved in starting objections and difficulties
    to it. However, if anything does occur to you, please tell us.

    Why then, replied Cleanthes, it seems to me that though
    the world does in many ways resemble an animal body, this
    analogy is also defective in many important respects: •no
    organs of sense; •no seat of thought or reason; •no one
    precise origin of motion and action. In short, it seems to be
    more like a plant than an animal, and that weakens your
    inference to the mind of the world.

    Secondly, your theory seems to imply the eternity of
    the world; and that thesis, I believe, can be refuted by
    the strongest reasons and probabilities. I shall suggest an
    argument against it—one that I think hasn’t been insisted on
    by any writer. ·First, though, we should look at a different
    and less strong argument for the world’s having had a
    beginning·. It is argued that the arts and sciences came
    into existence only recently, ·and so the world’s past is fairly
    short·. This inference has some force, but perhaps it can be
    refuted—·or, rather, its premise can be undercut·—by a point
    concerning the nature of human society. We continually
    revolve between ignorance and knowledge, between liberty
    and slavery, between riches and poverty; so our limited
    experience doesn’t enable us to foretell with confidence what
    outcomes may or may not be expected. Ancient learning
    and history seem to have been in great danger of entirely
    perishing after the influx of the barbarous nations ·into the
    Roman empire·; and if these convulsions had continued a lit-
    tle longer, or been a little more violent, we would probably not
    have known now what happened in the world a few centuries
    ago. Indeed, the Latin language would have been utterly lost
    if it weren’t for the superstition of the Popes, who preserved a
    little Latin jargon so as to keep their church looking ancient
    and universal. With Latin lost, the western world would have

    28

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 6

    been totally barbarous, and so wouldn’t have been in a fit
    state to receive the Greek language and learning that came
    to them after the sacking of Constantinople. When learning
    and books had been extinguished, even the practical arts,
    skills, and trades would have fallen into considerable decay;
    and it is easy to imagine that in that case fable or tradition
    might ascribe to those arts a much later origin than they
    actually had. ·And so, by parity of argument, we are not
    entitled to confidence that we aren’t doing the same thing,
    because the records of vastly earlier arts and sciences have
    been wiped out·. This common argument against the eternity
    of the world, therefore, seems a little precarious.

    But here is what seems to be the basis for a better
    argument. Lucullus was the first person who brought
    cherry-trees from Asia to Europe; yet that tree thrives so
    well in many European climates that it grows in the woods
    without being cultivated. Is it possible that throughout a
    whole eternity no European ever visited Asia and thought of
    transplanting such a delicious fruit into his own country?
    If it was once transplanted and propagated ·before the time
    of Lucullus·, how could it ever afterwards perish? Empires
    may rise and fall, liberty and slavery succeed alternately,
    ignorance and knowledge give place to each other—but the
    cherry-tree will still remain in the woods of Greece, Spain,
    and Italy, and will never be affected by the revolutions of
    human society.

    It is less than two thousand years since vines were
    transplanted into France, though there is no climate in the
    world more favourable to them. It is less than three centuries
    since horses, cows, sheep, pigs, dogs, and corn were first
    known in America. Is it possible that during the revolutions
    of a whole eternity there never arose a Columbus who could
    put Europe into communication with that continent? We
    may as well imagine that all men would wear stockings for

    ten thousand years, and never have the sense to think of
    garters to tie them. All these seem convincing proofs that the
    world is young, indeed a mere infant; because the argument
    involving them is based on principles that are more constant
    and steady than those by which human society is governed
    and directed. It would take a total convulsion of the elements
    to destroy all the European animals and vegetables that are
    now to be found on the American continent.

    Well, what argument have you against such convulsions?
    replied Philo. Strong and almost incontestable evidence can
    be found over the whole earth that every part of this planet
    has for centuries been entirely covered with water. And even
    if order is inseparable from matter and inherent in it, still
    matter may be susceptible of many and great revolutions
    through the endless periods of eternal duration. We can see
    that in the changes and collapses of which we have had ex-
    perience the world has merely passed from one state of order
    to another; and matter can’t ever stay in a totally disordered
    and confused state. Still, the constant changes that occur in
    every part of the material world seem to suggest ·that· some
    such general transformations ·sometimes occur·. What we
    see in the parts we may infer in the whole—at any rate
    that’s the pattern of argument on which you rest your whole
    theory. And if I had to defend some particular system of this
    type (which I would never do willingly!), I find none of them
    more plausible than the theory that ascribes to the world
    an eternal inherent ordering force, though accompanied by
    great and continual revolutions and alterations. This at once
    solves all the difficulties; and if the solution is too lacking in
    detail to be entirely complete and satisfactory, it is at least
    a theory that we must eventually accept, whatever ·more
    detailed· system we embrace. How could things have been
    as they are if there were not an original inherent principle of
    order somewhere—in thought or in matter? It doesn’t matter

    29

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 7

    in the slightest which of these—·thought or matter·—we
    prefer. No hypothesis, whether sceptical or religious, should
    make room for chance; everything is surely governed by
    steady, inviolable laws. And if the inmost essence of things
    were laid open to us, we would then discover a scene of which
    at present we can have no idea. Instead of wondering at the
    order of natural things, we would see clearly that it was
    absolutely impossible for their ordering to be different—even
    in some tiny detail—from what it is in actuality.

    If anyone wanted to revive the ancient pagan theology
    which maintained, as we learn from Hesiod, that this planet
    was governed by 30,000 gods who arose from the unknown

    powers of nature, you would naturally object, Cleanthes, that
    nothing is gained by this hypothesis, and that it’s as easy
    to suppose all men and animals—more numerous, but less
    perfect—to have sprung immediately from a source of that
    kind. Push the same inference a step further and you will
    find that a large society of gods is no harder to explain than
    one universal God who contains within himself the powers
    and perfections of the whole society. So you must allow that
    all these systems—scepticism, polytheism, and theism—are
    on an equal footing when judged by your principles. That
    shows you that your principles are wrong.

    Part 7

    In thinking about the ancient system of ·God as· the mind
    of the world, Philo continued, I have just been struck by
    a new idea. If it is right, it comes close to subverting all
    your reasoning, and destroying even the first inferences in
    which you place such confidence. If the universe resembles
    •animal bodies and plants more than it does •the works of
    human skill, it is more probable that its cause resembles
    the cause of •the former than the cause of •the latter; so
    its origin ought to be ascribed to •generation or vegetation
    rather than to •reason or design. So your conclusion is lame
    and defective, even according to your own principles.

    Please expand this argument a little, said Demea, for I
    haven’t properly grasped it in the concise form in which you
    have expressed it.

    Our friend Cleanthes, replied Philo, as you have heard,
    asserts that since no question of fact can be answered except
    through experience, the existence of a God cannot be proved
    in any other way. The world, he says, resembles things made
    by human skill; so its cause must also resemble the cause
    of human artifacts. I note in passing that the operation of
    one very small part of nature, namely man, on another very
    small part, namely the inanimate matter lying within his
    reach, is the basis on which Cleanthes judges of the origin
    of the whole of nature; he measures the vast whole by the
    same individual standard as he does the tiny parts. But I
    shan’t press that point. ·If we are going to argue from parts
    to the whole, let us at least be careful about what parts we
    select for this special treatment·. I affirm that some parts of
    the universe other than the machines of human invention

    30

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 7

    are still more like the fabric of the world than machines are,
    and therefore point to a better conjecture about the origin of
    this whole system of the universe. These parts are animals
    and plants. The world plainly resembles an animal or a plant
    more than it does a watch or a knitting-loom. Its cause is
    therefore more likely to resemble the cause of the former
    ·than to resemble the cause of the latter·. The cause of the
    former is generation or vegetation. So we can conclude that
    the cause of the world is something similar or analogous to
    generation or vegetation.

    But how is it conceivable, said Demea, that the world
    can arise from anything similar to vegetation or generation?

    Very easily, replied Philo. ·Here is one way it could
    happen·. Just as a tree sheds its seeds into the neighbouring
    fields and produces other trees, so the great plant, the world
    or this planetary system, produces within itself certain seeds
    which it scatters into the surrounding chaos in which they
    grow into new worlds. A comet, for instance, is the •seed of a
    world; and after it has been fully ripened by passing from sun
    to sun and star to star, it is at last tossed into the unformed
    elements which everywhere surround this universe, and
    immediately sprouts up into a new system.

    Or we might suppose this world to be an animal. (There
    is no advantage in this, but let’s try it just for variety.) So:
    a comet is the •egg of this animal; and just as an ostrich
    lays its egg in the sand, where the egg hatches without any
    further care, and produces a new animal, so. . .

    I understand you, interrupted Demea, but what wild,
    arbitrary suppositions are these? What data have you for
    such extraordinary conclusions? Is the slight, imaginary
    resemblance of the world to a plant or an animal sufficient to
    support conclusions about the world based on what happens
    with plants or animals? Ought objects that are in general so
    widely different be taken as a standard for each other?

    Right! exclaimed Philo: that is what I have been insisting
    on all along. I have gone on asserting that we have no
    data to establish any system of cosmogony [= ‘theory, system,

    or story about the origin of the world’]. Our experience, which is
    so imperfect in itself and which covers such small stretches
    of space and time, can’t give us any probable conjecture
    concerning the whole of things. But if we have to settle
    for some hypothesis, tell me what rule we can use to make
    our choice. Is there any rule except ·the one that bases
    the greater acceptability of an hypothesis on· the greater
    similarity of the objects compared? And doesn’t a plant or
    an animal that arises from vegetation or generation resemble
    the world more closely than does any artificial machine that
    arises from reason and design?

    But what is this vegetation and generation of which you
    talk? said Demea. Can you explain how they work, and lay
    out the details of that fine internal structure on which they
    depend?

    I can do that, replied Philo, at least as well as Cleanthes
    can explain how reason works, or lay out in detail the
    internal structure on which it depends! But I don’t need
    to go into all that: it is enough that when I see an animal, I
    infer that it arose from generation, and am as sure of this as
    you are when you infer that a house arose from design. The
    words ‘generation’ and ‘reason’ serve merely to label certain
    powers and energies in nature. We know the effects of these
    powers, but have no grasp of their essence; and neither of
    them has a better claim that the other to be made a standard
    for the whole of nature.

    In fact, Demea, we can reasonably expect that the wider
    the range of facts that we take in, the better they will guide us
    in our conclusions about such extraordinary and magnificent
    subjects. In this little corner of the world alone, there are
    four principles [here = ‘driving forces’ or ‘sources of energy’]:

    31

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 7

    reason, instinct, generation, vegetation,
    that are similar to each other and are the causes of similar
    effects. How many other principles can we naturally suppose
    to be at work in the immense extent and variety of the
    universe—principles that we might discover if we could travel
    from planet to planet, and from system to system, so to
    examine each part of this mighty structure? Any one of the
    above four principles (and a hundred others which lie open
    ·if not to our senses, then at least· to our conjecture) can
    give us a theory about the origin of the world; and to confine
    our view entirely to the one of the four that governs how
    our own minds operate—·namely, reason·—is to be guilty of
    gross bias. If reason were more intelligible to us than the
    other three principles because it governs our minds, there
    would be some excuse for our bias in its favour; but ·that
    isn’t how things stand, because· the internal structure of
    reason is really as little known to us as are the structures of
    instinct and vegetation. Even that vague, indeterminate word
    ‘nature’, which common people drag in to explain everything,
    ·stands for something that· is basically no more inexplicable
    than reason. Our experience shows us the effects of these
    principles; but the principles themselves, and their ways of
    working, are totally unknown to us. To say:

    The world arose by vegetation from a seed shed by
    another world

    is not less intelligible, or less in harmony with experience,
    than to say:

    The world arose from a divine reason or plan,
    taking this in the sense in which Cleanthes understands it.

    But if the world did have a vegetative quality, said Demea,
    and could sow the seeds of new worlds into the infinite chaos,
    I would see this power as a further argument for design in
    its author. For where could such a wonderful power come
    from if not from design? How can order spring from anything

    which doesn’t perceive the order which it gives?
    You need only look around you, replied Philo, to get the

    answer to this question. A tree •gives order and organization
    to the tree that arises from it, without •knowing that order;
    similarly with an animal and its offspring, a bird and its
    nest. There are in the world more examples of this kind
    than there are instances of order arising from reason and
    planning. To say that all this order in animals and plants
    proceeds ultimately from design is to assume the very point
    that is at issue. The only way to settle the point ·in favour
    of design· would be to prove a priori both that •order is from
    its own nature inseparably attached to thought, and that
    •order is prevented from belonging to matter, either by its
    own nature or by some unknown basic principle.

    Furthermore, Demea, the objection you have just brought
    can’t be made by Cleanthes unless he gives up a defence
    that he used against one of my objections. When I asked
    about the cause of that supreme reason and intelligence
    from which he derives everything else, Cleanthes said this:

    The impossibility of answering such questions is never
    a legitimate objection in any kind of philosophy. We
    must stop somewhere; and ·wherever we stop, more
    questions can be raised, because· humans will never
    be able to explain ultimate causes, or to show the
    absolutely basic connections between things. All that
    should be demanded is that whatever steps we do
    take be supported by experience and observation.

    Now it can’t be denied that order in nature is found by
    experience to come from •vegetation and generation, as well
    as from •reason. It is for me to choose whether to base
    my system of cosmogony on •the former rather than on
    •the latter. The choice seems entirely arbitrary. And when
    Cleanthes asks me what the cause is of my vegetative or
    generative faculty, I am equally entitled to ask him what

    32

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 7

    causes his reasoning principle. We have agreed to pass up
    these questions on both sides, and in our present context
    it is in his interests to stick to this agreement. Judging by
    our limited and imperfect experience, generation has some
    privileges over reason: for we see every day reason arise
    from generation—·for example, my reason, which has in its
    causal ancestry my parent’s begetting of me·—but never see
    generation arise from reason.

    Please compare the consequences on both sides. •The
    world, I say, resembles an animal, so it is an animal, so it
    arose from generation. The steps in that argument are jumps,
    I admit, but each of them involves some small appearance
    of analogy ·between world and animal·. •The world, says
    Cleanthes, resembles a machine, so it is a machine, so it
    arose from design. These steps are jumps too, and here the
    analogy—·between world and machine·—is less striking. And
    if he claims to push one step further than my hypothesis, by
    inferring that design or reason caused the great principle of
    generation which I have emphasized, I have a better right
    to push one step further than his hypothesis, by inferring
    that a divine generation or god-birth caused his principle of
    reason. I have empirical evidence on my side, because reason
    is observed in countless cases to arise from generation, and
    never to arise from any other source. This is ·admittedly
    only· a faint shadow of evidence for my hypothesis, but on
    this topic faint shadows are the best we can do.

    The ancient mythologists were so struck with this analogy
    that they all explained the origin of nature in terms of birth
    and copulation. Plato too, so far as he is intelligible, seems
    to have adopted some such notion in his Timaeus.

    The Brahmins assert that the world arose from an in-
    finitely large spider who spun this whole complicated mass
    from his bowels, and then annihilates all or some of it by
    absorbing it again and taking it into his own essence. Here
    is a kind of cosmogony that strikes us as ridiculous because
    a spider is a negligible little animal whose doings we are
    never likely to take for a model of the whole universe. Still,
    even for us on our planet, this is a new kind of analogy ·for
    us to think about·. If there were (as there well might be)
    a planet wholly inhabited by spiders, this inference would
    seem there as natural and secure against criticism as the
    one that here ascribes the origin of all things to design and
    intelligence, as explained by Cleanthes. He will find it hard
    to give a satisfactory reason why an orderly system might
    not be spun from the belly as well as from the brain,

    I must say, Philo, replied Cleanthes, that the task you
    have undertaken, of raising doubts and objections, suits
    you better than it does anyone else alive; it seems in a way
    natural and unavoidable to you. You are so fertile in your
    inventions that I am not ashamed to admit that I can’t,
    straight off, solve in a disciplined way such out-of-the-way
    difficulties as you keep launching at me, though I can clearly
    see in a general way that they are wrong. I have no doubt that
    you are at present in the same position as I am, not having
    any solution as ready to hand as the objection. And you
    must be aware that common sense and reason are entirely
    against you, and that whimsical hypotheses like the ones
    you have produced may puzzle us but can never convince
    us.

    33

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

  • Part 8
  • Part 8

    What you ascribe to the fertility of my invention, replied
    Philo, comes purely from the nature of the subject. In topics
    that are suited to our limited human reason there is often
    only one view that carries probability or conviction with
    it; and to a man of sound judgment all other suppositions
    appear entirely absurd and fanciful. But in questions like
    our present one, a hundred mutually contradictory views
    can ·get some kind of support, because each· preserves a
    kind of imperfect analogy; so here, ·with all those contenders
    and no clear winner·, invention has full scope to exert itself.
    I believe that I could, in an instant and with no great effort
    of thought, propose still further systems of cosmogony that
    would have some faint appearance of truth, though the odds
    are a thousand—indeed a million—to one against any of
    them, or yours, being the true system.

    For instance, what if I should revive the old Epicurean
    hypothesis? This is commonly and I think rightly regarded as
    the most absurd system ever yet proposed; but I suspect that
    with a few alterations it might be given a faint appearance
    of probability. Instead of supposing matter to be infinite, as
    Epicurus did, let us suppose it to be finite ·and also suppose
    space to be finite, while still supposing time to be infinite·.
    A finite number of particles ·in a finite space· can have only
    a finite number of transpositions; and in an infinitely long
    period of time every possible order or position of particles
    must occur an infinite number of times. So this world, with
    all its events right down to the tiniest details, has already
    been produced and destroyed and will again be produced
    and destroyed an unlimited number of times. No-one who
    properly grasps the difference between infinite and finite will
    have any trouble with this conclusion.

    But this presupposes, said Demea, that matter can come
    to move without any voluntary agent or first mover [= ‘without

    any agent that causes the motion by willing or deciding that it shall

    occur’].
    And where’s the difficulty in that? replied Philo. •In

    advance of experience every outcome is as hard to credit and
    as incomprehensible as every other; and •after experience
    every outcome is as easy to believe and as intelligible as
    every other. Matter often starts to move through gravity,
    through elasticity, through electricity, without any known
    voluntary agent; and to suppose that in all these cases there
    is an unknown voluntary agent is merely to put forward an
    hypothesis—and one that has no advantages. That unaided
    matter should put itself into motion is as conceivable a priori
    as that it should be put into motion by mind and intelligence.

    Besides, why can’t motion have been passed from object
    to object by impact, and the same (or nearly the same) stock
    of it go on being maintained in the universe? The motion
    lost in one process is gained in the opposite process. [Hume

    wrote: ‘As much is lost by the composition of motion, as much is gained

    by its resolution.’] And whatever the causes of it are, the fact
    is certain that matter is and always has been in continual
    agitation, as far as human experience or tradition reaches.
    In the whole universe right now there is probably not one
    particle of matter at absolute rest.

    Philo went on: And this very consideration that we have
    stumbled on in the course of the argument suggests yet
    another hypothesis of cosmogony that isn’t entirely absurd
    and improbable. Is there a system, an order, an arrangement
    of things, through which matter can •preserve the perpetual
    agitation that seems essential to it and yet •maintain a

    34

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 8

    constancy in the forms it produces? [Philo may be using ‘form’

    to refer to any regularly ordered part of the physical world, but he is

    evidently thinking mainly of organisms, especially animals.] Yes, there
    certainly is such an arrangement, for this is actually the case
    with the present world ·in which •matter is constantly mov-
    ing, and yet •many forms and structures remain the same·.
    If matter moves continually and has only a finite number
    of orderings into which it can fall ·assuming that matter
    and space are both finite·, it must ·eventually· produce this
    arrangement or order that the world actually has; and by its
    very nature this order once it is established supports itself
    for many ages, if not to eternity. But wherever matter is
    poised, arranged, and adjusted in such a way as to continue
    in perpetual motion and yet preserve a constancy in the
    forms, the state of affairs is bound to have the very same
    appearance of planning and skill that we observe at present.
    •Every part of each form must be related to each other part
    of it and to the whole form; and the whole form itself must
    be related to the other parts of the universe—•to the element
    in which the form subsists, •to the materials with which it
    repairs its waste and decay, •and to every other form which
    is hostile or friendly towards it. A defect in any of those
    respects—·as when •arteries fail to carry blood to the brain,
    or •a trout becomes unable to get oxygen out of the water
    it swims in, or •a heron becomes unable to escape hawks
    or to capture fish·—destroys the form; and the matter of
    which it is composed is again set loose, and is thrown into
    irregular motions and fermentations until it unites itself
    to some other regular form, ·for example by being eaten·.
    If no such form is prepared to receive it, and if there is a
    great quantity of this corrupted matter in the universe, the
    universe itself comes to be entirely disordered; and this holds
    true whether what is destroyed is •the feeble embryo of a
    world in its first beginnings or •the rotten carcass of a world

    drifting into old age and infirmity. In either case a chaos
    ensues, until through countlessly (though not infinitely)
    many re-arrangements there come to be, yet again, some
    forms whose parts and organs are so adjusted that they
    enable the forms to stay in existence while the matter in
    them continually changes.

    I shall try to put all this differently. Suppose that matter
    is thrown into some position by a blind, unguided force. It
    is obvious that this first position must in all probability be
    utterly confused and disorderly, with no resemblance to the
    human artifacts which display, along with a symmetry of
    parts, an adjustment of means to ends, and a tendency to
    self-preservation. If the ·original· actuating force ceases after
    this first operation ·and stops imparting motion to matter·,
    matter will have to remain for ever in disorder, and continue
    to be an immense chaos without any proportion or activity.
    But suppose that the actuating force (whatever it may be)
    still continues to drive matter along, this first position will
    immediately give place to a second, which will likewise in all
    probability be as disorderly as the first, and so on through
    many series of changes and revolutions. No particular order
    or position ever stays unaltered for a moment. The original
    force, still at work, gives a perpetual restlessness to matter.
    Every possible state of affairs is produced, and instantly
    destroyed. If a glimpse or dawn of order appears for a
    moment, it is instantly hurried away, reduced to a confusion,
    by that never-ceasing force which drives every part of the
    material world.

    Thus the universe goes on for many ages in a continuous
    series of states of chaos and disorder. But couldn’t it happen
    that it eventually settles down, not so as to lose its motion
    and active force (for we are assuming that that is inherent in
    it), but so as to preserve a uniformity of appearance through
    all the hubbub of its moving parts? This is what we find

    35

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 8

    to be the actual state of the universe at present. Every
    individual is perpetually changing, and so is every part of
    every individual; and yet the whole appears to be the same.
    ·A tiny example: a rabbit takes in pure air and breathes
    out foul air, it drinks water and emits urine, it eats grass
    and extrudes faeces; and yet through all this change in
    its constituent matter it appears to us as the very same
    rabbit·. Isn’t this state of affairs one that might be hoped
    for—indeed, one that would be sure to arise—out of the
    eternal revolutions of unguided matter; and couldn’t this
    account for all the appearances of wisdom and planning
    that the universe contains? Think about this a little and
    you’ll find that if matter did arrive at this set-up, in which
    forms seem to be stable while their parts are really moving
    and changing with them, that would provide a plausible and
    perhaps a true solution of the problem ·of explaining the
    appearance of design in the universe·.

    So it’s pointless to stress the uses of the parts in animals
    or plants, and their intricate interplay between the parts. I’d
    like to know how an animal could survive if its parts were
    not so inter-related! When an animal’s parts lose those inter-
    relations, don’t we find that it immediately dies and that its
    decaying flesh and blood try some new form? It happens
    indeed that the parts of the world are so well adjusted to
    one another that some regular form immediately lays claim
    to this decaying matter; if that didn’t happen, could the
    ·biological· world continue to exist? Wouldn’t it die along
    with the ·individual· animal, and ·its constituent matter· go
    through new positions and relationships, until—after a vast
    but finite series of changes—it falls at last into an order such
    as the one we actually have?

    It is just as well, replied Cleanthes, that you told us that
    this hypothesis came to you suddenly in the course of the
    argument. If you had taken the time to examine it, you

    would soon have seen the insuperable objections that it is
    open to. You say that no form can survive unless it has
    the powers and organs needed for survival; some new order
    or arrangement must be tried, ·and another, and another·,
    and so on without interruption until at last some order
    that can support and maintain itself happens to come into
    existence. But according to this hypothesis, what brings
    about the many conveniences and advantages that men and
    all animals have? •Two eyes, two ears, aren’t absolutely
    necessary for the survival of the species. •The human race
    could have existed and continued without there being any
    horses, dogs, cows, sheep, and those innumerable fruits
    and products which bring us satisfaction and enjoyment.
    •If no camels had been created for the use of man in the
    sandy deserts of Africa and Arabia, would the world have
    been dissolved? •If no magnet had been formed so as to give
    that wonderful and useful direction to the compass-needle,
    would human society and the human species have been
    immediately extinguished? The rules by which nature works
    are in general far from lavish, but still instances of this kind
    are far from being rare; and any one of them is a sufficient
    proof that a design—a benevolent design—gave rise to the
    order and arrangement of the universe.

    At least you can safely conclude, said Philo, that the
    hypothesis I put forward is not yet complete and perfect;
    and I readily admit that. But can we ever reasonably expect
    greater success in any attempts of this nature? Can we ever
    hope to construct a system of cosmogony that will be free
    of exceptions and in no way conflict with our limited and
    imperfect experience of the analogy of nature? Your own
    theory surely can’t claim to be as good as that, even though
    you have embraced anthropomorphism so as to improve the
    theory’s conformity to common experience. Let us try it out
    yet again. •In all instances that we have ever encountered,

    36

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 8

    ideas are copied from real objects. You reverse this order,
    and make thought come first. •In all instances that we have
    ever encountered, thought has no influence on matter except
    where that matter is so conjoined with thought as to have an
    equal reciprocal influence on it. All that an animal can move
    immediately are parts of its own body ·and the condition of
    those can in return affect the animal’s mental states·; and
    indeed, the equality of action and reaction seems to be a
    universal law of nature. Your theory implies a contradiction
    to this experience. It would be easy to assemble plenty more
    such difficulties, especially in the supposition of a mind or
    system of thought that is eternal, in other words an animal
    that was never born and will never die. These instances can
    teach us all to be moderate in our criticisms of each other,
    and let us see that just as •no system of this kind ought
    ever to be accepted on the basis of a slight analogy, so •none
    should be rejected on account of a small incongruity. For
    that is a drawback from which, we can reasonably hold, no

    system of cosmogony is exempt.
    Every religious system is held ·by many people· to be

    subject to great and insuperable difficulties. Each disputant
    has his period of triumph while he carries on an offensive
    war, and exposes the absurdities, barbarities, and pernicious
    doctrines of his antagonist. But religious systems taken all
    together provide the sceptic with a complete ·and permanent·
    triumph; for he tells the disputants that •no system of
    cosmogony ought ever to be accepted, for the simple reason
    that •no system of anything ought ever to be accepted if it
    is absurd. A total suspension of judgment is here our only
    reasonable resource. And given that we commonly see that
    among theologians every attack succeeds and every defence
    fails, how complete a victory must come to someone who
    remains always on the offensive against all mankind, and
    has himself no fixed position or abiding city that he is ever
    obliged to defend?

    37

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

    Part 9

    Part 9

    But if there are so many difficulties in the a posteriori
    argument, said Demea, hadn’t we better stay with the simple
    and sublime a priori argument which cuts off all doubt and
    difficulty with a single blow, by offering to us an infallible
    knock-down proof? Furthermore, this argument lets us
    prove •the infinity of God’s attributes—·that he is infinitely
    wise, infinitely good, infinitely powerful, and so on·—which,
    I am afraid, can never be established with certainty in any
    other manner. For how can an infinite cause be inferred
    from an effect that is finite, or that may be finite for all we
    know to the contrary? •The unity of God’s nature, also, is
    very hard—if not absolutely impossible—to infer merely from
    observing the works of nature; even if it is granted that the
    plan of the universe is all of a piece, that isn’t enough to
    ensure us of God’s unity. Whereas the a priori argument. . .

    Cleanthes interrupted: You seem to reason, Demea, as
    if those advantages and conveniences in the abstract ·a
    priori· argument were full proofs of its soundness. But in
    my opinion we should first settle what argument with all
    these advantages you choose to insist on; and then we can
    try to decide what value to put on it—doing this better by
    looking at the argument itself than by considering its useful
    consequences.

    The argument that I would insist on, replied Demea,
    is the common one: Whatever exists must have a cause
    or reason for its existence, as it is absolutely impossible
    for anything to produce itself, or be the cause of its own
    existence. In working back, therefore, from effects to causes,
    we must either (1) go on tracing causes to infinity, without
    any ultimate cause at all, or (2) at last have recourse to some
    ultimate cause that is necessarily existent ·and therefore

    doesn’t need an external cause·. Supposition (1) is absurd,
    as I now prove:

    In the ·supposed· infinite chain or series of causes and
    effects, each single effect is made to exist by the power
    and efficacy of the cause that immediately preceded it;
    but the whole eternal chain or series, considered as a
    whole, is not caused by anything; and yet it obviously
    requires a cause or reason, as much as any particular
    thing that begins to exist in time. We are entitled
    to ask why this particular series of causes existed
    from eternity, and not some other series, or no series
    at all. If there is no necessarily existent being, all
    the suppositions we can make about this are equally
    possible; and there is no more absurdity in •nothing’s
    having existed from eternity than there is in •the series
    of causes that constitutes the universe. What was it,
    then, that made something exist rather than nothing,
    and gave existence to one particular possibility as
    against any of the others? •External causes? We are
    supposing that there aren’t any. •Chance? That’s a
    word without a meaning. Was it •Nothing? But that
    can never produce anything.

    So we must ·adopt supposition (2), and· have recourse to
    a necessarily existent being, who carries the reason of his
    existence in himself and cannot be supposed not to exist
    without an express contradiction. So there is such a being;
    that is, there is a God.

    I know that Philo loves raising objections, said Cleanthes,
    but I shan’t leave it to him to point out the weakness of your
    metaphysical reasoning. Your argument seems to me so
    obviously ill-grounded, and ·even if it succeeded· to offer so

    38

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 9

    little help to the cause of true piety and religion, that I shall
    myself venture to show what is wrong with it.

    I start by remarking that there is an evident absurdity
    in claiming to demonstrate—or to prove by any a priori
    arguments—any matter of fact.

    •Nothing is demonstrable unless its contrary implies a
    contradiction.

    •Nothing that is distinctly conceivable implies a contra-
    diction.

    •Whatever we conceive as existent, we can also con-
    ceive as non-existent.

    •So there is no being whose non-existence implies a
    contradiction.

    •So there is no being whose existence is demonstrable.
    I offer this argument as entirely decisive, and am willing to
    rest the whole controversy on it.

    You claim that God is a necessarily existent being; and the
    friends of your line of argument try to explain this necessity
    of his existence by saying that if we knew his whole essence
    or nature, we would perceive it to be as impossible for •him
    not to exist as for •twice two not to be four. But obviously
    this can never happen, while our faculties remain the same
    as they are now. It will always be possible for us at any
    time to conceive the non-existence of something we formerly
    conceived to exist; the mind can never have to suppose some
    object to remain always in existence, in the way in which we
    always have to conceive twice two to be four. So the words
    ‘necessary existence’ have no meaning—or (the same thing)
    no meaning that is consistent.

    Furthermore, if we do go along with this claimed expla-
    nation of necessary existence, why shouldn’t the material
    universe be the necessarily existent being? We dare not
    claim to know all the qualities of matter; and for all we
    can tell, matter may have some qualities which, if we knew

    them, would make •matter’s non-existence appear as great
    a contradiction as •twice two’s being five. I have found only
    one argument trying to prove that the material world is not
    the necessarily existent being; and this argument is derived
    from the contingency both of the matter and the form of the
    world. ‘Any particle of matter’, Dr Clarke has said, ‘can be
    conceived to be annihilated; and any form can be conceived
    to be altered. Such an annihilation or alteration, therefore,
    is not impossible.’ But it seems very biased not to see that
    the same argument applies just as well to God, so far as we
    have any conception of him; and that our mind can at least
    imagine God to be non-existent or his attributes to be altered.
    If something is to make his non-existence appear impossible,
    or his attributes unalterable, it must be some qualities of his
    that we don’t know and can’t conceive; but then no reason
    can be given why these qualities may not belong to matter.
    As they are altogether unknown and inconceivable, they can
    never be proved incompatible with ·the nature of matter as
    we know· it.

    A further objection: in tracing an eternal series of items, it
    seems absurd to ask for a general cause or first author ·of the
    entire series·. How can something that exists from eternity
    have a cause, since the causal relation implies •priority in
    time and •a beginning of existence?

    Also: in such a chain or series of items, each part is
    caused by the part that preceded it, and causes the one that
    follows. So where is the difficulty? But the whole needs a
    cause! you say. I answer that the uniting of these parts into
    a whole, like the uniting of several distinct counties into one
    kingdom, or several distinct members into one organic body,
    is performed merely by an arbitrary act of the mind and has
    no influence on the nature of things. If I showed you the
    particular causes of each individual in a collection of twenty
    particles of matter, I would think it very unreasonable if you

    39

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

  • Part 10
  • then asked me what was the cause of the whole twenty. The
    cause of the whole is sufficiently explained by explaining the
    cause of the parts.

    Your reasonings, Cleanthes, may well excuse me from
    raising any further difficulties, said Philo, but I can’t resist
    bringing up another point. Arithmeticians have noted that
    every product of 9 has integers which add up to 9 or to some
    lesser product of 9. Thus, of 18, 27, and 36, which are
    products of 9, you make 9 by adding 1 to 8, 2 to 7, and
    3 to 6. Thus, 369 is a product also of 9; and if you add
    3, 6, and 9, you make 18, which is a lesser product of 9.
    To a superficial observer this splendid regularity may be
    wondered at as the effect either of •chance or •design; but a
    skillful algebraist immediately concludes it to be the work of
    •necessity, and demonstrates that it must forever result from
    the nature of these numbers. Isn’t it probable, I now ask,
    that the whole way the universe works depends on this sort
    of necessity, though no human algebra can provide a key
    that solves the difficulty? Instead of wondering at the order
    of natural beings, mightn’t it be that if we could penetrate
    into the intimate nature of bodies we would clearly see why
    it was absolutely impossible for them to be inter-related in

    any other way? So you run a great risk when you introduce
    this idea of necessity into the present question, because it
    naturally supports an inference that is directly opposite to
    the religious hypothesis!

    Anyway, continued Philo, dropping all these abstractions
    and staying with more familiar topics, I venture to remark
    that the a priori argument has seldom been found very
    convincing, except to people with metaphysical minds, who
    have accustomed themselves to abstract reasoning and who
    ·have developed bad intellectual habits, because·, finding
    in mathematics that the understanding frequently leads
    through darkness to truths that at first didn’t appear to be
    true, they have transferred the same habit of thinking to
    subjects where it isn’t appropriate. Other people, even ones
    who have good sense and strong inclinations in favour of
    religion, always feel that there is something wrong with such
    arguments ·as the a priori argument for the existence of
    God·, even though they may not be able to explain distinctly
    what the defect is; which is a certain proof that men always
    did and always will derive their religion from sources other
    than this sort of reasoning.

    Part 10

    It is my opinion, I admit, replied Demea, that each man
    somehow feels in his heart the truth of religion, and that
    what leads him to seek protection from ·God·, the being
    on whom he and all nature depend, is not any reasoning
    but rather his consciousness of his own weakness and

    misery. Even the best scenes of life are so troubling or so
    unpleasant that all our hopes and fears look to the future. We
    incessantly look forward, and try through prayers, adoration
    and sacrifice to appease those unknown powers who, we
    find by experience, can so thoroughly afflict and oppress

    40

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 10

    us. Wretched creatures that we are! What help would there
    be for us amid the innumerable ills of life if religion didn’t
    suggest some ways of reconciling ourselves with God and
    soothe the terrors with which we are incessantly agitated
    and tormented?

    I am indeed convinced, said Philo, that the best and
    indeed the only method of bringing everyone to a proper
    sense of religion is by making them see clearly the misery
    and wickedness of men. And for that purpose a talent for
    eloquence and strong imagery is more needed than a talent
    for reasoning and argument. What need is there to prove
    something that everyone feels within himself? It is only
    necessary to make us feel it, if possible, more strongly and
    intimately.

    Indeed, replied Demea, the people are sufficiently con-
    vinced of this great and melancholy truth. These phrases:

    the miseries of life
    the unhappiness of man
    the general corruptions of our nature
    the unsatisfactory enjoyment of pleasures, riches,
    honours

    have become almost proverbial in all languages. And who
    can doubt something that all men declare from their own
    immediate feeling and experience?

    On this point, said Philo, the learned are in perfect agree-
    ment with the common people; and in all literature, religious
    and otherwise, the topic of human misery has been stressed
    with the most pathetic eloquence that sorrow and melancholy
    could inspire. The works of the poets—whose testimony has
    extra authority because they speak from feeling, without a
    system—abound in images of this sort. From Homer down to
    Dr. Edward Young, the whole inspired tribe ·of poets· have

    always been aware that if they are to present human life in
    a way that fits what each individual person sees and feels it
    as being like, they will have to represent it in that way.

    As for authorities, replied Demea, you needn’t hunt for
    them. Look around this library of Cleanthes. I venture to
    guess that—except for authors of particular sciences such
    as chemistry or botany, who have no occasion to treat of
    human life—almost every one of those innumerable writers
    has, somewhere or other, been led by his sense of human
    misery to testify to it and complain of it. At any rate, the
    odds are that almost all of them have written in that way;
    and as far as I can remember no author has gone to the
    opposite extreme of denying human misery.

    There you must excuse me, said Philo: Leibniz has denied
    it. He is perhaps the first who ventured on such a bold
    and paradoxical opinion; or, anyway, the first who made it
    essential to his philosophical system.1

    Given that he was the first, replied Demea, mightn’t that
    very fact have made him realize that he was wrong? For
    is this a subject on which philosophers can claim to make
    discoveries, especially as late in history as this? And can
    any man hope by a simple denial to outweigh the united
    testimony of mankind, based on sense and consciousness?
    (I say ‘a simple denial’ because the subject scarcely admits
    of reasoning.)

    And, he added, why should man claim to be exempt from
    the fate of all the other animals? The whole earth, believe
    me, Philo, is cursed and polluted. A perpetual war goes on
    among all living creatures. Need, hunger, and deprivation
    stimulate the strong and courageous; fear, anxiety and terror
    agitate the weak and infirm. •The first entrance into life
    brings distress to the new-born infant and to its wretched

    1 It was maintained by Dr. King and a few others, before Leibniz, but not by any as famous as that German philosopher.

    41

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 10

    mother; •weakness, impotence and distress accompany each
    stage of that life: and •eventually it reaches its end in agony
    and horror.

    Observe too, says Philo, nature’s intricate devices for
    embittering the life of every living being. The stronger ones
    prey on the weaker, and keep them in perpetual terror and
    anxiety. The weaker, in their turn, often prey on the stronger,
    and vex and trouble them, giving them no respite. Think of
    the innumerable race of insects that either are bred on the
    body of an animal or, flying about, put their stings into him
    These insects are themselves tormented by others that are
    even smaller. And thus on every hand, before and behind,
    above and below, every animal is surrounded by enemies
    that constantly seek his misery and destruction.

    Man alone, said Demea, seems to be a partial exception
    to this rule. For by coming together in society men can easily
    master lions, tigers, and bears, whose greater strength and
    agility naturally enable them to prey on him.

    On the contrary, exclaimed Philo, it is just here that
    we can most clearly see how uniform and equal nature’s
    maxims are! It is true that man can by combining surmount
    all his real enemies and become master of the whole animal
    kingdom; but doesn’t he immediately conjure up imaginary
    enemies, the demons of his imagination, who haunt him
    with superstitious terrors and blast every enjoyment of life?
    He imagines that they see his pleasure as a crime, and that
    his food and leisure annoy and offend them. Even his sleep
    and dreams bring him new materials for anxious fear; and
    death, his refuge from every other ill, presents only the dread
    of endless and innumerable woes. The wolf’s attack on the
    timid flock is no worse than what superstition does to the
    anxious feelings of wretched mortals.

    Besides, Demea, think about this very society through
    which we get the upper hand over those wild beasts, our

    natural enemies: what new enemies it raises against us!
    What woe and misery it causes! Man is the greatest enemy of
    man. Oppression, injustice, contempt, disrespect, violence,
    sedition, war, slander, treachery, fraud—men use these to
    torment one another, and they would soon dissolve the
    society they had formed if they weren’t afraid that even
    greater ills would come from their doing so.

    These external injuries, said Demea, that we suffer from
    animals, from men, and from all the elements, do indeed
    form a frightful catalogue of woes; but they are nothing in
    comparison to the ones that arise within ourselves from the
    illnesses of our mind and body. How many people lie under
    the lingering torment of diseases? Hear the pathetic list of
    the great poet.

    Intestine stone and ulcer, colic-pangs,
    Demoniac frenzy, moping melancholy,
    And moon-struck madness, pining atrophy,
    Marasmus, and wide-wasting pestilence.
    Dire was the tossing, deep the groans: DESPAIR
    Tended the sick, busiest from couch to couch.
    And over them triumphant DEATH his dart
    Shook: but delay’d to strike, though oft invok’d
    With vows, as their chief good and final hope.

    (Milton, Paradise Lost 11)
    The disorders of the mind, continued Demea, though

    they are more secret may be no less dismal and vexatious.
    Remorse, shame, anguish, rage, disappointment, anxiety,
    fear, dejection, despair; who has ever passed through life
    without cruel attacks from these tormentors? Many people
    have scarcely ever felt any better sensations than those!
    Labour and poverty, so hated by everyone, are the certain
    fate of the majority, and the privileged few who enjoy leisure
    and wealth never reach contentment or true happiness. All

    42

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 10

    the goods of life put together would not make a very happy
    man; but all the ills together would make a wretch indeed!
    Life can indeed be made unsatisfactory by almost any one of
    the ills (and who can be free from every one?), or indeed by
    the lack of any one good (and who can possess all?).

    If an alien suddenly arrived in this world, I would show
    him, as a specimen of its ills, a hospital full of diseases, a
    prison crowded with criminals and debtors, a field of battle
    with corpses all over it, a fleet of ships sinking in the ocean,
    a nation suffering under tyranny, famine, or plague. To turn
    the cheerful side of life to him and give him a notion of its
    pleasures, where should I take him? to a ball, to an opera,
    to court? He might reasonably think that I was only showing
    him other kinds of distress and sorrow.

    There is no way to escape such striking instances, said
    Philo, except by explaining them away—and that makes
    the indictment even more severe. Why, I ask, have all men
    in all ages complained incessantly of the miseries of life?
    Someone replies: ‘They have no good reason: they complain
    only because they are disposed to be discontented, regretful,
    anxious.’ I reply: what greater guarantee of misery could
    there be than to have such a wretched temperament?

    ‘But if they were really as unhappy as they claim,’ says
    my antagonist, ‘why do they stay alive?’

    Not satisfied with life, afraid of death. [Milton, Paradise

    Lost 11]
    This is the secret chain that holds us, I reply. We are terrified,
    not bribed, into continuing our existence.

    ‘It is only a false delicacy’, he may insist, ‘which a few
    refined spirits permit themselves, and which has spread
    these complaints among the whole race of mankind.’ And
    what is this delicacy, I ask, which you blame? Isn’t it just
    a greater awareness of all the pleasures and pains of life?
    And if the man of a delicate, refined cast of mind, by being

    so much more •alive than the rest of the world, is only made
    so much more •unhappy, what conclusion should we reach
    about human life in general?

    ‘If men remained at rest,’ says our adversary, ‘they would
    be at ease. ·Through all their busy, ambitious activity· they
    are willing makers of their own misery.’ No! I reply: leisure
    makes them anxious and slack. ·Not that it would do any
    good for them to give up leisure, for· activity and ambition
    bring disappointment, vexation, and trouble.

    I can see something like what you describe in some others,
    replied Cleanthes: but I confess that I feel little or nothing
    of it in myself, and I hope it isn’t as common as you make it
    out to be.

    If you don’t feel human misery yourself, exclaimed De-
    mea, I congratulate you on your happy uniqueness! Others,
    seemingly the most prosperous, haven’t been ashamed to
    give voice to their complaints in the saddest tones. Let us
    attend to the great, the fortunate emperor Charles V when,
    tired with human grandeur, he resigned all his extensive
    dominions into the hands of his son. In the last speech
    he made on that memorable occasion, he publicly testified
    that the greatest prosperities he had ever enjoyed had been
    mixed with so many adversities that he could truly say that
    he had never enjoyed any satisfaction or contentment. But
    did the retired life in which he hoped to shelter give him any
    greater happiness? If we can believe his son’s account, he
    started to regret his abdication on the very day he abdicated.

    Cicero’s fortune rose from small beginnings to the greatest
    glory and fame; yet his letters to friends as well as his
    philosophical discourses contain ever so many pathetic
    complaints about the ills of life. And suitably to his own
    experience, he introduces Cato—the great, the fortunate
    Cato—protesting in his old age that if a new life were his for
    the asking, he would turn it down.

    43

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 10

    Ask yourself, ask anyone you know, whether they would
    be willing to live over again the last ten or twenty years
    of their lives. No! but the next twenty, they say, will be
    better. . . . Human misery is so great that it reconciles
    even contradictions! And so people eventually come to
    complain about the shortness of life and, in the same breath,
    complaining of its pointlessness and sorrow.

    And is it possible, Cleanthes, said Philo, that after all
    these reflections, and countless others that might be sug-
    gested, you still stick to your anthropomorphism, and assert
    that the moral attributes of God—his justice, benevolence,
    mercy, and uprightness—are of the same nature as these
    virtues in human creatures? We grant that •his power is
    infinite: whatever he wills to happen does happen. But
    neither man nor any other animal is happy; therefore God
    doesn’t will their happiness. His •knowledge is infinite: he
    is never mistaken in his choice of means to any end. But
    the course of nature doesn’t lead to human or animal hap-
    piness; therefore nature isn’t established for that purpose.
    Through the whole range of human knowledge, there are no
    inferences more certain and infallible than these. Well, then,
    in what respect do his benevolence and mercy resemble the
    benevolence and mercy of men?

    Epicurus’s old questions have still not been answered. •Is
    he willing to prevent evil, but not able? then he is impotent.
    •Is he able, but not willing? then he is malevolent. •Is he
    both able and willing? then where does evil come from? [In
    this work, as in all writings on the ‘problem of evil’, the topic is the entire

    range of bad states of affairs, including every kind of suffering; it is not

    confined to the extreme moral badness that ‘evil’ stands for today.]
    You ascribe a purpose and intention to nature, Cleanthes,

    and I think you are right about that. But what, I ask you,
    is the aim of all the intricately designed machinery that
    nature has displayed in all animals? ·Here is my answer

    to that·. The aim is simply the preservation of individuals,
    and the continuance of the species. It seems enough for
    nature’s purpose if the species is merely enabled to stay in
    existence, without any care or concern for the happiness of
    its individual members. No means for this are provided, no
    machinery aimed purely at giving pleasure or ease, no store
    of pure joy and contentment, no gratification without some
    lack or need to go with it. ·Or perhaps not quite none, but·
    at least the few phenomena of this nature are outweighed by
    opposite phenomena of greater importance.

    Our sense of music, harmony, and indeed beauty of all
    kinds gives satisfaction without being absolutely necessary to
    the preservation and propagation of the species. But contrast
    that with the racking pains that arise from gouts, gravels,
    migraines, toothaches, rheumatisms, where the injury to
    the animal machinery is either small ·so that no pain-signal
    is needed· or incurable ·so that no pain-signal is useful·.
    Joy, laughter, play, frolic, seem to be gratuitous satisfactions
    that don’t lead to anything further; and spleen, melancholy,
    discontent, superstition, are pains that also lead nowhere.
    How then does God’s benevolence display itself according to
    you anthropomorphites? It is only we ‘mystics’ (as you were
    pleased to call us) who can account for this strange mixture
    of phenomena, by deriving it from divine attributes that are
    infinitely perfect but incomprehensible.

    At last, Philo, said Cleanthes with a smile, you have let
    us see what you have been up to! Your long agreement with
    Demea surprised me a little, but now I see that all along
    you were preparing to train your guns on me. And I must
    admit that you have now come to a subject that is worthy
    of your notable spirit of opposition and controversy. If you
    can make good on your present point, and prove mankind
    to be unhappy or corrupted, there is an immediate end to
    all religion. For what is the point of establishing the natural

    44

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 10

    attributes of God while his moral attributes are still doubtful
    and uncertain?

    You’re very quick to object, replied Demea, to innocent
    opinions that are the most widely accepted, even among
    religious and devout people. I’m immensely surprised to
    find this theme of the wickedness and misery of man being
    charged with, of all things, atheism and profaneness. Haven’t
    all pious divines and preachers who have lavished their
    rhetoric on this rich topic given a solution for any difficulties
    that may come with it? This world is a mere point in
    comparison with the universe; this life is a mere moment
    in comparison with eternity. The present evil phenomena,
    therefore, are set right in other regions and at some future
    time. And ·when that happens· the eyes of men, being
    then opened to broader views of things, ·will· see the whole
    connection of general laws, and with admiring wonder trace
    God’s benevolence and justice through all the mazes and
    intricacies of his providence.

    No! replied Cleanthes, No! These arbitrary suppositions
    can never be admitted; they are contrary to visible and
    unchallenged facts. How can any cause be known except
    from its known effects? How can any hypothesis be proved
    except from the experienced phenomena? To base one
    hypothesis on another is to build entirely in the air; and
    the most we ever achieve through these conjectures and
    fictions is to show that our opinion is possible; we can never
    in this way establish that it is true.

    The only way to support divine benevolence—and it is
    what I willingly accept—is to deny absolutely the misery and
    wickedness of man. Your pictures ·of the human condition·
    are exaggerated; your melancholy views are mostly fictitious;
    your conclusions are contrary to fact and experience. Health
    is more common than sickness; pleasure than pain; happi-
    ness than misery. I calculate that for each vexation that we

    meet with we get a hundred enjoyments.
    Your position is extremely doubtful, replied Philo, but

    even if we allow it you must at the same time admit that
    if pain is •less frequent than pleasure it is infinitely •more
    violent and lasting. One hour of pain is often able to outweigh
    a day, a week, a month of our ordinary tepid enjoyments;
    and some people pass days, weeks, and months in the most
    acute torments! Pleasure hardly ever rises to the height of
    ecstasy and rapture; and it can never continue for any time
    at its highest pitch and altitude. The spirits evaporate, the
    nerves relax, the body is out of order, and the enjoyment
    quickly degenerates into fatigue and uneasiness. But pain
    often—good God, how often!—rises to torture and agony;
    and the longer it continues the more thoroughly it becomes
    genuine agony and torture. Patience is exhausted, courage
    fades, melancholy seizes us, and nothing puts an end to
    our misery except the removal of its cause—or another
    event that is the sole cure of all evil though our natural
    foolishness leads us to regard it with still greater horror and
    consternation.

    All this is obvious, certain, and important, continued
    Philo, but I shan’t go on about it. I do take the opportunity
    to warn you, Cleanthes, that you have taken your stand
    on most dangerous ground, and without realizing it have
    introduced a total scepticism into the most essential articles
    of natural and revealed theology. What! no way to give
    religion a sound basis unless we allow the happiness of
    human life, and maintain that a continued existence even in
    this world—with all our actual pains, infirmities, vexations,
    and follies—is satisfactory and desirable! This is contrary
    to everyone’s feeling and experience; ·which means that· it
    is contrary to an authority so well established that nothing
    can undercut it. No decisive proofs can ever be produced
    against this authority; nor is it possible for you to compute,

    45

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 10

    estimate, and compare all the pains and all the pleasures in
    the lives of all men and of all animals; and so when you rest
    the whole system of religion on a claim which from its very
    nature must for ever be uncertain, you tacitly admit that the
    system is equally uncertain.

    Animal happiness, or at least human happiness, in this
    life exceeds its misery—no-one will ever believe this, or at
    any rate you’ll never be able to prove it. But even if we grant
    it to you, your argument has still achieved nothing; for this is
    far from what we expect from infinite power, infinite wisdom,
    and infinite goodness. Why is there any misery at all in the
    world? Not by chance, surely. From some cause, then. Is
    it from the intention of God? But he is perfectly benevolent.
    Is it contrary to his intention? But he is almighty. Nothing
    can shake the solidity of this reasoning, so short, so clear,
    so decisive—unless we say that these subjects exceed all
    human capacity, and that our common measures of truth
    and falsehood are not applicable to them; a thesis I have
    all along insisted on, but which you have from the outset
    rejected with scorn and indignation.

    But I will be contented to shift back from this position—
    ·doing this voluntarily·, for I deny that you can ever force
    me out of it. I will allow ·for purposes of argument· that
    pain or misery in man is compatible with infinite power and
    goodness in God, even when these attributes are understood
    in your way: what help do all these concessions give to

    your position? A mere possible compatibility is not sufficient.
    You must prove ·the existence of· these pure, unmixed,
    and uncontrollable attributes from the present mixed and
    confused phenomena, and from these alone. A hopeful
    undertaking! Even if the phenomena were ever so pure and
    unmixed, because they are finite they would be insufficient
    for your purpose. How much more ·inadequate· when they
    are also so jarring and discordant!

    Here, Cleanthes, I find I can relax in my argument.
    Here I triumph! When we argued earlier about the natural
    attributes of intelligence and design, I needed all my sceptical
    and metaphysical subtlety to escape your grasp. In many
    views of the universe and of its parts, particularly its parts,
    the beauty and fitness of final causes strike us with such
    irresistible force that all objections seem to be (as I think they
    really are) mere fault-finding and trickery; and then we can’t
    imagine how we could ever give weight to them. But there is
    no view of human life or of the condition of mankind from
    which we can smoothly infer the moral attributes ·of God·, or
    learn about that infinite benevolence, conjoined with infinite
    power and infinite wisdom, which we must discover by the
    eyes of faith alone. ·But now the tables are turned!· It is
    now your turn to tug the labouring oar, and to defend your
    philosophical subtleties against the dictates of plain reason
    and experience.

    46

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

  • Part 11
  • Part 11

    I don’t mind admitting, said Cleanthes, that I have been
    inclined to suspect that the frequent repetition of the word
    ‘infinite’, which we meet with in all theological writers, has
    the flavour of praise more than of philosophy; and that any
    purposes of reasoning, and any purposes even of religion,
    would be better served if we contented ourselves with more
    accurate and moderate expressions. The terms ‘admirable’,
    ‘excellent’, ‘superlatively great’, ‘wise’, and ‘holy’—these suf-
    ficiently fill the imaginations of men, and anything that
    goes further than they do ·has two drawbacks: it· •leads
    into absurdities, and it •has no influence on our feelings or
    beliefs. ·The way someone feels about a God who is ‘infinitely
    great’ is exactly the way he would feel about a God who
    is superlatively great·. Thus in our present subject if we
    abandon all human analogy, as you seem to want, Demea,
    I am afraid we abandon all religion and are left with no
    conception of ·God·, the great object of our admiring wonder.
    If we keep the human analogy ·while also staying with
    ‘infinite’·, we’ll never be able to reconcile •any mixture of evil
    in the universe with •infinite attributes; much less can we
    ever infer the attributes from the facts about what evil there
    is in the universe. But if we suppose the author of nature
    to be ·only· finitely perfect, though far more perfect than
    mankind, we can give a satisfactory account of natural and
    of moral evil, and every bad phenomenon can be explained
    and harmonized with the rest. A lesser evil may then be
    chosen in order to avoid a greater; inconveniences may be
    put up with in order to reach a desirable end; and, in brief,

    benevolence, guided by wisdom, and limited by neces-
    sity

    can produce just such a world as the one we have. You, Philo,

    who are so prompt at launching views and reflections and
    analogies, I would be glad to hear—at length and without
    interruption—your opinion of this new theory of mine. If it
    turns out to deserve our attention, we can later take our
    time about shaping it up and filling in details.

    My opinions, replied Philo, aren’t worth being made a
    mystery of; so without more ado I’ll tell you what occurs to
    me regarding this present subject. It must be admitted, I
    think, that if a being who had very limited intelligence and
    was utterly unacquainted with our universe were assured
    that it is the product of a being who, though finite, is very
    good, wise, and powerful, this would lead him beforehand
    to expect something different from what our experience
    shows the universe to be like; he would never imagine,
    merely from being informed that •the cause is very good,
    wise, and powerful that •the effect could be as full of vice
    and misery and disorder as it appears to be in this life.
    Supposing now that this person were brought into our world,
    still sure that it was the workmanship of that sublime and
    benevolent being; he might be surprised at the discrepancy
    with what he had expected; but he wouldn’t retract his
    former belief ·about the cause of the universe· if that was
    founded on any very solid argument; for ·a person with· such
    a limited intelligence must be aware of his own blindness and
    ignorance, and must admit that these phenomena ·of vice,
    misery etc.· may have explanations that he’ll never be able
    to understand. But suppose that this creature is not—as
    we are not—convinced in advance of a supreme intelligence,
    benevolent and powerful, but is left to infer such a belief from
    the appearances of things; this entirely alters the case, and
    he will never find any reason for such a conclusion. He may

    47

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 11

    be fully convinced of the narrow limits of his understanding;
    but this won’t help him to make an inference concerning
    the goodness of superior powers, because he has to make
    that inference from what he knows, not from what he is
    ignorant of. The more you exaggerate his weakness and
    ignorance, the more cautious you make him, and the more
    you make him suspect that such subjects are beyond the
    reach of his faculties. You are obliged, therefore, to reason
    with him merely from the known phenomena, and to drop
    every arbitrary supposition or conjecture.

    If I showed you a house or palace where •there wasn’t
    one convenient or agreeable apartment, where •the windows,
    doors, fireplaces, passages, stairs, and the whole arrange-
    ment of the building were the source of noise, confusion,
    fatigue, darkness, and the extremes of heat and cold, you
    would certainly blame the planning of the building without
    any further examination. It would be no use for the architect
    to display his subtlety, and to prove to you that if this door
    or that window were altered something worse would follow.
    What he says may be strictly true: it may be that it would
    only make things worse to alter one detail while leaving the
    other parts of the building unchanged. But you would still
    say in general that if the architect had had skill and good
    intentions he could have planned the whole building, and
    inter-related its parts, in such a way as to remedy all or most
    of these inconveniences. His ignorance of such a plan—even
    your own ignorance of such a plan—will never convince you
    that it is impossible. If you find any inconveniences and de-
    fects in the building, you will always—straight off—condemn
    the architect.

    In short, I repeat the question: Is the world, considered
    over-all and as it appears to us in this life, different from
    what a limited being like a man would expect beforehand
    from a very powerful, wise, and benevolent God? It must

    be a strange prejudice to assert that it isn’t. And from this
    I conclude that however consistent the world may be (on
    certain assumptions and with allowances made) with the
    idea of such a God, it can never provide us with an inference
    to his existence. The consistency is not absolutely denied,
    only the inference. Conjectures, especially when infinity is
    excluded from God’s attributes, may perhaps be sufficient to
    prove a consistency, but they can never be foundations for
    any inference.

    There seem to be four circumstances on which depend all
    or most of the troubles that beset conscious creatures; and
    it isn’t impossible that all these circumstances are necessary
    and unavoidable. We know so little beyond common life—we
    know indeed so little of common life—that when it comes
    to the way a universe is arranged •any conjecture, however
    wild, may be correct ·so far as we can tell to the contrary·;
    and •any conjecture, however plausible, may be erroneous
    ·so far as we can tell to the contrary·. The human under-
    standing, in this deep ignorance and obscurity, ought to be
    sceptical, or at least cautious, and oughtn’t to accept any
    hypothesis whatever, especially ones that aren’t supported
    by any appearance of probability. I claim that this is the case
    with regard to all the causes of evil, and the circumstances
    on which it depends. None of them appears to human reason
    to be in the slightest necessary or unavoidable; and we can’t
    suppose them to be so without letting our imaginations run
    wild.

    (1) The first circumstance that introduces evil is the
    device or arrangement of the animal creation by which
    pains as well as pleasures are employed to rouse creatures
    to action, and make them alert in the great work of self-
    preservation. Now it seems to human understanding that
    pleasure alone, in its various levels of intensity, would suffice
    for this purpose. It could have been like this:

    48

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 11

    All animals are constantly in a state of enjoyment;
    but when they are urged by any of the necessities of
    nature—such as thirst, hunger, weariness—instead
    of pain they feel a lessening of pleasure, and this
    prompts them to seek whatever it is that is needed for
    their survival.

    Men pursue pleasure as eagerly as they avoid pain—or,
    anyway, they could have been so constituted that this was
    true of them. So it seems clearly possible to carry on the
    business of life without any pain. Why then is any animal
    ever subjected to such a sensation? If animals can be free
    from it for an hour, they could be free from it all the time; and
    ·their being subject to pain is a positive fact about them, not
    a mere absence of something it might have been impossible to
    provide·: it required a particular arrangement of their organs
    to produce pain, just as it did to endow them with sight,
    hearing, or any of the senses. Shall we conjecture—without
    any appearance of reason for it—that such an arrangement
    was necessary? and shall we build on that conjecture as we
    would on the most certain truth?

    (2) But a capacity for pain would not of itself produce
    pain if it weren’t for something else, namely the world’s
    being governed by general laws; and this seems to be in no
    way necessary for a very perfect being. It is true that if each
    thing that happens were caused by an individual volition
    on God’s part, the course of nature would be perpetually
    broken, ·there would be no dependable regularities, and so·
    no man could employ his reason in the conduct of life. But ·if
    some such volitions threatened to have that effect·, mightn’t
    other particular volitions remedy this inconvenience? In
    short, might not God exterminate all misfortune, wherever
    it was to be found, and make everything all good, ·through
    judiciously placed individual volitions, and thus· without
    any preparation or long chains of causes and effects?

    Besides, we should bear in mind that in the present
    arrangement of the world the course of nature, though
    supposed to be entirely regular, appears to us not to be
    so; many events are uncertain, and many disappoint our
    expectations. Countless kinds of happenings whose causes
    are unknown and variable—for example health and sick-
    ness, calm and tempest—have a great influence both on
    the fortunes of particular persons and on the prosperity of
    whole communities; and indeed all human life depends in a
    way on such happenings. So a being who knows the secret
    workings of the universe might easily, by particular volitions,
    turn all these happenings to the good of mankind and make
    the whole world happy, without revealing himself in any
    operation. A fleet whose purposes were useful to society
    might always meet with a fair wind. Good rulers might
    enjoy sound health and long life. Persons born to power
    and authority might be endowed with good temperaments
    and virtuous dispositions. A few outcomes such as these,
    regularly and wisely brought about, would change the face
    of the world; and yet they would no more seem to disturb the
    course of nature or thwart human conduct than does the
    present arrangement of things where the causes are secret,
    and variable, and complex. Some small touches given to
    Caligula’s brain in his infancy might have converted him
    into a Trajan. One wave a little higher than the rest, by
    burying Caesar and his fortune in the bottom of the ocean,
    might have restored liberty to a considerable part of mankind.
    There may, for all we know, be good reasons why Providence
    doesn’t intervene in this manner; but we don’t know them;
    and though the mere supposition that such reasons exist
    may be sufficient to save the conclusion concerning the
    Divine attributes ·from being refuted by the observed facts·,
    it can surely never be sufficient to establish that conclusion.

    49

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 11

    If (2) everything in the universe is governed by general
    laws, and if (1) animals are made capable of pain, it seems
    almost inevitable that some misfortune will arise in the
    various collisions of matter, and the various agreements and
    clashes between general laws; but such misfortune would be
    very rare if it weren’t for. . .

    (3) . . . the third of the four factors that I proposed to
    mention. It is the great frugality with which all powers
    and abilities are distributed to every particular being. The
    organs and capacities of all animals are so well organized
    and so well fitted to their preservation that—judging by
    history and tradition—there appears never yet to have been a
    species that was extinguished in the universe. Every animal
    has the endowments it needs; but these endowments are
    given out with such careful economy—·giving each creature
    only the bare necessities for its survival·—that if anything
    considerable is taken away from them the creature is entirely
    destroyed. Wherever one power is increased, there is a
    proportional lessening of the others. Animals that excel in
    speed are commonly lacking in strength. Those that have
    both are either imperfect in some of their senses or are
    oppressed with the most craving wants. The human species,
    whose chief excellence is reason and foresight, has more
    needs and fewer bodily advantages than any of the others:
    ·think of how humans would be situated if they were· without
    clothes, without weapons, without food, without lodging,
    without any convenience of life except what they owe to their
    own skill and hard work. In short, nature seems to have
    calculated exactly what her creatures need, and—like a stern
    employer—has granted them little more than the powers or
    endowments that are strictly sufficient to meet those needs.
    An indulgent parent would have provided a great deal extra,
    so as to guard against unforeseen events and to secure the
    happiness and welfare of the creature in the worst crises. He

    would not have left us in a condition where every course of
    life is surrounded with precipices to such an extent that the
    least departure from the true path—whether by mistake or by
    necessity—is bound to involve us in misery and ruin. Some
    reserve, some ·emergency· fund, would have been provided
    to ensure happiness; and our powers and our needs wouldn’t
    have been so strictly balanced against each other. The author
    of nature is inconceivably powerful; his force is supposed to
    be great, even if not limitless; and there’s no reason we can
    find why he should be so strictly frugal in his dealings with
    his creatures. If his power is extremely limited, he’d have
    done better to create fewer animals, and to have endowed
    these with more means for being happy and staying alive. A
    builder is never regarded as prudent if he tackles a plan that
    he hasn’t the materials to finish.

    In order to remedy most of the misfortunes of human
    life I don’t require that man should have the wings of the
    eagle, the swiftness of the stag, the force of the ox, the
    arms of the lion, the scales of the crocodile or rhinoceros;
    much less do I demand the intelligence of an angel. I will
    settle for an increase in one single power or capacity of his
    mind: let him be endowed with a greater liking for work, a
    more vigorous bounce and activity of mind, a more constant
    tendency to get on with his business. If the whole species
    possessed naturally the same high level of diligence that
    many individuals cultivate in themselves, the immediate
    and necessary result of this endowment would be the most
    beneficial consequences, with no taint of anything bad.
    Almost all the moral evils of human life, as well as its natural
    evils, arise from •idleness; and if our species had been built
    so as to be inherently free of •this vice or infirmity, the
    immediate result would have been the perfect cultivation
    of land, the improvement of arts and manufactures, the
    exact performance of every office and duty, and men would

    50

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 11

    straight away have reached the state of society that ·as
    things are· is only imperfectly achieved by the best regulated
    government. But as hard-workingness is a power, and indeed
    the most valuable of all the powers, nature seems to be
    determined to follow her usual policy and to bestow it on
    men with a very sparing hand; and to punish him severely
    for not having enough of it rather than to reward him for
    his achievements. She has built him in such a way that
    nothing but the strongest need can force him to work, ·and
    she exploits that fact in order to get him to work·: she uses
    all his other wants to overcome, at least in part, his lack
    of diligence, thus endowing him •·through hardship and
    need· with some share of a faculty that she has deprived him
    of •naturally. Here our demands can be agreed to be very
    humble, and thus all the more reasonable. If we required
    the endowments of sharper intellect and wiser judgment, of
    a more delicate taste for beauty, of more sensitive feelings
    of benevolence and friendship, we might be told •that we
    were impiously claiming to break the order of nature, •that
    we wanted to raise ourselves to a higher level of being, •that
    the gifts that we ask for, not being suitable to our state and
    condition, would only bring us misery. But it is hard—I dare
    to repeat it, it is hard—that when we are placed in a world so
    full of wants and necessities, where almost every being and
    element is either our foe or refuses its assistance, we should
    also have our own temperament to struggle with, and should
    be deprived of the only faculty—·namely, an inclination for
    hard work·—that can protect us from these multiplied evils.

    (4) The fourth factor leading to the misery and misfortune
    of the universe is the inaccurate workmanship of all the
    workings and principles of the great machine of nature. It
    must be admitted that most parts of the universe seem to
    serve some purpose, and in most cases the removal of a part
    would produce a visible defect and disorder in the whole. The

    parts all hang together; and you can’t change one without
    affecting the rest, more or less. But at the same time it must
    be observed that none of these parts or powers, however
    useful, are so accurately adjusted that they keep precisely
    within the limits of their usefulness; all of them are apt much
    of the time to run to one extreme or the other. This grand
    product, ·the universe·, is so unfinished in every part, and is
    carried out with such coarse brush-strokes, that one would
    think that its maker hadn’t yet put on its finishing touches.
    Thus, winds are needed to blow away smoke and fog and
    noxious fumes, and to help men in navigation: but often
    they grow to being tempests and hurricanes, and then they
    become pernicious. Rains are necessary to nourish all the
    plants and animals of the earth; but often there are droughts
    and often the rain is excessive. Heat is needed for life and
    vegetation, but isn’t always found at the right level. The
    health and prosperity of the animal depend on the making
    and mixing of the fluids and juices of its body, but the
    parts ·of these fluids· don’t dependably perform their proper
    function. The passions of the mind—ambition, vanity, love,
    anger—are extremely useful, but they often overflow their
    banks and cause the greatest convulsions in society. Ev-
    erything in the universe, however advantageous, frequently
    becomes pernicious through there being too much or too
    little of it; and nature has not guarded effectively against
    all disorder or confusion. The irregularity is perhaps never
    so great as to destroy any species, but is often sufficient to
    involve individuals in ruin and misery.

    There are the four factors on which all or most natural evil
    depends. If (1) all living creatures were incapable of feeling
    pain, or if (2) the world were governed by particular volitions,
    evil never could have found its way into the universe; and if
    (3) animals were endowed with a large stock of powers and
    faculties, beyond what they strictly need for survival, or if

    51

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 11

    (4) the various springs and principles of the universe were
    so accurately devised as to preserve always the temperate
    middle level ·and not run to extremes·, there would have been
    very little misfortune compared to what we feel at present.
    What then shall we say about all this? Shall we say that
    the universe could easily have been designed so as to be
    different in these four respects? This decision seems too
    presumptuous for creatures as blind and ignorant as we
    are. Let us be more modest in our conclusions. Let us allow
    that if the goodness of God (I mean a goodness like human
    goodness) could be established by any respectable a priori
    argument, these phenomena, however unfortunate, wouldn’t
    be sufficient to undercut that principle ·of God’s goodness·;
    for the phenomena might be easily reconcilable to it in some
    way we don’t know about. But we should still maintain that
    as God’s goodness is not antecedently established, and has
    to be inferred from the phenomena, there can be no grounds
    for such an inference when there are so many misfortunes
    in the universe, and while these misfortunes could—as far
    as human understanding can be allowed to judge on such
    a subject—easily have been remedied. I am sceptic enough
    to allow that the bad appearances, notwithstanding all my
    reasonings, may be compatible with such ·divine· attributes
    as you suppose; but surely they can never prove these
    attributes. The conclusion ·that God is good· cannot result
    from scepticism, but must arise from the phenomena and
    from our confidence in the reasonings through which we
    draw conclusions from these phenomena.

    Look around this universe. What an immense profusion
    of beings, animated and organized, conscious and active!
    You admire this prodigious variety and fruitfulness. But
    look a little more closely at these living things (the only ones
    worth thinking about). How hostile and destructive they are
    to each other! How far they all are from being able to achieve

    their own happiness! How contemptible or odious they are
    to the spectator! The whole picture is one of a blind nature
    impregnated by some powerful life-giving force and pouring
    forth from her lap, without discernment or parental care, her
    maimed and abortive children!

    Here the Manichaean system—·according to which the
    universe is governed by two fundamental forces, one good
    and the other bad·—comes to mind as a good hypothesis
    to solve the difficulty. No doubt it is in some respects very
    attractive, and its giving a plausible account of the strange
    mixture of good and ill that appears in life makes it more
    probable than the common hypothesis ·of a single benevolent
    God·. But if on the other hand we think about the perfect
    uniformity and agreement of the parts of the universe, we
    shan’t discover in it any signs of a malevolent being’s battle
    against a benevolent one. There is indeed an opposition of
    •pains and pleasures in the feelings of conscious creatures;
    but aren’t all the operations of nature carried on by an
    opposition of forces, of •hot and cold, •moist and dry, •light
    and heavy? The true conclusion is that the original source
    of all things is entirely indifferent to all these forces, and
    no more prefers •good above evil •than heat above cold, or
    •drought above moisture, or •light above heavy.

    Four hypotheses can be formed concerning the first
    causes of the universe: that they are endowed with per-
    fect goodness; that they have perfect malice; that they are
    opposite, and have both goodness and malice; that they have
    neither goodness nor malice. Mixed phenomena can never
    prove the two former unmixed principles; and the uniformity
    and steadiness of general laws seem to oppose the third. The
    fourth, therefore, seems by far the most probable—·that is,
    that the first causes of the universe are neutral with regard
    to good and bad·.

    52

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 11

    What I have said about •natural evil also applies with little
    or no change to •moral evil: we have no more reason to infer
    that the uprightness of the supreme being resembles human
    uprightness than that his benevolence resembles human
    benevolence. Indeed, it will be thought that we have more
    reason to exclude from him moral feelings such as ours,
    because many people think that moral evil predominates
    over moral good more than natural evil above natural good.

    But even if this is rejected, and even if the virtue that
    mankind has is acknowledged to be much superior to the
    vice, still as long as there is any vice at all in the universe you
    anthropomorphites will be very puzzled over how to account
    for it. You must assign a cause for it, without bringing in
    the first cause. But every effect must have a cause, and that
    cause must have another, and so you must either carry on
    the sequence ad infinitum or bring it to an end with that
    original principle who is the ultimate cause of all things. . .

    Wait! Wait! exclaimed Demea: where is your imagination
    taking you? I allied myself with you in order to prove the
    incomprehensible nature of the divine being, and to refute
    the principles of Cleanthes who wants to measure everything
    by human rules and standards. But now I find you agreeing
    with all the views of the greatest libertines and infidels,
    and betraying that holy cause which you seemed earlier
    to embrace. Are you secretly, then, a more dangerous enemy
    than Cleanthes himself?

    Has it taken you this long to see that? replied Cleanthes.
    Believe me, Demea, your friend Philo has from the outset
    been amusing himself at my expense and at yours; and I
    must admit that the incautious reasoning of our common
    theology has given him all too good a handle for ridicule. The
    total infirmity of human reason, the absolute incomprehensi-
    bility of God’s nature, the great and universal misery and the

    still greater wickedness of men—these are strange themes,
    surely, to be so fondly cherished by orthodox churchmen and
    professors. In ages of stupidity and ignorance, indeed, these
    principles may safely be espoused; and it may be that the
    best way to promote superstition is to encourage mankind
    in its blind bewilderment, its lack of confidence, its gloom.
    But at present. . .

    Don’t blame the trouble so much on the ignorance of these
    reverend gentlemen, interrupted Philo. They know how to
    change their style with the times. Formerly it was a most
    popular line in theology to maintain that human life is empty
    and miserable, and to exaggerate all the ills and pains that
    men undergo. But in recent years we have found theologians
    beginning to withdraw from this position, and to maintain,
    though still with some hesitation, that even in this life there
    are more goods than evils, more pleasures than pains. •When
    religion depended entirely on temperament and education,
    it was thought proper to encourage gloom; for indeed men
    are most ready to appeal to superior powers when they are
    feeling gloomy. •But now that men have learned to form
    principles and draw conclusions, ·so that religion depends
    on arguments rather than merely on how you feel and how
    you have been indoctrinated·, it is necessary to bring some
    different guns to bear, and to make use of arguments that
    can survive at least some scrutiny and examination. This
    change of tactics is the same (and from the same causes) as
    the one I formerly remarked on with regard to scepticism.

    In this way Philo continued to the last his spirit of
    opposition, and his condemnation of established opinions.
    But I could see that Demea didn’t at all like the last part of
    what he said; and soon after that he made some excuse or
    other to leave the group.

    53

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume

  • Part 12
  • Part 12

    After Demea’s departure, Cleanthes and Philo continued
    the conversation in the following manner. Our friend, I am
    afraid, said Cleanthes, won’t be much inclined to revive this
    topic of discussion in a group containing you; and to tell
    you the truth, Philo, on a subject that is so elevated and
    that matters so much I would prefer to reason with you,
    or with Demea, alone. Your spirit of controversy, joined to
    your hatred of common superstition, carries you to strange
    lengths when you are engaged in an argument; and on such
    an occasion you don’t spare anything, however sacred and
    venerable it is, even in your own eyes.

    I must admit, replied Philo, that I am less cautious on
    the subject of natural religion than on any other; both
    because •I know that I can never corrupt the principles
    (concerning religion) of any man of common sense, and
    because •I am confident that no-one who sees me as a man
    of common sense will ever misunderstand my intentions.
    You, in particular, Cleanthes, with whom I live in unreserved
    intimacy—you are aware that despite the freedom of my
    conversation and my love of unusual arguments, no-one
    has a deeper sense of religion impressed on his mind than I
    do, or offers more profound adoration to the divine being as
    he reveals himself to our reason in the inexplicable design
    and artfulness of nature. The most careless, the most
    stupid, thinker sees everywhere a purpose, an intention,
    a design; and no man can be so hardened in absurd systems
    as to reject that at all times. That nature does nothing in
    vain is a maxim established in all the universities, merely
    on the strength of observing the works of nature, without
    any religious purpose; and from a firm conviction of its
    truth an anatomist who had observed a new organ or canal

    ·in an animal body· would never be satisfied until he had
    also discovered what it does and what it is for. One great
    foundation of the Copernican system is the maxim that
    nature acts by the simplest methods, and chooses the most
    proper means to any end; and astronomers often, without
    thinking of it, lay this strong foundation ·stone on which can
    be erected the edifice· of piety and religion. The same thing
    is observable in other branches of learning; and thus almost
    all the sciences lead us insensibly to acknowledge a first
    thinking author; and their authority is often all the greater
    for the fact that they don’t openly say that that’s what they
    mean to do.

    It is with pleasure that I hear Galen reason concerning
    the structure of the human body. The anatomy of a man, he
    says, reveals more than

    60

    0 different muscles; and anyone
    who studies these will find that in each of them nature must
    have taken into account at least ten different circumstances,
    in order to achieve the end that she proposed:

    •right shape, •right size, •right disposition of the sev-
    eral ends, •the upper and •lower position of the whole
    muscle, the proper insertion of the various •nerves,
    •veins, and •arteries;

    so that in the muscles alone more than 6,000 different plans
    and intentions must have been formed and carried out. He
    calculates that there are 284 bones, and that the structure
    of each of them aims at more than forty purposes. What
    an enormous display of planning, even in these simple and
    homogeneous parts! But if we consider the skin, ligaments,
    blood-vessels, glands, bodily fluids, the various limbs and
    members of the body—how our astonishment must increase
    in proportion to the number and intricacy of the parts so

    54

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    artfully related to one another! As we go further in these
    researches, we discover new scenes of skill and wisdom;
    but we can tell that further down the smallness scale there
    are yet other scenes, beyond our ·perceptual· reach, in the
    fine internal structure of the parts, in the organization of
    the brain, in the build of the seminal vessels. All these
    devices are repeated in every different species of animal,
    with wonderful variety, and in each case exactly right for
    the intentions of nature in forming the species in question.
    And if Galen’s irreligion couldn’t withstand such striking
    appearances, even when these natural sciences were still
    imperfect, a scientist today must indeed be stubbornly
    obstinate if he can doubt that there is a supreme intelligence!

    If I met with one of this sort (thank God, they are very
    rare), I would ask him: Supposing there were a God who
    didn’t reveal himself immediately to our senses—·enabling
    us to see or feel or hear him·—could he possibly give stronger
    proofs of his existence than the proofs that do appear on
    the whole face of nature? What indeed could such a divine
    being do but •copy the present arrangement of things, •make
    many of his artifices so obvious that no stupidity could
    mistake them, •provide glimpses of still greater artifices that
    demonstrate his prodigious superiority above our narrow
    minds, and •conceal a great many of them altogether from
    such imperfect creatures ·as we are·? Now, according to all
    rules of sound reasoning, every factual proposition counts
    as indisputable when it is supported by all the arguments
    that its nature admits of, even if those arguments aren’t in
    themselves very numerous or strong; how much more this
    applies in the present case where no human imagination can
    compute the number of the arguments and no understanding
    can take in how strong they are!

    I shall add, said Cleanthes, to what you have so well
    urged that one great advantage of the principle of theism

    is that it’s the only system of cosmogony that can be made
    intelligible and complete while also preserving throughout a
    strong analogy to what we see and experience in the world
    every day. The comparison of the universe to a machine of
    human design is so obvious and natural, and is justified
    by so many examples of order and design in nature, that it
    must immediately occur to all unprejudiced minds, and win
    universal approval. Whoever wants to weaken this theory
    can’t claim to succeed by •establishing in its place any other
    that is precise and determinate, ·for there is no such rival·:
    it is sufficient for him if he raises doubts and difficulties,
    and by remote and abstract views of things reaches that
    •suspense of judgment which on this topic is the most he
    can wish for. But •this state of mind, as well as being
    in itself unsatisfactory, can never be steadily maintained
    against such striking appearances as continually draw us
    into the religious hypothesis. Human nature is capable,
    through the force of prejudice, of obstinately persevering in a
    false, absurd system; but I think it is absolutely impossible
    to maintain or defend having no system at all, in opposition
    to a theory that is supported by strong and obvious reasons,
    by natural propensity, and by early education.

    I have so little respect for this suspension of judgment
    about the existence of God, said Philo, that I’m inclined to
    suspect that this controversy is more of a verbal dispute than
    is usually imagined. That the works of nature are very like
    the products of ·human· ingenuity is evident; and according
    to all the rules of good reasoning we ought to infer—if we ar-
    gue at all about them—that their causes are correspondingly
    alike. But as there are also considerable differences ·between
    the works of nature and human products·, we have reason to
    suppose that their causes are correspondingly unalike, and
    that in particular we ought to attribute a much higher degree
    of power and energy to the supreme cause than to any we

    55

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    have ever observed in mankind. Here then the existence of a
    God is plainly discovered by reason: and if there is a question
    as to whether these analogies entitle us to call him a mind
    or intelligence, given the vast difference that can reasonably
    be supposed to exist between him and human minds, what
    is this but a mere verbal controversy? No man can deny the
    likenesses between the effects; to hold back from •enquiring
    about the causes is scarcely possible. From •this enquiry
    the legitimate conclusion is that the causes are also alike in
    some respects; and if we aren’t contented with calling the
    first and supreme cause ·only· a ‘God’ or ‘deity’ but want to
    find other words to apply to him, what can we call him but
    ‘mind’ or ‘thought’, given that he is justly supposed to bear a
    considerable resemblance to minds?

    All sensible people are annoyed by verbal disputes, which
    occur so often in philosophical and theological enquiries; and
    it is found that the only remedy for this misuse ·of language·
    comes from clear definitions, from the precision of the ideas
    that enter into any argument, and from strictly keeping to
    the meanings of the terms one uses. But there is one sort
    of controversy which, from the very nature of language and
    of human ideas, is involved in perpetual ambiguity and can
    never, by any precaution or any definitions, reach a reason-
    able certainty or precision. These are the controversies about
    the degrees of any quality or circumstance. •Was Hannibal
    a great, or a very great, or a superlatively great man? •How
    beautiful was Cleopatra? •What term of praise is Livy or
    Thucydides entitled to? Men may argue to all eternity about
    such questions without ever settling on agreed answers. The
    disputants may here agree in what they think, and differ in
    the words they use—or vice versa—and yet never be able to
    define their terms so as to understand each other’s meaning.
    That’s because the degrees of these qualities, unlike quantity
    or number, can’t be measured on any exact scale that could

    be the standard in the controversy. The slightest enquiry
    reveals that the dispute concerning theism is of this nature,
    and consequently is merely verbal—or perhaps still more
    incurably ambiguous, if that is possible. •I ask the theist if
    he doesn’t agree that the difference between the human mind
    and the divine mind is great and (because it is incomprehen-
    sible) immeasurable; and the more pious he is •the readier
    he will be to agree, and the more he will be disposed to
    magnify the difference; he will even assert that the difference
    is so great that it would be impossible to exaggerate how
    great it is. I next turn to the atheist—who I say is only
    nominally an atheist, and can’t possibly be seriously so—and
    •I ask him whether, judging by the coherence and apparent
    co-ordination among all the parts of this world, there isn’t
    a certain similarity among all the operations of nature, in
    every situation and in every age—whether

    the rotting of a turnip,
    the coming into existence of an animal, and
    the structure of human thought,

    are not energies that probably bear some remote analogy to
    each other—and •he can’t possibly deny it; ·indeed·, he will
    readily acknowledge it. Having obtained this concession from
    him, I push the self-described ‘atheist’ back still further: I
    ask him if it isn’t likely that the source that first ordered this
    universe ·in general· and still keeps it in order bears also
    some remote and hard-to-grasp analogy to the ·particular·
    operations of nature, including the arrangements that pro-
    duce the human mind and thought. However reluctantly, he
    must say Yes. Then I ask both these antagonists:

    What are you arguing about? The theist allows that
    the original intelligence is very different from human
    reason; the atheist allows that the original source of
    order bears some remote analogy to it. Will you quar-
    rel, gentlemen, about the degrees ·of difference and of

    56

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    similarity·, and enter into a controversy that can’t be
    made precise and thus can’t be settled? If you were to
    persist obstinately, I wouldn’t be surprised to find you
    unknowingly changing sides—•the theist exaggerating
    the dissimilarity between the supreme being and frail,
    imperfect, variable, fleeting, and mortal creatures,
    while •the atheist exaggerates the similarity that there
    is among all the operations of nature, at every time
    and in every place and circumstance! Consider, then,
    what you are really disagreeing about, and if you can’t
    set aside the disagreement, at least ·realize that it
    concerns the place of certain dissimilarities on a scale
    for which there is no precise measure, and thus· try
    to cure yourselves of your hostility to one another.

    And here I must also acknowledge, Cleanthes, that as the
    works of nature are more like the effects of our •skill and
    planning than they are like the effects of our •benevolence
    and justice, we have reason to infer that God’s •non-moral
    attributes have a greater resemblance to those of men than
    his •moral attributes have to human virtues. But what
    follows from that? Only that man’s moral qualities are more
    defective in their kind than are his non-moral abilities—·for
    example, that man’s justice is a worse sample of justice than
    his cleverness is a sample of cleverness·. For it is agreed
    that God is absolutely and entirely perfect, so whatever
    differs most from him departs the furthest from the supreme
    standard of moral uprightness and perfection.2

    These, Cleanthes, are my undisguised views on this
    subject; and you know that I have upheld and valued
    them for a long time. But my veneration for true religion
    is matched by my abhorrence of common superstitions,
    and I admit that I get a special pleasure out of pushing
    superstitions—sometimes into absurdity, sometimes into
    impiety. All bigots hate impiety more than they do absurdity,
    but, as you are well aware, they are often equally guilty of
    both.

    My inclination, replied Cleanthes, lies in a different
    direction. Religion, however corrupted, is still better than
    no religion at all. The doctrine of a future state is so strong
    and necessary a security to morals that we never ought to
    abandon or neglect it. For if finite and temporary rewards
    and punishments have such a great effect as we daily find
    that they do, how much greater must be expected from
    rewards and punishments that are infinite and eternal?

    If common superstition is so good for society, said Philo,
    then how does it happen that history is so full of accounts
    of its pernicious effects on public affairs? Factions, civil
    wars, persecutions, subversions of government, oppression,
    slavery—these are the dismal consequences which always
    accompany a prevalence of superstition in the minds of
    men. Whenever an historical narrative mentions the religious
    spirit, we are sure to find later in the story some details of the
    miseries that come with it. No period of time can be happier
    or more prosperous than those in which the religious spirit
    is never honoured or heard of.

    2 It seems obvious that the dispute between the sceptics and dogmatists is entirely verbal; or at any rate it only concerns how much doubt or assurance
    we should have in all our reasoning, and disputes about that are often basically verbal, and can’t be definitively settled. •No philosophical dogmatist
    denies that there are difficulties both with regard to the senses and to all science, and that these difficulties absolutely cannot be resolved in a
    regular, logical manner. •No sceptic denies that we, despite these difficulties, cannot get out of thinking, and believing, and reasoning with regard to
    all kinds of subjects, or of often assenting to things with confidence and security. So the only difference between these sects (if that is what they are)
    is that the sceptic—from habit, whim, or inclination—insists most on the difficulties; the dogmatist, for like reasons, insists on the necessity.

    57

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    The reason for this, replied Cleanthes, is obvious. The
    proper role of religion is to regulate the heart of men, human-
    ize their conduct, infuse the spirit of temperance, order, and
    obedience; and as it works silently, and only strengthens
    the motives of morality and justice, it is in danger of being
    overlooked and being confused with those other motives.
    When religion calls attention to itself and acts as a separate
    motive force in men—·instead of being only a good influence
    on all the other motive forces·—it has left its proper sphere
    and has become only a cover for faction and ambition.

    And so will all religion, said Philo, except the philosophi-
    cal and rational kind. Your reasonings are easier to escape
    from than are my facts. ‘Because finite and temporary
    rewards and punishments have so great influence, therefore
    infinite and eternal ones must have so much greater’—this
    reasoning is not sound. Consider, I beg you, how much
    we care about present things, and how little concern we
    express for objects as remote and uncertain ·as the rewards
    or punishments promised in the after-life·. When preachers
    declaim against the common behaviour and conduct of the
    world, they always represent this principle ·of concern for
    what is close· as the strongest imaginable (which indeed
    it is); and they describe most of mankind as lying under
    its influence, and sunk into the deepest lethargy and lack
    of concern for their religious interests. Yet these same
    religious spokesmen, defending religion against attacks, take
    the motives of religion to be so powerful that civil society
    couldn’t survive without them; and they aren’t ashamed of
    this obvious contradiction. Experience shows us, for sure,
    that •the smallest grain of natural honesty and benevolence
    has more effect on men’s conduct than •the most grandly
    inflated views suggested by theological theories and systems.
    A man’s natural inclination works on him all the time; it is
    always present to his mind, and mingles itself with every

    view and consideration; whereas religious motives, where
    they act at all, operate only by fits and starts, and it is
    scarcely possible for them to become altogether habitual to
    the mind. The force of the greatest gravitational pull, say
    the physicists, is incomparably smaller than the force of
    the least push; yet it is certain that the smallest gravity will
    eventually prevail over a large push, because no strokes or
    blows can be repeated with such constancy as attraction and
    gravitation.

    Another advantage that inclination has ·in the tussle with
    duty·: it brings into play on its side all the sharpness and
    ingenuity of the mind, and when it is placed in opposition
    to religious principles it seeks every method and device for
    eluding them—and it nearly always succeeds! Who can
    explain the heart of man, or account for those strange special-
    pleadings and excuses with which people let themselves off
    when they are following their inclinations in opposition to
    their religious duty? This is well understood in the world;
    and only fools would trust a man less because they heard
    that study and philosophy have given him some speculative
    doubts with regard to theological subjects. And when we
    have dealings with a man who makes a great profession of
    religion and devotion, doesn’t this put many sensible people
    on their guard against being cheated and deceived by him?

    We must further consider that philosophers, who cultivate
    reason and reflection, have less need of such ·religious·
    motives to keep them under the restraint of morals; and
    that common people—the only ones who may need religion
    ·to keep them in order·—can’t possibly have a religion so
    pure that it represents God as being pleased with nothing
    but virtue in human behaviour. Pleas for God’s favour are
    generally understood to be either frivolous observances, or
    rapturous ecstasies, or a bigoted credulity ·and therefore not
    to reflect or to encourage moral seriousness·. We needn’t

    58

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    go back to ancient times, or wander into remote places,
    to find instances of this degeneracy ·of religion divorced
    from morality·. Amongst ourselves some people have been
    guilty of something atrocious that ·even· the Egyptian and
    Greek superstitions were not guilty of, namely, speaking out
    explicitly against morality, saying that if one puts the least
    trust or reliance in morality one will certainly lose favour
    with God.

    And even if superstition or fanaticism didn’t put itself
    in direct opposition to morality, it would still have the
    most pernicious consequences, greatly weakening men’s
    attachment to the natural motives of justice and humanity.
    It would do this because of •its diverting of the attention
    ·away from morality·, •its raising up of a new and frivolous
    sort of ·supposed· merit, and •the preposterous way in which
    it distributes praise and blame.

    Such a ·religious· action-driver, not being one of the
    familiar motives of human conduct, acts only intermittently
    on a person’s temperament; and it has to be roused by
    continual efforts in order to render the pious zealot satisfied
    with his own conduct and make him fulfil his devotional
    task. Many religious exercises are begun with seeming
    fervour although the person’s heart at the time feels cold
    and apathetic; he gradually acquires a habit of covering
    up his true feelings; and fraud and falsehood ·eventually·
    become the predominant force ·in his mind·. This explains
    the common observation that •the highest zeal in religion
    and •the deepest hypocrisy, so far from being inconsistent,
    are often or usually united in the same individual person.

    The bad effects of such habits, even in ordinary everyday
    life, are easily imagined; but where the interests of religion
    are concerned, no morality can be strong enough to con-
    strain the fanatical zealot. The sacredness of his cause—·he
    thinks·—sanctifies anything that he does to promote it.

    Steadily and exclusively attending to something as impor-
    tant to oneself as eternal salvation is apt to extinguish one’s
    benevolent feelings and to generate a narrow, contracted
    selfishness. And when such a temperament is encouraged,
    it easily eludes all the general precepts of charity and benev-
    olence.

    Thus, the motives of common superstition have no great
    influence on general conduct, and where they do predomi-
    nate their influence is not favourable to morality.

    Is any maxim in politics more certain and infallible than
    the one saying that •the number and •the authority of priests
    should be confined within very narrow limits, and that the
    civil magistrate ought never to allow the instruments of
    his authority fall into such dangerous hands ·as those of
    priests·? But if the spirit of popular religion [= ‘the religion of

    ordinary people’] were as salutary to society ·as its defenders
    say it is·, a contrary maxim ought to prevail, ·reflecting a
    line of thought like the following: The more priests there are
    in law and government, the better·. A greater number of
    priests, and their greater authority and riches, will always
    increase the religious spirit. And though the priests have the
    guidance of •this spirit, ·we can expect them also to develop
    ever greater moral decency in •their feelings·. Why should we
    not expect a superior sanctity of life, and greater benevolence
    and moderation, from people who are set apart for religion,
    who are continually preaching it to others, and who must
    themselves imbibe a greater share of it?

    Then how does it come about that in fact the most that
    a wise ruler can propose with regard to popular religions
    is, as far as possible, to make a saving game of it [= ‘to

    minimize losses without expecting any gains’], and to prevent their
    pernicious consequences with regard to society? Every
    means he uses to carry out this modest purpose is sur-
    rounded with inconveniences. •If he allows only one religion

    59

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    among his subjects, he must sacrifice every consideration of
    public liberty, science, reason, industry, and even his own
    independence—all this in return for an uncertain prospect
    of ·religious· peace. •If he allows several sects, which is
    the wiser course for him to follow, he must preserve a very
    philosophical even-handedness regarding all of them, and
    carefully restrain the claims of the dominant sect; other-
    wise he can expect nothing but endless disputes, quarrels,
    factions, persecutions, and civil commotions.

    True religion, I admit, has no such pernicious conse-
    quences; but we have to concern ourselves ·not with true
    religion, but· with religion as it has commonly been found
    in the world. And I am not discussing the speculative thesis
    of theism: being a philosophical theory, it must share in the
    beneficial influence of philosophy, while also suffering from
    philosophy’s drawback of being accepted by very few people.

    Oaths are required in all courts of law, but does their
    authority arise from any popular religion? ·I say No·. The
    chief restraints on mankind are •the solemnity and impor-
    tance of the occasion, •a concern for one’s reputation, and
    •reflection on the general interests of society. Custom-house
    oaths [= ‘declarations about what one is importing or exporting’] and
    political oaths are not regarded as binding even by some
    who claim to abide by principles of honesty and religion; and
    we rightly put a Quaker’s •assertion on the same footing
    as the •oath of any other person. I know that Polybius as-
    cribes the notorious untrustworthiness of the Greeks to the
    prevalence of the Epicurean philosophy; but I know also that
    Carthaginian promises had as bad a reputation in ancient
    times as Irish testimony does today, and we can’t account
    for these general impressions in the same way, ·namely the
    influence of Epicurean philosophy·. Not to mention that the
    Greeks were already notoriously untrustworthy before the
    rise of the Epicurean philosophy, and Euripides has aimed a

    remarkable stroke of satire against his nation, with regard
    to trustworthiness.

    Take care, Philo, replied Cleanthes, take care! Don’t
    push matters too far; don’t allow your zeal against false
    religion to undermine your reverence for the true. Don’t
    give up this ·religious· principle, which is the chief, the only
    great comfort in life, and our principal support amidst all
    the attacks of adverse fortune. The most agreeable reflection
    that the human imagination can possibly suggest is that of
    genuine theism, which represents us as the workmanship of
    a being who is perfectly good, wise, and powerful; a being
    who created us to be happy and who, having implanted in
    us immeasurable desires for good things, will prolong our
    existence to all eternity, taking us into an infinite variety
    of scenes in order to satisfy those desires, and make our
    happiness complete and lasting. To be under the guardian-
    ship and protection of such a divine being is the happiest
    prospect we can imagine—second only (if this comparison is
    permissible) to the happiness of the divine being himself.

    That picture of how a person seems to relate to religion,
    said Philo, is most engaging and alluring, and when the
    person is a true philosopher it is more than just seeming.
    But here as before, with regard to the greater part of mankind
    the appearances are deceitful, and the terrors of religion
    commonly prevail over its comforts.

    It is common knowledge that men never seek help from
    devotion so readily as when they are dejected with grief or
    depressed by sickness. Doesn’t that show that the religious
    spirit is not so closely tied to joy as it is to sorrow?

    But when men are afflicted they find consolation in
    religion, replied Cleanthes.

    Sometimes, said Philo; but it is natural to imagine that
    when they apply themselves to the contemplation of those
    unknown Beings—·the Gods of their religion·—they will form

    60

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    a notion of them that is suitable to their own present gloom
    and melancholy. Accordingly, we find in every religion that
    the images of God as fearsome predominate over all the other
    images of him; and we ourselves, after using the most exalted
    language in our descriptions of God, fall into the flattest
    contradiction when we affirm that the damned infinitely
    outnumber those who are chosen to be saved.

    I venture to assert that there has never been a popular
    religion which represented the state of departed souls in
    such a way as to make it a good thing from the human point of
    view that there should be such a state. These fine models of
    religion ·that you speak of so cheerfully, Cleanthes·, are the
    mere product of philosophy ·and get no grip on the ordinary
    thoughts and feelings of ordinary people·. When plain folk
    try to imagine the after-life, death intervenes between the
    mind’s eye and the object; and death is so shocking to nature
    that it throws a gloom on all the regions that lie on the far
    side of it, and suggests to the general run of people the
    idea of Cerberus and Furies, devils, and torrents of fire and
    brimstone.

    It is true that both •fear and •hope enter into religion,
    because both those passions agitate the human mind from
    time to time, and each of them forms a kind of divinity
    suitable to itself. But when a man is in a cheerful frame of
    mind he is fit for business, or company, or entertainment
    of any kind, and he naturally turns his attention to these
    and doesn’t think of religion. When gloomy and dejected,
    ·on the other hand, he hasn’t the spirit or energy to apply
    himself to anything in this world, so· all he can do is to
    brood on the terrors of the after-world, and ·thus· make
    his condition worse than ever. It may indeed happen that
    after he has in this way engraved the religious opinions deep
    into his thought and imagination, some change of health
    or circumstances restores his good-humour and, raising

    cheerful prospects of the after-life, send him to the other
    extreme of joy and triumph. But still it must be admitted
    that, as terror is the driving force of religion, it is the passion
    that always predominates in it, and allows for only short
    periods of pleasure.

    A further point: these bouts of excessive, extravagant joy,
    by exhausting the spirits, always prepare the way for equal
    bouts of superstitious terror and dejection. The happiest
    state of mind is ·not frenzied joy, but· balanced calm. But
    it is impossible for a man to remain long in that state when
    he thinks that he lies in such profound darkness and un-
    certainty •between an eternity of happiness and an eternity
    of misery. No wonder that •such an opinion unhinges the
    ordinary frame of the mind and throws it into the utmost
    confusion. And though •that opinion is seldom so steady in
    its operation that it influences all the person’s actions, it is
    apt to make considerable inroads on his temperament, and
    to produce the gloom and melancholy that are so noticeable
    in all devout people.

    It is contrary to common sense to be anxious or terrified
    ·about what may happen to us in the after-life· on account
    of any opinion that we have, or to imagine that the freest
    use of our reason will run us into any risk in the hereafter.
    Such a view implies both an absurdity and an inconsistency.
    It is an absurdity to believe that God has human passions,
    and indeed one of the lowest of them, namely a restless
    appetite for applause. It is an inconsistency to believe that
    God has this human passion but doesn’t have others also,
    and especially a disregard for the opinions of creatures so
    much inferior.

    To know God, says Seneca, is to worship him. All other
    worship—·that is, all worship that goes beyond expressing
    one’s knowledge that God exists·—is indeed absurd, supersti-
    tious, and even impious. It degrades God to the low condition

    61

    Dialogues concerning Natural Religion David Hume Part 12

    of ordinary men, who are delighted to be approached with
    entreaties, requests, presents, and flattery. Yet this is
    the least of the impieties of which superstition is guilty.
    Commonly, superstition pushes God down to a level far
    below that of mankind, and represents him as a capricious
    demon who exercises his power without reason and without
    humanity! If God were inclined to be offended at the vices
    and follies of silly mortals who are his own workmanship,
    the devotees of most popular superstitions would be in for
    a very bad time. None of the human race would deserve
    his •favour except for a very few, •the philosophical theists,
    who have—or at any rate try to have—suitable notions of
    his divine perfections; and the only persons entitled to his
    •compassion and leniency would be •the philosophical scep-
    tics, an almost equally small sect, whose natural modesty
    about their own capacities leads them to suspend—or try
    to suspend—all judgment with regard to such sublime and
    extraordinary subjects.

    If the whole of natural theology, as some people seem
    to maintain, boils down to one simple, though somewhat
    ambiguous or at least undefined proposition:

    •The cause or causes of order in the universe probably
    bear some remote analogy to human intelligence;

    if •this proposition can’t be extended, varied, or explained
    in more detail; if •it yields no inference that affects human
    life or can be the source of any action or forbearance from
    acting; and if •the analogy, imperfect as it is, extends only
    to human intelligence, and can’t plausibly be transferred
    to the other qualities of the mind—if all this really is the
    case, what can the most curious, thoughtful, and religious
    man do except •give a plain, philosophical assent to the

    proposition as often as it comes up, and •believe that the
    arguments on which it is based outweigh the objections
    against it? He will naturally feel somewhat unnerved by the
    greatness of the object, ·that is, by the thought of the cause
    of the universe·; somewhat sad that the object is hidden
    from him; somewhat contemptuous of human reason for
    its inability to make a better job of such an extraordinary
    and magnificent question. But believe me, Cleanthes, the
    most natural feeling that a well-disposed mind will have
    on this occasion is a longing desire and expectation [Hume’s

    phrase] that God will be pleased to remove or at least to lessen
    this profound ignorance, by giving mankind some particular
    revelation, revealing the nature, attributes, and operations
    of the divine object of our faith. A person who has a sound
    sense of the imperfections of natural reason will eagerly fly to
    revealed truth, while the haughty dogmatist, persuaded that
    he can erect a complete system of theology with no help but
    that of philosophy, will disdain any further aid and will reject
    this help from the outside. To be a philosophical sceptic is,
    in a man of letters, the first and most essential step towards
    being a sound, believing Christian; a proposition which I
    would willingly recommend to the attention of Pamphilus:
    and I hope Cleanthes will forgive me for interposing so far in
    the education and instruction of his pupil.

    Cleanthes and Philo did not pursue this conversation
    much further; and as nothing ever made greater impression
    on me than all the reasonings of that day, so I confess that
    on carefully looking over the whole conversation I cannot
    help thinking that Philo’s principles are more probable than
    Demea’s, but that those of Cleanthes approach still nearer
    to the truth.

    62

      Letter from Pamphilus to Hermippus

      Part 1

      Part 2

      Part 3

      Part 4

      Part 5

      Part 6

      Part 7

      Part 8

      Part 9

      Part 10

      Part 11

      Part 12

    Lesson 7: Ethical Theories, Consequentialism

    Ethical theories attempt to answer the question ‘what is a right or good action?’  Do we look at the results of an action to determine rightness or does motivation matter?  Perhaps we should look at the character of the agent who is performing the action. In this lesson we explore the idea that morality is determined by observing and evaluating the consequences of action.

    Ethical Egoism

    This folder contains material on Egoism and Contemporary views of Ethical Egoism .

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/egoism/

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/hobbes-moral/

    Utilitarianism

    This folder contains material on Utilitarian Ethics.

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/mill-moral-political/

    107

    14

    Kantian ethics

    ONORA O’NEILL

    i Introduction
    I K (1724–1804) was one of the most important European philosophers since antiquity; many would say simply that heMMANUEL ANT
    is the most important. He lived a notoriously uneventful life in the remote Prussian town of Königsberg (now Kaliningrad in the
    USSR), and published an array of significant works in his later years. His writings on ethics are marked by an unswerving
    commitment to human freedom, to the dignity of man, and to the view that moral obligation derives neither from God, nor from
    human authorities and communities, nor from the preferences or desires of human agents, but from reason.

    His writings are difficult and systematic; to understand them it helps to keep the following three things separate. First, there is
    Kant’s ethics, contained in his writings of the 1780s and 1790s. Secondly, there is ‘Kant’s ethics’, a (mainly unfavourable) account of
    Kant’s ethics developed by his early and influential critics and still often attributed to Kant. This position has an independent life in
    current debates. Thirdly, there is ‘Kantian ethics’, a much broader term which covers both Kant’s ethics and ‘Kant’s ethics’ and is also
    used as a (mainly admiring) label for a range of contemporary ethical positions which claim descent from Kant’s ethics, but which
    diverge from Kant in many ways.

    ii Kant’s ethics: the critical background
    Kant’s ethics is to be found in his (1785), (1787), Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals Critique of Practical Reason The

    (1797), (whose two parts, and are often publishedMetaphysics of Morals The Metaphysical Elements of Justice The Doctrine of Virtue
    separately), as well as in his (1793) and a large number of essays on political, historical andReligion within the Limits of Reason Alone
    religious themes. However, the fundamental moves that determine the shape of this work are most fully discussed in Kant’s
    masterpiece, (1781), and an account of his ethics has to be set in the wider context of the ‘criticalThe Critique of Pure Reason
    philosophy’ which he develops there.

    This philosophy is in the first place critical in a negative sense. Kant argues against most of the metaphysical claims of his
    rationalist predecessors, and in particular against their supposed proofs of the existence of God. On his account our thinking has to be
    undertaken from a human standpoint, and we can vindicate no claims about any transcendent reality to which we have no access. The
    knowledge claims that we can vindicate must therefore be about a reality that meets the condition of being experienceable by us.
    Hence an inquiry into the structure of our cognitive capacities yields a guide to the aspects of that empirical reality which we can know
    without referring to particular experiences. Kant argues that we can know a priori that we inhabit a natural world of spatially and
    temporally extended objects that are causally connected.

    Kant is distinctive for insisting that this causal order and our claims to knowledge are restricted to the natural world, but that we
    have no reason to think that the knowable natural world is all there is. On the contrary, we have and cannot do without a conception of
    ourselves as agents and as moral beings which makes sense only on the assumption that we have free will. Kant argues that free will
    and natural causality are compatible, provided that human freedom – the capacity to act autonomously – is not taken to be an aspect of
    the natural world. Causality and freedom apply in separate domains; knowledge is restricted to the former and morality to the latter.
    Kant’s resolution of the problem of freedom and determinism is the most controversial and fundamental feature of his moral
    philosophy, and the one that creates the greatest difference between his thought and that of nearly all twentieth-century writing on
    ethics, including most that is classified as ‘Kantian ethics’.

    The central question around which Kant arranges his discussion of ethics is ‘What ought I do?’. He tries to identify the maxims, or
    fundamental principles of action, that we ought to adopt. His answer is developed without reference to any supposedly objective
    account of the good for man, such as those proposed by the perfectionist positions that we associate with Plato, Aristotle and much
    Christian ethics. Nor does he base his position on claims about whatever subjective conceptions of the good, desires, preferences, or
    commonly shared moral beliefs we may happen to have, in the way that utilitarians and communitarians do. As in his metaphysics, so
    in his ethics, he neither introduces claims about a moral reality that transcends our experience nor assigns moral weight to actual
    beliefs. He repudiates both the realist and theological framework within which natural law theory and accounts of the virtues had been
    developed, and the appeal to a contingent consensus of feeling or belief on which many eighteenth (and twentieth!) century writers
    rely.

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    1
    99
    3.
    W
    il

    ey
    -B
    la
    ck
    we
    ll
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re
    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or
    a
    pp
    li
    ca
    bl
    e

    co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    la
    w.

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/24/2017 3:16 PM via TARRANT COUNTY COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 44509 ; Singer, Peter.; A Companion to Ethics
    Account: tarrant

    108

    iii Kant’s ethics: universal law and the construction
    of duty
    Kant’s central move is to construct the principles of ethics according to rational procedures. Although he begins his Groundwork
    (which is short, famous and difficult) by identifying a as the only unconditional good, he denies that the principles of goodgood will
    willing can be fixed by reference to an objective good or at which they aim. Rather than assuming a determinate account of thetelos
    good, and using this as the basis for determing what we ought to do, he uses an account of the principles of ethics to determine what it
    is to have a good will. He asks only one rather minimal question: what maxims or fundamental principles could be adopted by a
    plurality of agents without assuming specific about the agents’ desires or their social relations? Principles that cannot serveanything
    for a plurality of agents are to be rejected: the thought is that nothing could be a moral principle which cannot be a principle for all.
    Morality begins with the rejection of non-universalizable principles. This idea is formulated as a demand, which Kant calls ‘the
    Categorical Imperative’, or more generally the Moral Law. In its best known version it runs: ‘Act only on the maxim through which
    you can at the same time will that it be a universal law’. This is the keystone of Kant’s ethics, and is used to classify the maxims
    agents may adopt.

    An example of the use of the Categorical Imperative would be this: an agent who adopts a maxim of promising falsely could not
    ‘will it as a universal law’. For if she were (hypothetically) to do so she would be committed to the predictable result that trust would
    break down so that she could not act on her initial maxim of promising falsely. This thought experiment reveals that a maxim of false
    promising is not universalizable, hence cannot be included among the shared principles of any plurality of beings. The maxim of
    rejecting false promising is morally required; the maxim of promising falsely morally forbidden. It is important to note that Kant does
    not think false promising wrong because of its presumed unpleasant effects (as utilitarians would) but because it cannot be willed as a
    universal principle.

    The rejection of a maxim of false promising, or of any other non-universalizable maxim, is compatible with a wide variety of
    courses of action. Kant distinguishes two modes of ethical assessment. In the first place we might evaluate the maxims that agents
    adopt. If we could discern these we would be able to pick out those who reject non-universalizable principles (so have morally worthy
    principles) and those who adopt non-universalizable principles, (so have morally unworthy principles). Kant speaks of those who hold
    morally worthy principles as acting ‘out of duty’. However, Kant also holds that we do not have certain knowledge either of our own
    or of others’ maxims. We normally infer agents’ maxims or underlying principles from the pattern of their action, yet no pattern will
    pick out a unique maxim. For example, the activity of the genuinely honest shopkeeper may not differ from that of the reluctantly
    honest shopkeeper, who deals fairly only out of desire for a good business reputation and would cheat if a safe opportunity arose.
    Hence for ordinary purposes we can often do no more than concern ourselves with outward conformity to maxims of duty, rather than
    with claims that an act was done out of such a maxim. Kant speaks of action that would have to be done by anyone who had a morally
    worthy maxim as action ‘in accordance with duty’. Such action is obligatory and its omission forbidden. Evidently, many acts accord
    with duty although they were not done out of maxims of duty. However, even this notion of outward duty has been defined by
    reference to being indispensable in a given situation for one who holds underlying principles of acting out of duty. This is in sharp
    contrast with contemporary accounts of duty which identify it with patterns of outward action. Kant’s question ‘What ought I do?’
    therefore receives a double answer. I ought at best to base my life and action on the rejection of non-universalizable maxims, and so
    lead a morally worthy life whose acts are done out of duty; but even if I fail to do this I ought at least to make sure to do any acts that
    would be indispensable if I had such a morally worthy maxim.

    Kant’s more detailed account of duty introduces (versions of) certain traditional distinctions. He contrasts duties to self and others,
    and under each of these distinguishes perfect and imperfect duties. duties are complete, in the sense that they hold for allPerfect
    agents in all their actions with all possible others. In addition to refraining from false promising, refraining from coercion and violence
    are examples of principles of perfect duties to others; they are obligations which can be met for all others, (to which negative liberty
    rights may correspond). Kant derives principles of obligation by introducing one further assumption: he takes it that we notimperfect
    only have to deal with a plurality of rational agents who share a world, but that these agents are not self-sufficient, hence are mutually
    vulnerable. Such agents, he argues, could not rationally will that a principle of refusing to help others or of neglecting to develop one’s
    own potential be universally adopted: since they know that they are not self-sufficient, they know that to will such a world would be
    (irrationally) to will away indispensable means to at least some of their own ends. The principles of not neglecting to help those in
    need or to develop one’s own potential are, however, less complete (hence imperfect) principles of obligation. For we cannot help all
    others in all needed ways, nor can we develop all possible talents in ourselves. Hence these obligations are necessarily selective as
    well as indeterminate. They lack counterpart rights and are the basis for imperfect duties. The implications of this account of duties are
    most fully developed in the , whose first part deals with the principles of justice that are matters of perfectMetaphysics of Morals
    obligation and whose second part deals with the principles of virtue that are matters of imperfect obligation.

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    1
    99
    3.
    W
    il

    ey
    -B
    la
    ck
    we
    ll
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re
    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or
    a
    pp
    li
    ca
    bl
    e

    co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    la
    w.

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/24/2017 3:16 PM via TARRANT COUNTY COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 44509 ; Singer, Peter.; A Companion to Ethics
    Account: tarrant

    109

    iv Kant’s ethics: respect for persons
    Kant develops his basic lines of thought along a number of parallel (he claims equivalent) tracks. The Categorical Imperative is
    formulated in a number of strikingly different versions. The formulation discussed above is known as ‘The Formula of Universal
    Law’, and is said to be the ‘strictest’. The one that has had the greatest cultural impact is the so-called ‘Formula of the End in Itself’,
    which demands that we treat ‘humanity in your own person or in the person of any other never simply as a means but always at the
    same time as an end’. This second-order principle is once again a constraint on the maxims we adopt; it is a highly articulated version
    of a demand for respect for persons. Instead of demanding that we check that all could adopt the same maxims, it demands less
    directly that we act in ways that respect, so leave intact, others’ capacities to act (and so, in effect, leave them able to act on the
    maxims we ourselves adopt). The Formula of the End in Itself is also used to distinguish two sorts of moral failure. To use another is
    to treat him or her as a thing or tool and not as an agent. On Kant’s account to use another is not merely a matter of doing something
    the other does not actually want or consent to, but of doing something to which the other consent. For example, deceivers makecannot
    it for their victims to consent to the deceiver’s project. Unlike most other appeals to consent as a criterion of legitimate (orimpossible
    just) action, Kant (in keeping with his basic philosophical position) appeals neither to the hypothetical consent of ideally rational
    beings, nor to the historically contingent consent of actual others. He asks what is needed to make it possible for others either to
    dissent or consent. This does not mean that actual dissent may be coercively overridden on the grounds that consent has at least been
    made possible – for the very act of overriding actual dissent will itself coerce, hence make consent impossible. Kant’s contention is
    that the principles we must adopt if we are not to use others will be the very principles of justice that were identified by considering
    which principles are universalizable for rational beings.

    Correspondingly, Kant interprets the moral failure of not treating others as ‘ends’ as an alternative basis for an account of the
    virtues. To treat others who are specifically human in their finitude – hence vulnerable and needy – as ‘ends’ requires that we support
    one another’s (fragile) capacities to act, to adopt maxims and to pursue their particular ends. Hence it requires at least some support for
    others’ projects and purposes. Kant holds that this will require at least a limited beneficence. Although he does not establish an
    unrestricted obligation of beneficence, such as utilitarians hold to, he does argue for an obligation to reject a policy of refusing needed
    help. He also argues that systematic failure to develop one’s own potential amounts to disrespect for humanity and its capacities for
    rational agency ‘in one’s own person’. Failure to treat others or oneself as ends is once again seen as a failure of virtue or imperfect
    obligation. Imperfect obligations cannot prescribe universal performance: we can neither help all in need, nor develop all possible
    talents. We can, however, refuse to make indifference of either sort basic to our lives – and may find that rejecting principled
    indifference demands a lot. Even a commitment of this nature, taken seriously, will demand much. If we honour it, we have on Kant’s
    account shown respect for persons and specifically for human dignity.

    The remaining formulations of the Categorical Imperative bring together the perspectives of one who seeks to act on principles that
    all others could share, and one who seeks to act on principles that respect all others’ capacities to act. Kant makes use of traditional
    Christian rhetoric and of Rousseau’s conception of the social contract to formulate the image of a ‘Kingdom of Ends’ where each is
    simultaneously legislator and bound by law, where each is autonomous (literally: self-legislating) on condition that what is legislated
    is respect for others’ like status as ‘legislators’. For Kant, as for Rousseau, to be autonomous is no mere matter of wilfulness or
    independence from others or from social conventions; it is to have the mode of self-control that takes account of others’ like moral
    status. To be Kantianly autonomous is to act morally.

    v Kant’s ethics: the problems of freedom, religion
    and history
    This basic structure of thought is developed in many different directions. Kant presents arguments to suggest why we should think of
    the Categorical Imperative as a principle of reason that is binding on us. He explores what is involved in moving from a principle to its
    concrete application to actual situations. He discusses the relationship between moral principles and our actual desires and inclinations.
    He develops the political implications of the Categorical Imperative, which include a republican constitution and respect for freedom,
    especially of religion and speech. He sketches a still influential programme for seeking international peace. He explores how his
    system of moral thought is connected to traditional religious claims. Many objections of principle and of detail have been raised. Some
    of the less fundamental objections can be conveniently discussed under the heading of ‘Kant’s ethics’. However, the most central
    objection demands independent discussion.

    This objection is that Kant’s basic framework is incoherent. His account of human knowledge leads to a conception of human
    beings as parts of nature, whose desires, inclinations and actions are susceptible of ordinary causal explanation. Yet his account of
    human freedom demands that we view human agents as capable of self-determination, and specifically of determination in accordance
    with the principles of duty. Kant is apparently driven to a dual view of man: we are both (natural, causally determined)phenomenal
    beings and (non-natural, selfdetermining) beings. Many of Kant’s critics have held that this dual-aspect view of humannoumenal
    beings is ultimately incoherent.

    In the Kant tackles the difficulty by proposing that provided we accept certain ‘postulates’ we canCritique of Practical Reason
    make sense of the idea of beings who are part both of the natural and of the moral order. The idea is that if we postulate a benevolent
    God, then the moral virtue at which free agents aim can be compatible with, indeed proportioned to, the happiness at which natural

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    1
    99
    3.
    W
    il

    ey
    -B
    la
    ck
    we
    ll
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re
    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or
    a
    pp
    li
    ca
    bl
    e

    co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    la
    w.

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/24/2017 3:16 PM via TARRANT COUNTY COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 44509 ; Singer, Peter.; A Companion to Ethics
    Account: tarrant

    110

    beings aim. Kant speaks of such perfect co-ordination of moral virtue and happiness as the highest good. Producing the highest good
    will take a long time: so we have to postulate immortal souls as well as divine providence. This picture has been lampooned time and
    again. Heine depicted Kant as a bold revolutionary who killed deism: then timidly conceded that practical reason could ‘prove’ God
    after all. Nietzsche less kindly likens him to a fox who escapes – then slinks back into the cage of theism.

    In later writings Kant dropped both the idea of a guaranteed co-ordination of virtue and rewarding happiness (he thought this might
    undermine true virtue) and the demand that we postulate immortality, understood as everlasting life (see ). HeThe End of All Things
    offers a variety of historized versions of the thought that we can make sense of our status as free beings who are part of nature only if
    we adopt certain postulates. For example, he suggests that we must at least for the possibility of moral improvement in humanhope
    history, and so for a co-ordination of the moral and natural ends of mankind. The various historicized accounts he offersthis-worldly
    of the postulates of practical reason are aspects and precursors of a this-worldly account of human destiny that we associate with the
    revolutionary tradition, and specially with Marx. However, Kant did not renounce a religious interpretation of claims about human
    origins and destiny. In his late work he depicts Christian scriptures as a temporal narrativeReligion within the Limits of Reasons Alone
    which can be understood as a ‘symbol of morality’. The interpretation of this work, which got Kant into trouble with the Prussian
    censors, presents many problems. However, it is at least clear that he does not reintroduce theological claims to serve as a foundation
    for morality, but rather uses his moral theory as a lens for reading scripture.

    If Kant did not go back on his original repudiation of theological foundations, an understanding of the connection he sees between
    nature and morality remains problematic. One way of understanding it may be by relying on the idea, which he uses in ,Groundwork
    that nature and freedom do not belong in two independent worlds, or metaphysical realities, but rather constitute two ‘standpoints’. We
    must see ourselves both as parts of the natural world and as free agents. We cannot without incoherence do without either of these
    standpoints, although we cannot integrate them, and can do no more than understand thay are compatible. On such a reading, wethat
    can have no insight into the ‘mechanics’ of human freedom, but can understand that without freedom in the activity of cognition,
    which lies behind our very claims to know, a causally ordered world would be unknown to us. Hence it is impossible for us to think
    freedom away. For practical purposes this may be enough: for these we do not need to human freedom. However, we are leftprove
    trying to conceptualize the hiatus between the natural order and human freedom, and must also commit ourselves to some version of
    the ‘postulates’ or ‘hopes’ that connect the two. At the very least a commitment to acting morally in the world depends on assuming
    (postulating, hoping) that the natural order is not wholly incompatible with moral intentions.

    vi ‘Kant’s ethics’
    Many other criticisms of Kant’s ethics recur so often that they have acquired an independent life as elements of ‘Kant’s ethics’. Some
    hold that these criticisms do not apply to Kant’s ethics, others that they are decisive reasons for rejecting Kant’s position.

    (1) . The commonest charge against Kant’s ethics is the allegation that the Categorical Imperative is empty, trivial orFormalism
    purely formal and identifies no principles of duty. The charge has been widely made by Hegel, by J. S. Mill and in many
    contemporary works. On Kant’s own view the demand for universalizable maxims is a demand that our fundamental principles
    be fit for adoption by all. This condition can seem pointless: for cannot well-formed act-description be prescribed by aany
    universal principle? Are principles such as ‘steal when you can’ or ‘kill when it isn’t risky’ universalizable? This reductio ad

    of universalizability is achieved by replacing Kant’s Categorical Imperative with a different principle. The Formulaabsurdum
    of Universal Law demands not just that we formulate a universal principle incorporating some act-description that applies to a
    given act. It demands that an agent’s maxim, or fundamental principle, be such that the agent can ‘will it as universal law’. The
    test requires commitment to the normal, predictable consequences of principles to which the agent is committed and to normal
    standards of instrumental rationality. When maxims are non-universalizable this is typically because commitment to the
    consequences of their universal adoption would be incompatible with commitment to the means of acting on them (e.g. we
    cannot be committed both to the results of universal false promising, and to preserving the means to promising, hence to false
    promising).
    Kant’s account of universalizability differs from related principles (universal prescriptivism, Golden Rules) in two major
    respects. First, it does not refer to what is desired or preferred, not even to what it is desired or preferred should be universally
    done. Second, it is a procedure only for picking out the maxims that must be rejected if the fundamental principles of a life or a
    society are to be universalizable. Non-universalizable principles are identified in order to discover the side constraints on the
    more specific principles agents may adopt. These side constraints enable us to identify more specific but still indeterminate
    principles of obligation. (For a different account of universalizability, see Article 40, UNIVERSAL PRESCRIPTIVISM.)
    (2) . This is the claim that Kant’s ethics, far from being empty and formalistic, leads to rigidly insensitive rules, and soRigorism
    cannot take account of differences between cases. However, universal principles need not mandate uniform treatment; indeed
    they may mandate differentiated treatment. Principles such as ‘taxation should be proportionate to ability to pay’ or ‘the
    punishment must fit the crime’ are universal in scope but demand differentiated treatment. Even principles that do not
    specifically mandate differentiated treatment will be indeterminate, so leave room for differentiated application.
    (3) . Those who concede that Kant’s arguments identify some principles of duty, but do not impose rigid uniformity,Abstraction
    often advance a further version of the formalism charge. They will say that Kant identifies ethical principles, but that these
    principles are ‘too abstract’ to guide action, hence his theory is not action-guiding. Kant’s principles of duty certainly are
    abstract, and he does not provide a detailed set of instructions for following them. There is no moral algorithm of the sort
    utilitarianism might provide if we had sufficiently full information about all options. Kant emphasizes that the application of
    principles to cases involves judgement and deliberation. He also maintains that principles are and must be abstract: they are
    side-constraints (not algorithms) and can only guide (not make) decisions. The moral life is a matter of finding ways of actingCo
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    1
    99
    3.
    W
    il

    ey
    -B
    la
    ck
    we
    ll
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re
    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or
    a
    pp
    li
    ca
    bl
    e

    co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    la
    w.

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/24/2017 3:16 PM via TARRANT COUNTY COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 44509 ; Singer, Peter.; A Companion to Ethics
    Account: tarrant

    111

    that meet all obligations and violate no moral prohibitions. There is no automatic procedure for identifying such actions, or all
    such actions. However, for moral practice we begin by making sure that the specific acts we have in mind are not incompatible
    with acts on maxims of duty.
    (4) . This criticism points out that Kant’s ethics identifies a set of principles which may comeConflicting grounds of obligation
    into conflict. The demands of fidelity and of helpfulness, for example, may clash. This criticism is true of Kant’s ethics, as for
    any ethic of principles. Since ‘trade-offs’ between differing obligations are not part of the theory, there is no routine procedure
    for dealing with conflicts. On the other hand, since the theory is only a set of side constraints on action, the central demand is to
    find some action that falls within all constraints. Only when no such action can be found does the problem of multiple grounds
    of obligation arise. Kant has nothing very illuminating to say about these cases; the charge made by advocates of virtue ethics
    (e.g. Bernard Williams, Martha Nussbaum), that he does not say enough about the regret that may be appropriate when some
    moral commitment has unavoidably to be violated or neglected, is apposite.
    (5) . A group of serious criticisms of Kant’s moral psychology occurs throughout the secondaryPlace of the inclinations
    literature. In particular it is said that Kant requires that we act ‘out of the motive of duty’, hence not out of inclination, and so is
    driven to the claim that action which we enjoy cannot be morally worthy. This grim interpretation, perhaps first suggested by
    Schiller, involves a tangle of difficult issues. By acting ‘out of the motive of duty’, Kant means only that we act on a maxim of
    duty and so experience a feeling of ‘reverence for the law’. This reverence is a to and not the of moral worth. Itresponse source
    is compatible with action being in line with our natural inclinations and so enjoyed. On one view the apparent conflict between
    duty and inclination is only epistemological; we can know for sure that we act out of duty only if inclination is lacking. On other
    views, the issue runs deeper, and leads to a more serious charge that Kant cannot account for wrongdoing.
    (6) . This charge is that Kant can allow only for free action which is fully autonomous – i.e. done on aNo account of wrongdoing
    principle that meets the constraint that all others can do likewise – and for action which reflects only natural desires and
    inclinations. Hence he cannot allow for free, imputable but wrong action. Clearly Kant thinks he can give an account of wrong
    doing, for he frequently gives examples of imputable wrongdoing. This charge probably reflects a failure to keep separate the
    claim that free agents must be capable of acting autonomously (in the distinctive Rousseauian or Kantian sense which links
    autonomy with morality) with the claim that free agents always act autonomously. Imputability requires the capacity to act
    autonomously but this capacity may not always be exercised. Wrongful acts are indeed not autonomous, but they are chosen
    rather than inflicted mechanically by our desires or inclinations.

    vii Kantian ethics
    Kant’s ethics and the image of his ethics which often replaces it in modern debates do not exhaust Kantian ethics. This term is now
    often used to cover any of a range of quasi-Kantian positions or commitments in ethics. Sometimes the usage is very broad. Certain
    writers will talk of Kantian ethics when they have in mind theories of rights, or more generally action-based rather than result-based
    moral thinking, or any position that treats the right as prior to the good. In these cases the points of resemblance to Kant’s ethics are
    fairly general – for example, concern with universal principles and respect for persons, or more specifically for human rights. In other
    cases a more structural resemblance may be indicated – for example, a commitment to a single non-utilitarian supreme moral
    principle, or to the view that ethics is based on reason. The specific understanding of Kantian ethics varies very much from context to
    context.

    The most definite Kantian programme in ethics recently has been that of John Rawls, who has labelled one stage in the
    development of his theory ‘Kantian constructivism’. Many features of Rawls’s work are clearly Kantian, above all his conception of
    ethical principles as determined by constraints on principles chosen by rational agents. However, Rawls’s constructivism assumes a
    quite different account of rationality from Kant’s. Rawls identifies the principles that be chosen by instrumentally rationalwould
    beings to whom he ascribes certain sparsely specified ends – not the principles that consistently be chosen regardless ofcould
    particular ends. This produces far-ranging differences between Rawls’s work, even at its most Kantian, and Kant’s ethics. Others who
    use the label ‘Kantian’ in ethics are even more loosely related to Kant – for example, many of them offer no account of the virtues, or
    even deny that an account is possible; many treat rights rather than obligations as fundamental; nearly all rely on a preference-based
    theory of action and an instrumental account of rationality, all of which are incompatible with Kant’s ethics.

    viii The Kantian legacy
    Kant’s ethics remains the paradigmatic and most influential attempt to vindicate universal moral principles without reference to
    preferences or to a theological framework. The hope of identifying universal principles, which is so apparent in discussions of justice
    and in the human rights movement, is constantly challenged by communitarian and historicist insistence that we cannot appeal beyond
    the discourse and traditions of particular societies, and by utilitarian insistence that principles derive from preferences. For those who
    find neither of these routes compelling, the neo-Kantian slogan ‘Back to Kant’ remains a challenge which they must explore or refute.

    References

    Works by Kant

    Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals; trans. H. J. Paton, as (London: Hutchinson, 1953).The Moral LawCo
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    1
    99
    3.
    W
    il

    ey
    -B
    la
    ck
    we
    ll
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re
    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or
    a
    pp
    li
    ca
    bl
    e

    co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    la
    w.

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/24/2017 3:16 PM via TARRANT COUNTY COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 44509 ; Singer, Peter.; A Companion to Ethics
    Account: tarrant

    112

    Critique of Practical Reason: trans. L. W. Beck (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1977).

    Religion Within the Limits of Reason Alone; trans. T. M. Greene, and H. H. Hudson (New York: Harper and Row, 1960).

    The Metaphysic of Morals. There is no English translation of the entire work. The first part appears as The Metaphysical Elements of
    , trans. J. Ladd (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1965), and the second as , trans. M. Gregor (New York:Justice The Doctrine of Virtue

    Harper and Row, 1964). Both translations contain the introduction to the .Metaphysic of Morals

    Also two anthologies of his shorter writings – H. Reiss, ed.: (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970)Kant’s Political Writings
    and L. W. Beck, ed.: , Library of Liberal Arts (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1963).On History

    Other references

    Nussbaum, M.: (Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityThe Fragility of Goodness: Luck and Ethics in Greek Tragedy and Philosophy
    Press, 1986).

    Rawls, J.: (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1971).A Theory of Justice

    _____: ‘Kantian constructivism and moral theory’, , LXXVII (1980), 515–72.Journal of Philosophy

    Williams, B.: (London: Fontana, 1985).Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy

    Further reading

    Works on Kant’s ethics

    Beck, L. W.: (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960).A Commentary on Kant’s Critique of Practical Reason

    H. Paton, (London: Hutchinson & Co., 1947).The Categorical Imperative

    O’Neill, O.: (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).Constructions of Reason: Explorations of Kant’s Practical Philosophy

    For discussion of ‘Kant’s ethics’

    MacIntyre, A.: (London: Duckworth, 1981).After Virtue

    For recent Kantian ethics

    Nozick, R.: (Oxford: Blackwell, 1974).Anarchy, State and Utopia

    Gewirth, A.: (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982).Human Rights: Essays on Justifications and Applications

    Co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    ©
    1
    99
    3.
    W
    il

    ey
    -B
    la
    ck
    we
    ll
    .
    Al
    l
    ri
    gh
    ts
    r
    es
    er
    ve
    d.
    M
    ay
    n
    ot
    b
    e
    re
    pr
    od
    uc
    ed
    i
    n
    an
    y
    fo
    rm
    w
    it
    ho
    ut
    p
    er
    mi
    ss
    io
    n
    fr
    om
    t
    he
    p
    ub
    li
    sh
    er
    ,
    ex
    ce
    pt
    f
    ai
    r
    us
    es
    p
    er
    mi
    tt
    ed
    u
    nd
    er
    U
    .S
    .
    or
    a
    pp
    li
    ca
    bl
    e

    co
    py
    ri
    gh
    t
    la
    w.

    EBSCO Publishing : eBook Collection (EBSCOhost) – printed on 5/24/2017 3:16 PM via TARRANT COUNTY COLLEGE DISTRICT
    AN: 44509 ; Singer, Peter.; A Companion to Ethics
    Account: tarrant

  • Universal Declaration of Human Rights
  • Preamble

    Whereas recognition of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable

    rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of freedom, justice

    and peace in the world,

    Whereas disregard and contempt for human rights have resulted in barbarous

    acts which have outraged the conscience of mankind, and the advent of a world

    in which human beings shall enjoy freedom of speech and belief and freedom

    from fear and want has been proclaimed as the highest aspiration of the common

    people,

    Whereas it is essential, if man is not to be compelled to have recourse, as a last

    resort, to rebellion against tyranny and oppression, that human rights should be

    protected by the rule of law,

    Whereas it is essential to promote the development of friendly relations between

    nations,

    Whereas the peoples of the United Nations have in the Charter reaffirmed their

    faith in fundamental human rights, in the dignity and worth of the human person

    and in the equal rights of men and women and have determined to promote

    social progress and better standards of life in larger freedom,

    Whereas Member States have pledged themselves to achieve, in cooperation

    with the United Nations, the promotion of universal respect for and observance of

    human rights and fundamental freedoms,

    Whereas a common understanding of these rights and freedoms is of the

    greatest importance for the full realization of this pledge,

    Now, therefore,

    The General Assembly,

    Proclaims this Universal Declaration of Human Rights as a common standard of

    achievement for all peoples and all nations, to the end that every individual and

    every organ of society, keeping this Declaration constantly in mind, shall strive by

    teaching and education to promote respect for these rights and freedoms and by

    progressive measures, national and international, to secure their universal and

    effective recognition and observance, both among the peoples of Member States

    themselves and among the peoples of territories under their jurisdiction.

    Article I

    All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. They are

    endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a

    spirit of brotherhood.

    Article 2

    Everyone is entitled to all the rights and freedoms set forth in this Declaration,

    without distinction of any kind, such as race, colour, sex, language, religion,

    political or other opinion, national or social origin, property, birth or other status.

    Furthermore, no distinction shall be made on the basis of the political,

    jurisdictional or international status of the country or territory to which a person

    belongs, whether it be independent, trust, non-self-governing or under any other

    limitation of sovereignty.

    Article 3

    Everyone has the right to life, liberty and the security of person.

    Article 4

    No one shall be held in slavery or servitude; slavery and the slave trade shall be

    prohibited in all their forms.

    Article 5

    No one shall be subjected to torture or to cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment

    or punishment.

    Article 6

    Everyone has the right to recognition everywhere as a person before the law.

    Article 7

    All are equal before the law and are entitled without any discrimination to equal

    protection of the law. All are entitled to equal protection against any

    discrimination in violation of this Declaration and against any incitement to such

    discrimination.

    Article 8

    Everyone has the right to an effective remedy by the competent national tribunals

    for acts violating the fundamental rights granted him by the constitution or by law.

    Article 9

    No one shall be subjected to arbitrary arrest, detention or exile.

    Article 10

    Everyone is entitled in full equality to a fair and public hearing by an independent

    and impartial tribunal, in the determination of his rights and obligations and of any

    criminal charge against him.

    Article 11

    1. Everyone charged with a penal offence has the right to be presumed

    innocent until proved guilty according to law in a public trial at which he

    has had all the guarantees necessary for his defence.

    2. No one shall be held guilty of any penal offence on account of any act or

    omission which did not constitute a penal offence, under national or

    international law, at the time when it was committed. Nor shall a heavier

    penalty be imposed than the one that was applicable at the time the penal

    offence was committed.

    Article 12

    No one shall be subjected to arbitrary interference with his privacy, family, home

    or correspondence, nor to attacks upon his honour and reputation. Everyone has

    the right to the protection of the law against such interference or attacks.

    Article 13

    1. Everyone has the right to freedom of movement and residence within the

    borders of each State.

    2. Everyone has the right to leave any country, including his own, and to

    return to his country.

    Article 14

    1. Everyone has the right to seek and to enjoy in other countries asylum from

    persecution.

    2. This right may not be invoked in the case of prosecutions genuinely

    arising from non-political crimes or from acts contrary to the purposes and

    principles of the United Nations.

    Article 15

    1. Everyone has the right to a nationality.

    2. No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his nationality nor denied the right to

    change his nationality.

    Article 16

    1. Men and women of full age, without any limitation due to race, nationality

    or religion, have the right to marry and to found a family. They are entitled

    to equal rights as to marriage, during marriage and at its dissolution.

    2. Marriage shall be entered into only with the free and full consent of the

    intending spouses.

    3. The family is the natural and fundamental group unit of society and is

    entitled to protection by society and the State.

    Article 17

    1. Everyone has the right to own property alone as well as in association with

    others.

    2. No one shall be arbitrarily deprived of his property.

    Article 18

    Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right

    includes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom, either alone or in

    community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in

    teaching, practice, worship and observance.

    Article 19

    Everyone has the right to freedom of opinion and expression; this right includes

    freedom to hold opinions without interference and to seek, receive and impart

    information and ideas through any media and regardless of frontiers.

    Article 20

    1. Everyone has the right to freedom of peaceful assembly and association.

    2. No one may be compelled to belong to an association.

    Article 21

    1. Everyone has the right to take part in the government of his country,

    directly or through freely chosen representatives.

    2. Everyone has the right to equal access to public service in his country.

    3. The will of the people shall be the basis of the authority of government;

    this will shall be expressed in periodic and genuine elections which shall

    be by universal and equal suffrage and shall be held by secret vote or by

    equivalent free voting procedures.

    Article 22

    Everyone, as a member of society, has the right to social security and is entitled

    to realization, through national effort and international co-operation and in

    accordance with the organization and resources of each State, of the economic,

    social and cultural rights indispensable for his dignity and the free development

    of his personality.

    Article 23

    1. Everyone has the right to work, to free choice of employment, to just and

    favourable conditions of work and to protection against unemployment.

    2. Everyone, without any discrimination, has the right to equal pay for equal

    work.

    3. Everyone who works has the right to just and favourable remuneration

    ensuring for himself and his family an existence worthy of human dignity,

    and supplemented, if necessary, by other means of social

    protection.

    4. Everyone has the right to form and to join trade unions for the protection of

    his interests.

    Article 24

    Everyone has the right to rest and leisure, including reasonable limitation of

    working hours and periodic holidays with pay.

    Article 25

    1. Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the health and

    well-being of himself and of his family, including food, clothing, housing

    and medical care and necessary social services, and the right to security

    in the event of unemployment, sickness, disability, widowhood, old age or

    other lack of livelihood in circumstances beyond his control.

    2. Motherhood and childhood are entitled to special care and assistance. All

    children, whether born in or out of wedlock, shall enjoy the same social

    protection.

    Article 26

    1. Everyone has the right to education. Education shall be free, at least in the

    elementary and fundamental stages. Elementary education shall be

    compulsory. Technical and professional education shall be made

    generally available and higher education shall be equally accessible to all

    on the basis of merit.

    2. Education shall be directed to the full development of the human

    personality and to the strengthening of respect for human rights and

    fundamental freedoms. It shall promote understanding, tolerance and

    friendship among all nations, racial or religious groups, and shall further

    the activities of the United Nations for the maintenance of peace.

    3. Parents have a prior right to choose the kind of education that shall be

    given to their children.

    Article 27

    1. Everyone has the right freely to participate in the cultural life of the

    community, to enjoy the arts and to share in scientific advancement and

    its benefits.

    2. Everyone has the right to the protection of the moral and material interests

    resulting from any scientific, literary or artistic production of which he is the

    author.

    Article 28

    Everyone is entitled to a social and international order in which the rights and

    freedoms set forth in this Declaration can be fully realized.

    Article 29

    1. Everyone has duties to the community in which alone the free and full

    development of his personality is possible.

    2. In the exercise of his rights and freedoms, everyone shall be subject only

    to such limitations as are determined by law solely for the purpose of

    securing due recognition and respect for the rights and freedoms of others

    and of meeting the just requirements of morality, public order and the

    general welfare in a democratic society.

    3. These rights and freedoms may in no case be exercised contrary to the

    purposes and principles of the United Nations.

    Article 30

    Nothing in this Declaration may be interpreted as implying for any State, group or

    person any right to engage in any activity or to perform any act aimed at the

    destruction of any of the rights and freedoms set forth herein.

      Universal Declaration of Human Rights

      Preamble

      Article I

      Article 2

      Article 3

      Article 4

      Article 5

      Article 6

      Article 7

      Article 8

      Article 9

      Article 10

      Article 11

      Article 12

      Article 13

      Article 14

      Article 15

      Article 16

      Article 17

      Article 18

      Article 19

      Article 20

      Article 21

      Article 22

      Article 23

      Article 24

      Article 25

      Article 26

      Article 27

      Article 28

      Article 29

      Article 30

    Lesson 8: Ethical Theories, Deontology

    Ethical theories attempt to answer the question ‘what is a right or good action?’  Do we look at the results of an action to determine rightness or does motivation matter?  Perhaps we should look at the character of the agent who is performing the action. In this lesson we explore the idea of doing one’s duty for the right reasons. In addition, we explore the notion of having rights.

    Kantian Ethics

    This folder contains introductory material to Immanuel Kant’s (1724-1804) duty ethics.

    https://www.earlymoderntexts.com/assets/pdfs/kant1785

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/kant-moral/

    Rights Ethical Theory

    This folder contains material on the foundation and theory of rights.

    https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/

    Final Essay Assignment

    You are to write an essay explaining and evaluating what you learned in this course The purpose of this assignment is for you to demonstrate your understanding of one of the central debates in philosophy by explaining what you learned about that issue.

     

    Your essay must be 2-3 pages, double-spaced, in 12-point font. 

     

    I will be evaluating your essay based on the following criteria.

     

    Regarding your content development, you will be graded based on the quality of your writing. I expect you to start with an introduction that motivates the project and plainly states what you learned and finish with a conclusion that both summarizes your evaluation of the position clearly and explores implications or limitations of your assessment. In addition, your essay must have a clear and logical organizational plan as well, with ideas, sentences, and paragraphs building naturally in support of your thesis. To accomplish this, you must make sure your organizational plan would be obvious to the reader, and you must use transitional words, phrases, and sentences to show how your sentences and paragraphs relate to each other and to your thesis.

     

    To demonstrate your mastery of the relevant conventions of philosophical writing, you will need to provide a clear and complete explanation of the position you are discussing. In addition, you will also need to provide a clear and complete explanation of the relevant alternative views discussed in the lesson and draw a clear contrast between all of these views.

     

    To demonstrate your understanding of the context and purpose of this assignment, you should provide a clear example that illustrates to the reader the relevance of this debate to your life. Your example needs to be realistic, and you need to come up with it on your own. You will also need to explain how the example illustrates the position under discussion.

     

    Concerning the appropriate use of sources and evidence, I expect you to explain and evaluate the relevant arguments or considerations from the lessons both for and against the position under discussion, in detail and with clarity. In your evaluation of each argument, you will need to explain whether the premises are true, whether the reasoning is valid, and why you think so. Further, you will need to consider and assess at least one possible objection to each argument and then provide a sufficiently compelling overall evaluation of the argument in light of this objection. 

     

    Finally, to demonstrate your control of syntax and mechanics, I expect you to skillfully communicate your meaning to the reader with clarity and virtually no grammatical mistakes. Overall, your essay must be clear, with well-developed paragraphs, complete and grammatical sentences, and words chosen for their precise meanings.

    Calculate the price of your order

    550 words
    We'll send you the first draft for approval by September 11, 2018 at 10:52 AM
    Total price:
    $26
    The price is based on these factors:
    Academic level
    Number of pages
    Urgency
    Basic features
    • Free title page and bibliography
    • Unlimited revisions
    • Plagiarism-free guarantee
    • Money-back guarantee
    • 24/7 support
    On-demand options
    • Writer’s samples
    • Part-by-part delivery
    • Overnight delivery
    • Copies of used sources
    • Expert Proofreading
    Paper format
    • 275 words per page
    • 12 pt Arial/Times New Roman
    • Double line spacing
    • Any citation style (APA, MLA, Chicago/Turabian, Harvard)

    Our guarantees

    Delivering a high-quality product at a reasonable price is not enough anymore.
    That’s why we have developed 5 beneficial guarantees that will make your experience with our service enjoyable, easy, and safe.

    Money-back guarantee

    You have to be 100% sure of the quality of your product to give a money-back guarantee. This describes us perfectly. Make sure that this guarantee is totally transparent.

    Read more

    Zero-plagiarism guarantee

    Each paper is composed from scratch, according to your instructions. It is then checked by our plagiarism-detection software. There is no gap where plagiarism could squeeze in.

    Read more

    Free-revision policy

    Thanks to our free revisions, there is no way for you to be unsatisfied. We will work on your paper until you are completely happy with the result.

    Read more

    Confidentiality Guarantee

    Your email is safe, as we store it according to international data protection rules. Your bank details are secure, as we use only reliable payment systems.

    Read more

    Fair-cooperation guarantee

    By sending us your money, you buy the service we provide. Check out our terms and conditions if you prefer business talks to be laid out in official language.

    Read more

    24/7 Support

    Our specialists are always online to help you! We are available 24/7 via live chat, WhatsApp, and phone to answer questions, correct mistakes, or just address your academic fears.

    See our T&Cs
    Live Chat+1(978) 822-0999EmailWhatsApp

    Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code ESSAYHELP