Philosophical Reflection

A. Assignment Guidelines

DIRECTIONS: As reported in Plato’s account The Apology, Socrates famously claimed at his trial that “The unexamined life is not worth living.” In this course, you have had the opportunity to examine your own life and reality through the thoughts of the ancient Greek philosophers. The purpose of this Touchstone assignment is for you (1) to engage with the philosophical ideas presented in this course and (2) to reflect on how these philosophical ideas have impacted your own life.

Part I: Philosophical Thinking
In the first part of the Touchstone, you will be distinguishing between the three primary branches of philosophy.

Don't use plagiarized sources. Get Your Custom Essay on
Philosophical Reflection
Just from $13/Page
Order Essay

Consider the three following questions:

  • What is knowledge?
  • What is reality made of? 
  • What is the good life and how ought I to live it?

These are the basic questions that were considered in different forms by the major figures in ancient Greek philosophy. But they are also critical questions for our own lives today, whether we are philosophers or not.

Part I of this assignment should be approximately 1-2 pages (300-600 words) and cover each of the following steps:

  1. First, you should define philosophy and then distinguish and define each of the three main branches of philosophy covered in this class. 
  2. Then, identify which of the above questions is associated with each branch of philosophy.
  3. You should illustrate the differences between the three branches of philosophy using examples from the course. For example, explain how Socrates would answer the question “What is knowledge?” or how Epictetus would answer the question “What is the good life?”

You will use information and examples from the Sophia tutorials to support your response. When citing material from a tutorial, please include the name of the lesson and use the following format:

  • In-text citation: (Aristotle’s Highest Good, n.d.) or (The Footnotes to Plato, n.d.).

Part II: Reflection
For the second part of the Touchstone, now that you’ve distinguished between the three main branches of philosophy, you will focus on one of those three questions from Part I and use that as a starting point and guide for your personal philosophical reflection.

The purpose of Part II is for you to reflect on the philosophical mindset and some of the ideas presented in this course and apply them to your own life. This reflection is more open-ended than Part I, but should include reflections on the following questions:

  1. What does it mean to think philosophically? How can thinking philosophically help me in my own life?
  2. What impact do the ideas of the ancient Greek philosophers have on my own views and opinions? 
  3. Then, based on these reflections, you should give your own answer to whichever of the three questions from Part I you chose to focus on, using cited examples from the course to support your answer. (“What is knowledge?”; “What is reality?”; “What is the good life?”) 

Part II of this assignment should be approximately 1-2 pages (300-600 words). You should write at least one paragraph for each of the three prompts listed above.
In answering these reflection questions, you are free to draw from your own experiences as well as bringing in the ideas of different ancient Greek philosophers. Please note: Some philosophers will be more suited for particular questions than others. For example, Epictetus has a lot to say about “What is the good life and how ought I to live it?” while not saying much about knowledge or reality. Plato and Aristotle wrote a great deal about all three questions. 

  • Your draft must be 3-4 page (approximately 700-1000 words)
  • Double-space your submission and use one-inch margins.
  • Use a readable 12-point font.
  • All writing must be appropriate for an academic context. 
  • Your submission must be original and written for this assignment.
  • Plagiarism of any kind is strictly prohibited.
  • In-text citations should use this style: (Aristotle’s Highest Good, n.d.)
  • Your submission must include your name, the name of the course, the date, and the title of your composition. 
  • Include all of the assignment components in a single file.
  • Acceptable file formats include and x.

  • Unit 1 Tutorials: Great Philosophers
  • INSIDE UNIT 1

    Introduction to Philosophy and the

    Pre-Socratics

    What is Philosophy?

    Why Study Philosophy?

    Cosmology and the First Philosophers

    The Atomistic Worldview

    Parmenides and the Doctrine of Permanence

    Heraclitus and the Doctrine of Impermanence

    Socrates and

    Dialectic

    Socrates: The Father of Western

    Philosophy

    The Socratic Approach

    Introducing Arguments

    Evaluation and Analysis of Arguments

    Evaluating an Argument in Action

    The Apology: A Defense of Philosophy

    The Apology — Socrates’ Arguments

    The Crito: The Duties of the Social Contract

    The Phaedo: The Death of

    Socrates

    Plato and Aristotle

    Plato: An academic approach to concepts

    Plato’s Forms: The Objects of Knowledge

    Plato Forms: The Foundations of Being

    Applying Plato’s

    Metaphysics

    The Footnotes to Plato

    Aristotle: The Dissection of Reality

    Aristotle on What There Is

    Plato vs. Aristotle: The Mathematician or the Biologist

    Philosophy as a Way of Life

    Aristotelianism: The Naturalistic Worldview

    Aristotle’s Highest Good

    Applying Aristotle’s

    Ethics

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 1

    Stoicism: The Ethics of Dispassion

    Philosophical Analysis as a Way of Life

    What is Philosophy?

    by Sophia Tutorial

    Philosophy is a field of study that many people (including students) don’t know much about. This

    course enables you to increase your knowledge of philosophy by examining its origins in ancient

    Greece, as well as some of the areas that are studied by philosophers today, including logic,

    epistemology, ethics, and metaphysics.

    This section responds to the question, “What is Philosophy?” in

    three

    parts:

    1. The Beginning of Western Philosophy

    2. The Big Picture and a Contemporary Definition

    3. Some Major Branches of Philosophy

    1. The Beginning of Western Philosophy

    Western philosophy is traditionally thought to have started when a mathematician named Thales of Miletus
    successfully predicted an eclipse in 585 BCE. Although this may seem to have been an accomplishment in
    the field of astronomy, not philosophy, astronomy, like many other sciences, was once considered to be a
    branch of philosophy.

    Imagine for a moment that you lived in Greece 2600 years ago, but Thales had not made his famous
    prediction about the eclipse. What would people have thought caused the eclipse? Would they have
    concluded that the gods were angry, or bringing the world to an end? Whatever conclusions might have been
    reached about the meaning of the event, it’s likely that it would have been connected to the gods. By making
    his prediction based on analysis of his observations, Thales demonstrated that humans were capable of
    interpreting reality on their own, without divine assistance.

    Thales demonstrated that the world was fundamentally understandable and predictable. Human beings do
    not need to appeal to the gods to learn about the world, or to use what they learn. By applying reason to
    observations, people can solve many of life’s puzzles. The desire to know and learn is the foundation of
    philosophy.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 2

    Thales, illustrated here, was a pre-socratic philosopher. In addition to philosophy, Thales also had a strong interest

    in mathematics and astronomy.

    2. The Big Picture and a Contemporary Definition

    To better understand what philosophy involves, consider the etymology of the word, “philosophy.” It comes
    from two Greek words, philos and sophia. Philos means “love.” It is the basis of a number of common words,
    including “philanthropy” and “Philadelphia.” Sophia, which is also part of “sophisticated” and “sophomore,”
    means “wisdom” (and before you sophomores start feeling too proud, sophomore means “wise fool”).
    Philosophy, at a fundamental level, is the love of wisdom.

    Wisdom is not the same as knowledge. One can have all of the knowledge in the world but still lack wisdom.
    Rather than referring to information retained in memory (i.e, knowledge), wisdom refers to the ability to apply
    reason to knowledge, in order to make use of it in beneficial ways. Wisdom focuses on how we use what we
    learn, rather than on what we learn.

    The highest degree one can earn in biology is a PhD — a doctorate in philosophy. A PhD in biology not only
    means that you know facts and concepts in the field (i.e., knowledge), but that you can use that knowledge to
    make new contributions — in biology or a related field. You can evaluate the body of biological knowledge
    and determine how parts of it can be used in new ways. As a result of philosophy’s focus on wisdom, science
    and philosophy share a similar methodology.

    Defining philosophy as “love of wisdom” helps us to begin to understand it, but it lacks precision. Here is the
    definition of philosophy that we will use in this course:

     TERM TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 3

    Philosophy

    The pursuit of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically.

    Philosophy seeks to find truth in areas where science cannot.

     EXAMPLE Consider this philosophical question: “Is there a creator god of a certain description?”
    We cannot answer this question by looking for a god through a telescope. In this instance, science

    cannot help us to find the truth. There are two possible answers to this question: “there is” or “there

    isn’t.”

    In seeking to arrive at the truth, philosophy is not mere opinion. If two people disagree, this doesn’t mean that
    it is not possible to find an answer and that they must agree to disagree. With respect to the example above, If
    two people disagree as to what is true, one of them is simply wrong. Philosophy helps us to determine which
    one.

    Since we cannot use a telescope, a microscope, etc. to discover who is right and who is wrong, we must make
    inferences: We take the evidence we have and ask whether it supports one position or the other. We use
    logic to decide which position is better-supported and, therefore, more reasonable. It is for this reason that
    logic is the backbone of philosophy.

    3. Some Major Branches of Philosophy

    Philosophy encompasses a number of branches/sub-disciplines. The three most significant branches involving
    the philosophers we’ll study in this course are ethics, epistemology, and metaphysics.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Ethics

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of value, and thereby determines

    right and wrong.

    Questions of right and wrong fit within the definition of philosophy provided above. Consider this action:
    punching a small child. The sciences can tell us a lot about this action. Medicine can predict the damage it
    would cause. Political science can determine its legal consequences. Psychology can provide insight into the
    mind of the perpetrator. But no scientific analysis can tell us that this action is wrong.

    Of course, it is wrong, and anyone who claims that “wrong” is merely an opinion, and that this action is

    not

    something that can be true or false, should be ignored. Science can tell us that this action would cause pain,
    but it is a philosophical truth that causing pain unnecessarily is wrong.

    Although questions of right and wrong are the prerogative of philosophy, science has a role. Later in the
    course, we will consider philosophical approaches to ethics, including the philosophy of Socrates, who was
    not only deeply interested in determining how to live a morally upright life, but was willing to die to uphold his
    beliefs.

    Philosophy provides a benefit to science through epistemology.

     TERM TO KNOW

    Epistemology

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 4

    methodologies by which it is attained.

    Philosophy is sometimes called the “mother of the sciences” because it determines what constitutes
    knowledge. For example, it helps biologists determine what is biological knowledge (versus mere opinion),
    and what methods can generate knowledge. Philosophers of science were the driving force behind the
    development and refinement of the scientific method. Socrates distinguished knowledge from opinion, while
    Plato gave the first clear account of knowledge. Aristotle, the father of physics, biology, and astronomy, used
    philosophy to develop and enhance these disciplines.

    The largest and, perhaps, the most fundamental branch of philosophy is metaphysics.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Metaphysics

    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate

    nature of reality.

    The prefix “meta” means “beyond.” Metaphysics works on fundamental issues that are beyond science —
    principles in which science may be grounded. For instance, although science identifies and describes the
    laws of physics, what is a law? What is its status? What kind of a thing is it? These are metaphysical questions.
    Metaphysics also considers questions including, is there a god? Are we free to make decisions, or are all of
    our choices predetermined? What is the ultimate nature of time? What is causation? All of the philosophers
    included in this course have something to say about these topics. Additionally, we’ll learn how metaphysics
    informs other philosophical disciplines, such as ethics.

    These three branches of philosophy will be a major focus of this course. Other branches of philosophy (e.g.,
    natural philosophy and cosmology), have been largely relegated to the sciences.

    TERMS TO KNOW

    Natural Philosophy

    The branch of philosophy that examines nature and the universe

    Cosmology

    The branch of philosophy that studies the universe in its totality

    The subjects studied in what was called “natural philosophy” have moved from philosophy to physics,

    astronomy, and other sciences. Cosmology is now a branch of astrophysics (cosmogony is a branch of

    cosmology that focuses on the origin of the universe).

    Since philosophy is the pursuit of wisdom, it supports all pursuits of knowledge. To discover wisdom,

    philosophy uses logic, reason, and critical thinking, and studies topics including ethics, epistemology,

    and metaphysics. In this course, we’ll learn about these branches of philosophy, practice logic,

    and

    examine philosophical approaches to questions including “What is knowledge?” “What is real?” and

    “What is a good life and how should I live?”

    Source: Image of Thales, PD,
    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Thales_of_Miletus#/media/File:Illustrerad_Verldshistoria_band_I_Ill_107

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 5

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Thales_of_Miletus#/media/File:Illustrerad_Verldshistoria_band_I_Ill_107

    Cosmology

    The branch of philosophy that treats the universe in its totality

    Epistemology

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies

    that attain it

    Ethics

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of value and thereby seeks to determine

    right and wrong

    Metaphysics

    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality

    Natural Philosophy

    The branch of philosophy that treats nature and the universe

    Philosophy

    The pursuit of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically

    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 6

    Why Study Philosophy?
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Philosophy is sometimes stereotyped as an “ivory tower” discipline that does not apply to the “real”

    world. In this lecture, we will cover four areas in which the benefits of philosophy are easy to see:

    higher education, the sciences, society, and the people who study philosophy.

    This section answers the question, “Why Study Philosophy?” in five parts:

    1. Philosophy and Higher Education

    2. Benefits of the Philosophical Mindset

    3. Benefits Through the Sciences

    4. Benefit to Society

    5. Benefit to the Individual

    1. Philosophy and Higher Education

    Recall that philosophy is the pursuit of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically. Philosophy
    pursues wisdom, and is therefore crucial in defining methods for the development and refinement of
    knowledge in all fields. As a result, philosophy is nearly synonymous with higher learning. Indeed, the words
    “academia” and “academic” come from the name of Plato’s school of philosophy, the Academy. The highest
    degree attainable in academia is the PhD, Latin for philosophiae doctor, or doctor of philosophy.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Philosophy
    The pursuit of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically.

    Asking “why care about philosophy” is like asking “why care about higher education?” Philosophy is a
    collegiate activity that signifies intellectual maturity. One can question the status quo — not to be belligerent,
    but out of a genuine desire to understand it. All you have learned previously becomes a starting point, not an
    end.

    2. Benefits of the Philosophical Mindset

    In enumerating the advantages of philosophy, 20th century philosopher Bertrand Russell pointed out that it
    enlarges our thoughts and frees us from the “tyranny of custom.” How does philosophy do this? By asking
    “why” questions, and determining whether the answers are satisfactory. Philosophy requires that all beliefs be
    justified. What does this mean?

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 7

     TRY IT

    State a belief: “I believe (fill in the blank) is true.” Next, ask “why” you believe what you’ve stated. Why do

    you think your belief is true? If you can provide a good answer, one that is good enough to convince a

    reasonable skeptic, then you have justified your belief and, therefore, know it. If you cannot provide an

    answer, or only an answer that a skeptic would find unsatisfactory, you have an opinion, but do not know.

    You should not believe what you’ve stated, or should believe it only provisionally.

    Philosophy’s requirement that beliefs must be justified leads to regular questioning of beliefs and refinement
    of answers.

     EXAMPLE For thousands of years, people believed that only certain organic matter (composted
    plants and excrement) were adequate fertilizers. In the 20th century, someone finally asked the crucial

    question: “Why do we think that we can only use organic matter as fertilizer?” No one could provide a

    good answer to this question. What people had believed for thousands of years was opinion, not

    knowledge — something handed down through generations of farmers. It was Russell’s “tyranny of

    custom.” When freed from this tyranny, scientists developed nitrogen-based fertilizers, more land was

    farmed, and every acre produced more crops. Millions of people were spared famine and starvation,

    thanks to the philosophical mindset and its determination to hold only justified beliefs.

    This is only one example, but it represents how progress has taken place over the centuries.

    3. Benefits Through the Sciences

    As the last example demonstrated, the philosophical mindset is key to progress in the sciences. However, the
    connection between philosophy and science is deeper than that.

    Philosophers have made the significant contributions to scientific methodology, and have contributed to the
    formation of science as we know it today. Epistemology set the standards of knowledge, and the philosophy
    of science developed methods to attain it. Aristotle, a Greek philosopher, is considered to be the father of
    physics and biology. He contributed to the development of the foundations of science. His concepts were
    later refined and incorporated into the modern scientific method by Francis Bacon, who was also a
    philosopher.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies

    used to attain it.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 8

    Images of Aristotle and Francis Bacon, key contributors to the foundations of science and to the modern scientific

    method.

    Philosophy has inspired breakthroughs in theoretical science. Isaac Newton’s Principia is, in part, a text on
    natural philosophy. Albert Einstein cites the work of philosopher David Hume as the primary influence on his
    development of the Theory of Relativity. Hume’s work also inspired much of Adam Smith’s economics.

    Many philosophers were also mathematicians and/or scientists, including René Descartes (perhaps you have
    heard of Cartesian coordinates), and G.W. Leibniz, who developed the binary number system and symbolic
    logic, without which we would not have computers. When someone’s passion is knowledge, and that
    knowledge is groundbreaking, distinctions between philosophy and theoretical science disappear.

    4. Benefit to Society

    Although you may have hesitated to give philosophy any credit for developments in theoretical science, you
    need only look around you to see what it has done in ethics and political philosophy. As a result of its
    influence in these areas, philosophy has led to improvements in society and culture.

     DID YOU KNOW

    The U.S. Constitution, including much of the Bill of Rights, is based on the political philosophy of John

    Locke. Many of the Founding Fathers were Lockeans.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 9

    General acceptance of democracy as the fairest form of government was a philosophical development.
    Similarly, most of our modern concepts and advancements with respect to justice, fairness, and equality
    originated with political philosophers. If you appreciate the end of slavery, the fight for racial equality,
    women’s suffrage, or other instances of social progress, thank a philosopher.

    Philosophy has also contributed to advancement in ethics. Philosophers are often employed as consultants
    on hospital ethics boards, as well as in other fields of applied ethics including environmental and business
    ethics. Philosophy has influenced societies’ views on right and wrong for millennia.

    5. Benefit to the Individual

    Do you think you would benefit from being wiser? More moral? A better critical thinker? Being better
    equipped to distinguish knowledge from opinion? Making decisions based on reason instead of emotion?
    Acting according to your beliefs? Having a consistent worldview? Recognizing value? Minimizing bias while
    maximizing objectivity?

    The study of philosophy does all this and more. It makes you a better person, but it can also have more
    immediate, tangible results. The study of philosophy has been shown to increase standardized test scores
    and performance in other courses. And, despite opinions to the contrary, philosophy degrees are highly
    sought by business employers because “thinking outside the box” is vital to business solutions and strategy.

    Like your other courses, you will get out what you put into a philosophy class. If you make an effort in “Ancient
    Greek Philosophers,” you will be rewarded.

    Philosophy brings value from the global level to the individual. A philosophical mindset is required f

    or

    any sort of progress. Philosophy has advanced (and continues to advance) the sciences; it has

    contributed to the growth of more ethical and just societies; and has broadened and improved the

    minds of those who study it.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Image of Francis Bacon | License: Public Domain

    Image of Aristotle | License: Public Domain


    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies
    that attain it
    Philosophy
    The pursuit of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 10

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Francis_Bacon#/media/File:Pourbus_Francis_Bacon

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aristotle#/media/File:Aristotle_Altemps_Inv8575

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 11

    Cosmology and the First Philosophers
    by Sophia Tutorial

    In this section, we will examine the very first western philosophers, the Pre-Socratics. After discussing

    why they are considered philosophers, we’ll learn about some of the major figures and their ideas,

    and how those ideas shaped the world as we know it.

    This tutorial examines Cosmology and the first philosophers in three parts:

    1. Who Were the Pre-Socratic Philosophers?

    2. Some Pre-Socratic Philosophers and their Influential Ideas

    3. Intellectual Legacy of the Pre-Socratics

    1. Who Were the Pre-Socratic Philosophers?

    A group of philosophers now known as the Pre-Socratics were active In Greece between (approximately)
    600- 450 BCE.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Pre-Socratics

    A collective term used for Greek philosophers who practiced philosophy before Socrates

    The influence of the Pre-Socratics is limited because most of their work has not survived. What remains of
    their beliefs and teachings are fragmenta: mostly quotations from other philosophers whose works were
    preserved, and testamonia: references to them and their work (but not quotations) in other ancient texts. Our
    access to their work, therefore, is limited, but their work remains important. They influenced and inspired
    those whose ideas changed our science, culture and intellectual traditions. They were true philosophers, even
    though what we know about them and their work is limited to their major ideas.

    They are categorized as Pre-Socratics, not only because of their limited influence, but also because much of
    their work can be assigned to natural philosophy or cosmology, branches of philosophy that have been
    largely relegated to the sciences.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Natural Philosophy

    The branch of philosophy that considers nature and the universe

    Cosmology

    The branch of philosophy that considers the universe in its totality

    Natural philosophy has moved from being a branch of philosophy to an area that is studied in physics,

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 12

    astronomy, and other sciences. Cosmology is now a branch of astrophysics (cosmogony is a branch of
    cosmology that focuses on the origin of the universe). When we take this into account, we can see that the
    Pre-Socratics were practicing theoretical science when science was still part of philosophy.

    Why then was their work once considered philosophy? To answer this question, recall that philosophy is the
    pursuit of truths that cannot be determined empirically. Questions like, “what are stars made of” could not be
    answered empirically 2,500 years ago. The theories, discoveries, and tools required to answer those
    questions had not been developed. All that the Pre-Socratics had to work with was their observations, and
    what they could conclude based on those observations.

    Their methodology was philosophical in two ways: First, they used argument and reason to identify the best
    answers to the questions. Second, their methodology was naturalistic. They did not rely on divine mechanisms
    to support their answers. Also, they did not only work on these topics. Their findings in natural philosophy
    influenced their views in other areas of philosophical inquiry.

    2. Some Pre-Socratic Philosophers and their
    Influential Ideas

    Following is a list of some of the most influential Pre-Socratic philosophers, and their major ideas. The list is a
    sample; it is not comprehensive. Two significant Pre-Socratics, Heraclitus of Ephesus and Parmenides of Elea,
    have been omitted because they will be examined in detail in separate tutorials.

    The Milesians
    This group, usually considered to be the first Pre-Socratic philosophers, consisted of Thales and his pupils,
    Anaximander and Anaximenes. It was said that Thales claimed that everything in the cosmos was made of
    water, but Anaximenes held that everything was made of air. Anaximander maintained that the cosmos was
    initially apeiron (i.e., “boundless” or “without qualities”), but became differentiated.

    If these theories seem far fetched, note that their methodology was sound. These philosophers used
    empirical data (i.e., information obtained by observation) to formulate theories of reality that best fit that data.

    What these three theories have in common was the positing of a single cosmos: the claim that all matter was
    united according to a single arrangement/order, governed by universal laws. This was the Milesians’ true
    philosophico-scientific advancement. They were essentially correct in taking this position. Science worked out
    the details over the next 2,500 years.

    Pythagoras
    Pythagoras (long thought to be the discoverer of the Pythagorean Theorem) and his followers incorporated
    mathematics into his philosophical worldview.

     MAKE THE CONNECTION

    The Pythagorean Theorem, a basic component of algebra courses today, has been around for thousands

    of years!

    To the Pythagoreans, the world was a mathematical entity of perfect harmony. They assigned great
    importance to certain numbers found in nature (e.g., the number of heavenly bodies). A human’s job was to
    find his or her proper place in this harmonious system. They also formulated and defended a reincarnation
    doctrine related to their worldview.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 13

    Xenophanes of Colophon
    Xenophanes, a traveling poet, was also a philosopher who lived to a great age. Secularization played a major
    role in his philosophy. He reassigned divine mechanisms to naturalistic causes, such as the rainbow, which
    ancient Greeks believed to be a manifestation of the messenger goddess Iris. Xenophanes identified
    rainbows as phenomena produced as a result of meteorological causes.

    Xenophanes maintained that it is better to rely on observation and reason than on signs from the gods. He
    was not an atheist, but objected to then-common conceptions of the gods, faulting earlier poets for depicting
    deities as treacherous and deceitful beings who constantly interfered in human affairs. He also opposed
    theories that relied on “the god of the gaps,” in which a miracle is used to support an otherwise-scientific
    explanation because there was no known natural cause. To Xenophanes, the gods controlled all things, but
    acted predictably, not miraculously. Indeed, science is close to impossible if gods constantly interfere with
    natural phenomena.

    Xenophanes characterized this as anthropomorphism — the application of human attributes to something that
    is non-human (like the gods). In some ways, the Greek gods were depicted as the worst of humans. Zeus
    used his powers to change his form and rape women. Hera, his wife, punished those women. The gods
    sometimes helped the strong to defeat the weak, and the unreasonable to kill the reasonable. As depicted,
    the gods often behaved in ways that humans might behave if they had divine power. In these depictions,
    therefore, humans projected their attributes onto the gods. As Heraclitus stated:

    Any gods worth their titles would be the authors of the laws of nature. Their actions in the world would take
    place through nature, not above and beyond it.

    Anaxagoras of Clazomenae

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 14

    Anaxagoras was primarily interested in cosmology. Denying that celestial bodies were gods, he interpreted
    the world around him in natural terms, and formulated one of the first cosmogonies. Before there was a known
    universe, he theorized that everything began as an undistinguished mixture that took form and definition
    when a force called nous began to spin the mixture. The literal translation of nous is “mind,” but ancient Greek
    had such a small vocabulary that a word was often used for several things. As a result, it is not clear whether
    Anaxagoras defined nous as a deity or as a force of order (like the laws of nature). Either way, nous is the force
    which gives form to the universe, a process which Anaxagoras believed to be ongoing. He was condemned in
    Athens for maintaining this naturalistic concept.

    Empedocles of Acragas
    Empedocles was a physicist who was deeply religious. He was probably a Pythagorean. As a physicist,
    Empedocles maintained that there were four “roots” — what Aristotle would later call the elements — earth,
    air, fire, and water. These were combined by love, and separated by strife. In this system, there were six
    metaphysical entities that formed everything in the cosmos. Instead of coming into existence and passing
    away, Empedocles viewed the universe in terms of mixing and separating. (He thought this process also
    occurred on the physical level, involving the flow of blood.) He was concerned with religious purity and
    purification, and defended the Pythagorean notion of reincarnation.

    Protagoras of Adera
    Protagoras was a member of the “Older Sophists,” a group of traveling intellectuals. He made two significant
    intellectual contributions, which are interrelated. Protagoras was perhaps the first outspoken agnostic. He
    argued that we could not know whether the gods existed or not. This led him to make a second claim: “man is
    the measure of all things.” This statement is usually interpreted to mean that knowledge is relative to the
    knower. This implies that we cannot escape our biased perspective. We cannot know what it is like to walk in
    another person’s shoes.

    3. Intellectual Legacy of the Pre-Socratics

    It might be tempting to dismiss some of the ideas of the Pre-Socratics as quaint and outdated, but they mark
    the beginning of science. By observing the natural world and using reason to explain phenomena, the Pre-
    Socratics’ provided a basis for all subsequent advances in the sciences.

    Notice that there are common themes shared by the Pre-Socratic philosophers. The first is a consistent
    worldview, in which one or a few laws and elements are used to account for a variety of phenomena. The
    second is methodological naturalism. Most Pre-Socratics did not deny the existence of the gods, but
    maintained that we should not invoke them to explain phenomena. This (as a method, not with respect to
    belief) has enabled scientific progress from their time until the present day.

    The Pre-Socratics viewed natural philosophy and theology as separate disciplines, with different standards of
    knowledge, and different applications. Their commitment to natural philosophy enabled them to think in new
    ways. In a number of areas, it took science millennia to catch up with them (e.g., thought described as a result
    of physical processes; Anaximander hinting that humans evolved from lower animals).

    The Pre-Socratics were the first Western philosophers. In this tutorial, we examined the contributions

    of some of the most influential philosophers in this group. The Pre-Socratics took a philosophical

    approach to questions that are now of interest to the sciences. Their ideas were a starting point for

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 15

    philosophic and scientific investigation.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Heraclitus Image | License: Public Domain


    Cosmology

    The branch of philosophy that treats the origin of the universe in its totality

    Natural Philosophy
    The branch of philosophy that treats nature and the universe
    Pre-Socratics

    A collective term for the group of Greek philosophers practicing philosophy before the influence of

    Socrates
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 16

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Heraclitus#/media/File:Hendrik_ter_Brugghen_-_Heraclitus

    The Atomistic Worldview
    by Sophia Tutorial

    In this lecture, we will examine the notion of a philosophical worldview, and present an influential

    worldview from ancient Greece: philosophical atomism.

    This tutorial investigates the philosophical worldview and atomism, in three parts:

    1. Philosophy as a Worldview

    2. The Atomistic Worldview

    3. Atomistic Influence

    1. Philosophy as a Worldview

    Perhaps you have been asked, “What is your philosophy?” In light of our definition of philosophy — the pursuit
    of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically — you may find this question difficult to answer.
    However, the question and our definition may be more closely related than they seem to be. Since
    metaphysics, a branch of philosophy, considers first principles and the ultimate components of reality, there is
    a sense in which everything falls within the purview of philosophy.

    A cohesive and defensible system of metaphysics enables provides one with a way to interpret reality — a
    worldview. For example, if you answer “what is your philosophy?” by stating your belief that physical reality is
    the only reality, your answer impacts how you view the world. As a result of your answer, you must reject or
    radically reinterpret religion and belief in a deity. You must also interpret thought as a purely physical
    phenomenon, and deny the existence of a brain-independent mind or soul. You must likewise take a position
    on other abstract entities that many people believe exist.

     EXAMPLE Numbers are abstract entities that many people believe exist independent of the
    human mind. If your philosophy only allows for physical entities, you must reject the existence of mind-

    independent numbers, since they are not physical things. (You would also have to equate “mind” with

    part of the brain.)

    Lastly, you must ensure that your actions are consistent with your beliefs. Hence, in developing a
    metaphysical view, you have also developed a worldview.

    2. The Atomistic Worldview

    An early and extremely influential worldview was developed by the ancient Greek atomists. According to
    atomism, reality is composed of atoms in a void.

    The word “atom” comes from the Greek atomon, which means “uncuttable.” An atom, therefore, is matter

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 17

    which is indivisible and without parts. This is not the definition of atom used in contemporary chemistry and
    physics. We now know that atoms are divisible and have parts (i.e., subatomic particles).

    At the time when these atoms (think of them as “chemical atoms”) were discovered, scientists thought they
    had found a basic, indivisible entity, so they took the name from ancient Greek philosophy and applied it to
    their discovery. It was later determined that chemical atoms are divisible, but the name (i.e., atom) continues to
    be used. As a result, we must distinguish a philosophical atom from a chemical atom.

     TERM TO KNOW

    Philosophical Atom

    An indivisible physical entity

    Since chemical atoms do not fit this description, they are not the same as philosophical atoms.

    The chief defenders of philosophical atomism in ancient Greece were Leucippus and his student Democritus.
    It is through the latter that we have received most of what we know about ancient Greek atomism. (It is
    important to note that, in addition to Greek atomism, there were other ancient atomist philosophies, including
    Indian and Islamic traditions.)

    Greek atomism states that everything that exists is either an atom or a collection of atoms. Atoms are the
    smallest entity, but they are not infinitely small. Aristotle, when attempting to solve one of Parmenides’
    (another philosopher) metaphysical puzzles involving change, referred to the atomistic view that new things
    don’t come into existence. Instead, existing things change their organization: they take new forms.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Have you ever seen something begin to exist? Matter doesn’t seem to come into being. It only seems to

    change form. Consider, for instance, a human coming into being. The cellular material doesn’t come from

    nowhere. It comes from nutrients consumed and processed by the mother. Matter (the nutrients) is

    reordered into a new form (a human).

    The atomists believed that there were different kinds of atoms. They came in different shapes and sizes, and
    could be combined in a variety of ways. In the atomistic view, different atomic textures were used to explain
    how different sensations were produced. Different bonding configurations accounted for the degree of
    solidity of objects and other phenomena. Since, at that time, action at a distance was believed to be
    impossible, the atomist account was used to solve other puzzles (as in the following example).

     EXAMPLE The ability to perceive odors — to smell — was explained as the transfer of atoms from
    an object into the nose. Different shapes and configurations of atoms produced a variety of smells.

    It is important to note that the atomist philosophy is rich in explanations. Starting with a few simple
    assumptions, the atomists described and explained a variety of complex phenomenon.

    3. Atomistic Influence

    As was the case with the work of the Pre-Socratics in natural philosophy, science has had to “catch up” with
    philosophy. With some revisions (including how molecules form bonds), the atomist worldview has been
    adopted by contemporary science.

    However, it is important to keep in mind that, in addition to its influence on the sciences, atomism is a
    philosophical worldview, and that worldviews impact your perception of reality. The natural explanations for

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 18

    phenomena provided by philosophical atomism provoked religious and theological responses. Some
    theologians viewed atomism as an attack on religious belief. Others embraced it. In general, the worldview
    provided by Greek atomism, which is rich in satisfactory explanations of reality, requires us to consider, and
    even accommodate it. We are compelled to incorporate the tenets of atomism into our own worldviews, just
    as we are obliged to incorporate contemporary breakthroughs in physics and astrophysics.

    Ancient Greek atomism is an example of a successful worldview. It provides a metaphysical system

    that is defensible and rich in explanations of phenomena. It is based on a belief in philosophical atoms

    of different qualities (e.g., shape, texture) that are the fundamental components of reality.


    Philosophical Atom
    An indivisible physical entity
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 19

    Parmenides and the Doctrine of Permanence
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Parmenides of Elea was an influential Pre-Socratic philosopher, often considered the father of

    metaphysics. He and his school had a profound impact on later philosophy, especially that of Plato.

    Though, as with other Pre-Socratics, we have only fragments and testemonia of his philosophy, they

    indicate that he was an original thinker. What remains of Parmenides’ work is part of a single,

    extended metaphysical poem in which a student travels to meet a goddess, who lectures him about

    truth and belief. The proper interpretation of the poem has been the subject of scholarly debate. In

    this tutorial, Parmenides’ ideas regarding “the turn to metaphysics,” and his doctrine that the universe

    is one unchanging entity, will be examined.

    This tutorial investigates the philosophy of Parmenides, including the doctrine of permanence, in

    three parts:

    1. The Turn to Metaphysics

    2. The Doctrine of the Unchanging One

    3. Zeno’s Paradoxes

    1. The Turn to Metaphysics

    Parmenides was deeply influenced by Xenophanes (Parmenides may have been his student). Recall that
    Xenophanes criticized the pre-philosophical tradition of relying on the gods to explain natural phenomena.
    Xenophanes maintained that there was a strict division between mortal and divine knowledge that cannot be
    crossed. Parmenides upheld this distinction, but went even further by claiming that the opinions of mortals are
    universally unreliable.

    If mortals do not have access to divinity, but cannot attain knowledge without divine aid, how can they move
    beyond their flawed opinions and discover the nature of reality? Parmenides’ answer is that there are signs we
    can follow, which point to genuine reality: signs that “turn to metaphysics.”

    Recall that metaphysics seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality. In this context, it is a
    quest to look beyond the mortal world, the world of the senses and of unreliable opinion, to perceive reality as
    it truly is. Metaphysics is the answer to how humans can take a god’s-eye view and discover what is real.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Metaphysics
    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality
    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 20

    2. The Doctrine of the Unchanging One

    Substance monism is a component of Parmenides’ metaphysics, that has been attributed to him by later
    sources. It is the view that all of reality is one object, usually translated as the “what-is.” The “what-is” is a term
    for the way things are: The True. Parmenides also posited a corresponding “what-is-not.” This can be thought
    of as The False. Together, these two concepts create a duality in Parmenidean metaphysics.

    In this metaphysical system, what-is, is, but what-is-not, cannot be. That this must be so becomes evident
    when basic questions are asked: where would what-is-not come from? How would it come into being?

    What-is-not cannot come from what-is. The False cannot come from The True. Non-being cannot come from
    being. However, it is also impossible for what-is-not to come from nothing, since nothing cannot produce
    anything. As a result, the universe cannot change from what-is to what-is-not. If “The True” is true, it cannot
    become “The False.” At the same time, what-is cannot cease to be, since transformation from being to non-
    being is metaphysically impossible, according to Parmenides.

    In this system, what-is is eternal and unchanging, because change would require the universe to pass from
    what-is to what-is-not. Although this is the conclusion to which Parmenides’ metaphysical analysis leads, it is
    not the universe with which we are familiar. Our universe is changing and impermanent. This creates a duality
    between the genuine, unchanging realm of reality, and the changing world of appearance. Parmenides’ way
    focuses on the former, but the way of opinion, in which observers do not realize that this transient world of
    change is illusory, is focused on the latter.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    What are some advantages in seeing the world as unchanging? How might they account for our ability to

    know and learn?

    3. Zeno’s Paradoxes

    Maintaining that change is illusory, as Parmenides does, seems to run counter to common sense. You may be
    tempted to dismiss Parmenides’ view for that reason alone, but you would be wise to avoid a quick dismissal
    of his conclusions. Think about all of the things we know are true, despite what “common sense” tells us.

     EXAMPLE Right now, you are moving at 67,000 miles per hour while standing on a round surface
    that is rotating at up to 1,000 miles per hour. Space itself is expanding, and it curves around heavy

    objects.

    These examples show that “strange” cannot be equated with “false.” This is especially true when you are
    forced to choose between two peculiar options. For example, when you think about the origin of the universe,
    it seems as if you must choose between a Big Bang, in which all matter in the universe comes randomly into
    being, and a creator god who waited for an infinity before deciding to create the cosmos 13 billion years ago.
    In this debate, one side calling the other’s view “strange” is a case of the pot calling the kettle black. Such
    accusations are not significant challenges to any view. When considering big questions, things sometimes get
    weird.

    One of Parmenides’ most famous students, Zeno of Elea, wrote a short book describing paradoxes. He
    demonstrated that motion was a far stranger phenomenon than the “commonsense” view of it held by most
    people would allow. By doing so, Zeno showed that rejection of Parmenides’ explanations of how things work

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 21

    simply because they’re “strange,” and because they refuted “commonsense” opinions based on what seemed
    to be obvious and apparent, was illegitimate criticism.

     TERM TO KNOW

    Paradox

    Situations in which seemingly reasonable assumptions lead to a contradiction or an absurdity

    Consider this claim: “This sentence is false.” This claim seems reasonable because it is presented in the same

    structure as many claims we make. However, if the sentence is true, then it’s false; if it’s false, then it’s true!

    Instead of describing contradictions, Zeno’s paradoxes of motion show that simple assumptions about motion

    lead to absurdity.

    There are many kinds of paradoxes, as a result of how slippery the notion of “absurdity” is (e.g., is the
    presence of absence an absurdity?). “Paradox” covers a large number of logical and metaphysical oddities.
    Socrates and Plato, who we’ll discuss later in this course, emphasized precise definition of important words
    including “justice,” “craft,” and “piety.” They believed that precise definitions were required in order to be
    clear about the concepts being discussed. However, it can be difficult to define terms like these with
    precision. In contrast, the oddities uncovered by Zeno are relatively straightforward.

    Zeno explained a number of paradoxes, but only a few of them have been preserved. His paradoxes of
    motion fall into two categories: those which demonstrate the difficulties involved in positing time as a
    continuum, and those which demonstrate the difficulties involved in positing time as being composed of
    discrete moments.

    To argue against a continuum, Zeno raises considerations which include the following:

    If time is a continuum, how could we ever get from one place to another? To move from A to B, we must first
    halve the distance, then halve it again, then halve it again, and so on. That is, we must complete an infinite
    task through a series of finite actions.

     BRAINSTORM

    If you haven’t grasped this paradox yet, imagine an additional feature: a light turns on when you move half

    the distance from A to B. It turns off when you halve it again, and so on. When you finally arrive at B, is the

    light on or off?

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 22

    To argue against a discrete notion of time, imagine an arrow being fired. Consider one point in time (i.e., one

    moment), and label it T1. At time T1, the arrow will have a specific position, P1. At the next moment, T2, the

    arrow has moved to a new position, P2. When did the motion occur? Between moments? There is no such

    thing as “between moments,” if time is discrete. If we assume that time is composed of discrete moments, the

    arrow didn’t move, even though it is no longer at P1, but is now at P2. This is also absurd.

    Parmenides saw metaphysics as a way to transcend opinion and examine the world as it really is. But

    his analysis, based on the use of reason, led him to conclude that this world is unchanging, unified,

    and eternal. Such a world does not correspond to the world of appearances, which means that the

    latter is an illusion. Zeno modified this extreme claim by pointing out some of the strange features of

    the illusion.

    Source: Archer by damar bintang from the Noun Project (CC), bullseye by Dinosoft Labs from the Noun Project
    (CC), Arrow by Valeriy from the Noun Project (CC). All retrieved from The Noun Project
    :www.thenounproject.com


    Metaphysics
    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality
    Paradox

    When seemingly reasonable assumptions lead to either a contradiction or an absurdity

    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 23

    http://www.thenounproject.com

    Heraclitus and the Doctrine of Impermanence
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Heraclitus of Ephesus was another influential Pre-Socratic philosopher. Like Parmenides, he was

    interested in metaphysics and the realm of appearances, and thought that the gods could not guide

    humans in these areas. However, he reached some conclusions that differed greatly from those

    reached by Parmenides, arguing that the impermanence of the world of the senses was the true

    nature of reality.

    This tutorial examines Heraclitus and impermanence in three parts:

    1. Heraclitus on the Secular

    2. Heraclean Flux and the Unity of Opposites

    3. Parmenides and Heraclitus

    1. Heraclitus on the Secular

    Though he was not affiliated with any philosophical school, Heraclitus, like Parmenides, was influenced by the
    rational theology established by Xenophanes. Recall that Xenophanes disparaged the practice of turning the
    gods into fickle meddlers in human affairs, and thought that actions taken by the gods were constant (i.e.,
    according to the laws of nature). Heraclitus went further than his predecessors by emphasizing the human role
    in affairs. His approach to reality was entirely secular. He maintained that there was one true version of reality
    which he called the Logos.

     DID YOU KNOW

    The Greek word “logos” is translated as “account.” Hence, “biology” means to give an account of life.

    Logos was translated by ancient Greek Christians as “the Word,” as in, “in the beginning was the Word” —

    a surprisingly Heraclitean notion.

    Heraclitus believed that the Logos governed and/or organized all things, and.that it did so independently —
    without the participation of the gods. Although it is not clear whether he intended Logos to be distinct from
    reality (like a god), or dispersed through everything in the universe, all things in the cosmos are unified
    according to the Logos.

    The Logos belongs in the realm of metaphysics because it is not in the world we experience, but underlies it.
    Though difficult to understand, the “Logos” can be comprehended by humans, even though not all of them
    are capable of grasping it. The Logos is always true, whether anyone is aware of its reality or not. It is
    independent of knowledge and language, and belongs in the realm of metaphysics.

    2. Heraclitean Flux and the Unity of Opposites

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 24

    The two most significant principles through which Heraclitus’ Logos governs are the Unity of Opposites and
    the Doctrine of Flux.

    The Unity of Opposites is an assumption that the world is composed of opposites, and that opposites are
    linked in a system of connections.

     EXAMPLE There cannot be a mountain without a valley, and vice-versa. People cannot awaken if
    they have not first been asleep, and vice versa. Things are linked to what they are not. Heraclitus

    points out, for example, that ocean water is toxic to humans but necessary for fish. The opposite is true

    of fresh water.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Can you think of more unities of opposites? One that is frequently cited, especially in the philosophy of

    religion, is the importance of good and evil. Do you think this is a unity of opposites? Why or why not?

    Beyond simply pointing out these unities, Heraclitus locates them inside us. He maintains that youth and age,
    life and death, are already within us. One quality becomes the other. Each of them changes into its opposite
    — young becomes old, life becomes death, healthy becomes ill.

    Human beings occupy a privileged position in the universe according to Heraclitus. He indicates that our
    souls are connected to the Logos through language, a human phenomenon.

    Heraclitus’ Doctrine of the Flux is closely related to the unity of opposites. It states that all things change over
    time. Everything is impermanent, and is in a constant state of change, moving from what it is to what it is not.
    He famously declared that you cannot step into the same river twice, since, as water passes ceaselessly, the
    river becomes new. (The Heraclitans later pointed out that you cannot step into the same river once.) You are
    not the same person you were yesterday.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Have you encountered anything in the world (other than metaphysical objects, such as numbers, laws of

    nature, etc.) that does not change?

    Heraclitus holds that change is the ultimate nature of reality. All is flux. However, when reading the philosophy
    of Heraclitus, we must be careful to avoid taking some statements too literally. For example, Heraclitus’
    assertion regarding change is sometimes translated as a claim that all is fire. This should be read
    metaphorically, and in light of the rest of the text. Fire flickers, and in doing so it changes constantly. Saying
    that all is fire is a metaphorical way of saying that all is changing.

     DID YOU KNOW

    The metaphorical use of words — like using “fire” for “change” — was common in ancient Greek writing,

    because the language had a small vocabulary.

    3. Parmenides and Heraclitus

    Recall that Parmenides claimed that the ultimate nature of reality is static, and that change is

    illusory.

    Heraclitus, on the other hand, asserted that the ultimate nature of reality is change. It may be tempting to view
    them as polar opposites, philosophically speaking. In doing so, however, we would ignore significant points
    on which they agree.

    Both Parmenides and Heraclitus join Xenophanes in turning from divine causation and oracular knowledge to

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 25

    a secular concept of reality. For both of them, this involved examination of what is universal and regular in
    nature, rather than what is random. Both of them studied metaphysics, searching for the first principles and the
    ultimate nature of reality. They both recognized that the world of appearances is in constant flux, and that it is
    impermanent.

    Parmenides and Heraclitus believed that something constant underlies the impermanent world of change.
    Parmenides identified it as the realm of being, the realm of what-is Heraclitus posited a Logos that contains
    the universal principles of the Doctrine of Flux and the Unity of Opposites.

     BIG IDEA

    What is the significant difference between the philosophy of Parmenides, and that of Heraclitus? It seems

    to be the status of change. Parmenides states that change is illusory, while Heraclitus claims that change

    is not only genuine, but essential to reality.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Do you agree with Heraclitus or Parmenides? Start by answering a smaller question: Which of the

    following is more important to reality: what changes, or what is permanent? If you believe that reality is

    somehow a combination of the two, you will begin to see the metaphysical problem that Plato inherited,

    and some of what underlies his philosophy. We will investigate Plato and his solution in a subsequent

    tutorial.

     SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 26

    Heraclitus, like Parmenides, was interested in metaphysics as a way to examine the true nature of

    reality without involving the gods. He maintained that a Logos governs all things, and does so via the

    Unity of Opposites and the constancy of Flux. Although his philosophy is in some ways similar to that

    of Parmenides, they are ultimately at odds regarding the ultimate status of change — essential or

    illusory.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 27

    Socrates: The Father of Western Philosophy

    by Sophia Tutorial

    Socrates (circa 470-399 BCE) was one of the most important philosophers of all time. Although he

    was not the first western philosopher, he is known as the “Father of Western Philosophy.” This is not

    only because of his influence on other significant historical figures, but also because he re-oriented

    philosophy to focus on the areas studied today. He was completely dedicated to living his philosophy,

    even

    though it cost him his life.

    This tutorial investigates Socrates’ life and work in four parts:

    1. Socrates, Patriarch of Western Thought

    2. Socrates, Seeker of Wisdom

    3. The First Step on the Path to Wisdom

    4. Socrates, a Martyr for Wisdom

    1. Socrates, Patriarch of Western Thought

    Socrates lived until the age of 70. For most of his adult life, he was a teacher of philosophy. He did not charge
    tuition, but his ability, wisdom, and pedagogy attracted Athenian pupils, many of whom came from wealthy
    and noble families. One of these pupils was Aristocles, better known as Plato.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 28

    Bust of Socrates in the Vatican Museum. Socrates is known as the “Father of Western Philosophy.” His impacts on

    the field of philosophy and on other historical figures were numerous.

    Socrates taught Plato philosophy: not only how to seek wisdom, but also its importance. Plato started the
    Academy (and, arguably, higher education), and laid the foundations for western philosophy (and, perhaps,

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 29

    theology and political science). Plato’s influence and accomplishments were vast, but some portion the
    accolades he receives belongs to Socrates.

    Plato also taught an important pupil: Aristotle. Aristotle was a philosopher and scientist. He may have done
    more to advance science than anyone else. He is known as the father of physics, biology, and logic, and was
    a major contributor to the development of western thought. His work influenced the doctrine of the medieval
    Catholic Church, and was disseminated throughout the western world as a result.

    Like Plato, Aristotle’s accomplishments and influence cannot be overstated. However, he could not have
    achieved what he did without his teacher, Plato, and Plato’s teacher, Socrates. These philosophers and their
    accomplishments are discussed in more detail in later tutorials.

    It is in no way an exaggeration to say that Socrates was one of the most influential people in history. Like
    some of the other significant ancient thinkers, he did not produce any written work. The accounts we have of
    his life and teachings were primarily recorded by Plato.

    2. Socrates, Seeker of Wisdom

    Socrates’ historical influence has continued to this day, but it is important to understand that, during his life, he
    oriented philosophy in new directions. Recall that the Pre-Socratics were given their name because their
    methods, and the topics they investigated, were different than those that are the focus of contemporary
    philosophy. Socrates redirected philosophy to consider topics that are studied to this day.

    The Pre-Socratic philosophers primarily studied cosmology and natural philosophy, fields that were later
    appropriated by the sciences. Ethics and epistemology, on the other hand, have not (and probably cannot) be
    appropriated by other fields of study. These were the topics of greatest importance to Socrates. He sought
    wisdom. How to live according to ethical principles, and how to differentiate knowledge from opinion, were
    questions that must be answered to attain true wisdom. Socrates was the first moral philosopher and the first
    epistemologist.

     TERMS TO KNOW
    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies

    used to attain it

    Ethics

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of value and thereby seeks to

    determine right and wrong

     BIG IDEA

    Though all of these thinkers investigated many areas of philosophy, the ways in which Socrates changed

    the direction of philosophy can be simplified as follows:

    Pre-Socratics’ Primary Focus Socrates’ Primary Focus

    Key areas of philosophy Cosmology and Natural

    Philosophy

    Ethics and Epistemology

    The most important philosophical

    questions

    What is real?

    What is the nature of the

    What is knowledge?

    What is right?

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 30

    universe? What is the good life and how should

    I live?

    3. The First Step on the Path to Wisdom

    How did Socrates distinguish knowledge from opinion? First, it is a distinction in belief. But secondly, the
    distinction is not in what you believe, but in why you believe it. Two people can believe the same thing, but
    one knows why he or she believes; the other merely believes.

    What’s the difference? The answer involves the all-important philosophical question — why? If you ask
    someone, “why do you believe x?”, and he or she provides a reasonable answer that is grounded in fact, that
    person knows x. If you ask why, and receive no answer, or a bad answer (i.e., one that is not grounded in
    reason or fact), that person has an opinion about x, but does not know it.

    Here are some of the most common sources of bad answers:

    Source Example Why it falls short of knowledge

    Belief based on

    falsities

    I think we should keep capital

    punishment because it saves

    money.

    This is opinion, not knowledge, because it costs far more

    to execute someone than to imprison him/her for life.

    Belief based on

    tradition/culture

    I think that a certain race is

    inferior because that’s what

    people previously believed or

    This is opinion, not knowledge, because the statement is

    not grounded in fact or reason.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 31

    that’s what my parents told

    me.

    Belief based on

    false authority

    I believe this about the

    economy because a celebrity

    said so, or I believe that about

    climate change because a

    politician (or lobbyist) said so.

    The celebrity may very well be right, but that does not

    justify the belief. This person has an opinion about climate

    change, rather than knowledge on this topic. Difficult

    subjects require expertise, not hearsay.

    Belief based on

    confirmation

    bias

    I believe there is an afterlife

    because I cannot bear to think

    of death as the end.

    A well-documented fact about human psychology is that

    we lower our evidentiary standards when we like the

    conclusion. We raise them when we dislike the conclusion.

    “I want x to be true, therefore, x is true” is an invalid, and

    sometimes dangerous, inference.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Think of answers to “why” questions that fall into these four categories.

    First, think of examples of each in politics or a national issue.

    Next, think of personal examples of each (e.g., people you have interacted with in your family or on social

    media).

    See if you can do what Socrates requires — to shift from thinking about these mistakes in others to

    thinking about them in ourselves.

    Think of one example of when you have defended opinions in each of these ways. Socratic wisdom

    requires us to be wise by realizing that we are not wise.

    4. Socrates, A Martyr for Wisdom

    As the previous thought experiment demonstrates, it is easier to recognize the mistakes of others than those
    we make. It is easier to say than to do, to “talk the talk” than “walk the walk.” One of the most important
    aspects of Socrates’ legacy is that he lived what he taught, no matter the cost.

    While teaching (and learning) philosophy in Athens, asking “why” questions (he referred to himself as a
    gadfly), Socrates irritated people, and it got him into trouble. He was charged with corrupting the youth, and
    put on trial (this trial will be examined in detail in a subsequent tutorial). Socrates presented his own defense,
    but did so in philosophical terms. He refused to use rhetorical tricks like the sophists, and did not appeal to
    emotions (e.g., by bringing in crying family members before sentencing). He refused punishment by exile that
    would have required an implicit admission of regret for his conduct, and an end of his teaching. Had he
    accepted exile, he would have avoided execution.

    It’s unnecessary to speculate whether he was willing to die for his beliefs, or just believed that he was
    doomed either way. Later, his friend Crito provided him with an opportunity to escape from prison before his
    execution, but Socrates did not take it because he believed that it would be morally wrong for him to do so.

    It may be tempting to reason as Crito did and point out how much good Socrates could have done if he had
    escaped and resumed teaching. However, if Socrates had, in opposition to his teachings, escaped, would we
    be reading about him today? Would he have inspired Plato to pursue philosophy? Would we revere him for
    acting in a self-serving way, instead of doing what he believed was right?

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 32

    We remember and revere Socrates because he was one of the few who lived, and died, according to his
    beliefs.

    In this tutorial, we introduced Socrates, the patriarch of western philosophy, and compared his

    methodologies to the philosophers who preceded him. His intellectual offspring, including Plato and

    Aristotle, were incalculably important to the development of western civilization. Socrates reinvented

    philosophy as the discipline that it is today. He taught by example, and lived what he taught even

    though it cost him his life.
     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Bust of Socrates, PD


    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies
    that attain it
    Ethics
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of value and thereby seeks to determine
    right and wrong
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 33

    HTTPS://en.wikipedia.org/WIKI/SOCRATES#/MEDIA/FILE:SOCRATES_PIO-CLEMENTINO_INV314.JPG

    The Socratic Approach
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Socrates, the father of western philosophy, used different approaches to discover the truth,

    depending on whether a situation involved opposing viewpoints, or students who wanted to learn

    from him. His way of teaching continues to influence the manner in which philosophy is taught today,

    because it is a way that leads to understanding.

    This tutorial investigates the Socratic approach in three parts:

    1. The Character of Socrates

    2. Dialectic

    3. The

    Socratic Method

    1. The Character of Socrates

    Socrates was a man of virtue. He is remembered and revered because he lived according to his principles,
    which he believed were correct. His life was guided by what sound reasoning led him to conclude was right.
    He was a man of keen intellect and upstanding moral character.

    Socrates’ life was completely involved in the pursuit of philosophy, truth, and wisdom. What he did not know,
    he sought to discover. The Symposium describes Socrates standing outside a building before entering a party
    that was being held there, thinking about something that had been puzzling him. His extreme dedication to
    learning led him to become a teacher. Although he was an excellent instructor, he did not charge his students
    for the lessons they received. He shared wisdom with all who sought it.

    Socrates dedicated his life (and death) to doing what he thought was right, to his quest for wisdom and ethics.
    His final moments are recorded in a dialogue called the Phaedo, which will be covered in a subsequent
    tutorial. The last line of the Phaedo summarizes how he is regarded by those who knew him: “Such was the
    end…of our friend; concerning whom I may truly say, that of all the men of his time whom I have known, he
    was the wisest and justest and best.”

    2. Dialectic

    Socrates sought wisdom through philosophy. He believed that philosophy was best pursued by a method
    (carried on by Plato) called dialectic.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Dialectic
    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 34

    A discourse between two or more people of opposing viewpoints, the goal of which is to discover

    truth through reasoning

    Dialectic is a somewhat more noble endeavor than debate. The goal of a debate is to win — to use arguments
    in a way that enables your side to prevail. (The skill used to win debates is rhetoric.) Winning, however, is not
    the goal of dialectic.

    Dialectic is used to find the truth. When opposing viewpoints are involved, one is wrong, and the other is right.
    It is the dialectician’s job to determine which is which. This is a philosophical endeavor: not only because
    philosophy pursues truth and seeks to separate knowledge from opinion, but also because of the importance
    of logic and reasoning in dialectic.

    Unlike the process of rhetorical debate, only good reasoning prevails in philosophical dialectic. Since logic,
    like mathematics, is universal and dispassionate, when the truth is discovered, both sides in a dialectic can,
    should, and do recognize it. Since the emphasis is on truth and reason, bias, emotion, upbringing, and
    worldview are set aside. This makes dialectic an objective process, motivated by a genuine desire for truth on
    all sides.

    Imagine contemporary political debates being conducted in this way. If two political opponents were united in
    a search for truth, they would engage in genuine, open-minded inquiry as to what is the best course of action
    for their country, instead of the familiar quest for personal advantage and victory.

    If this seems unrealistic, focus on your own experience.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Consider whether you have ever had a discussion, perhaps with a friend or sibling, that resembled a

    dialectic. What influenced the way in which this discussion took place? First and foremost, respect. You

    didn’t assume the worst about the person with whom you were chatting. You did not immediately dismiss

    his/her position as wrong. Also, since you did not dismiss his/her position, you questioned your own view.

    The discussion was a dialectic because you disagreed respectfully, and it was fruitful because you held

    your own view as being subject to questioning, rather than as inviolable. Neither of you tried to prove the

    other wrong. Together, you were simply searching what is true.

    Socrates conducted all of his inquiries in this way and did not assume that any of his beliefs were inviolable.
    When following this standard, it does not matter whether you respect the person with whom you disagree, or
    whether you respect his or her point of view. All that matters is that you respect truth. If you do, you will
    ensure that all of your beliefs are true (or not) by questioning them. You will care enough about truth to share
    it with others.

    3. The Socratic Method

    Dialectic is used by those who hold opposing viewpoints to dispassionately search for truth. Although the
    opponents initially disagree, they do so respectfully. A different method is required when one who knows a
    truth wants to teach it to others. When teaching, Socrates used the Socratic Method.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Socratic Method

    The pedagogical method of teaching by asking questions to which the student knows the answers,

    thereby leading them, step by step, to the truth being taught

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 35

    Suppose a teacher has taught students how to multiply using flashcards, and is moving on to more
    complicated multiplication problems.

    Example of the Socratic Method

    Teacher: Do you know what 8 times 72 is?

    Student: No, I don’t.

    Teacher: Do you know what 8 times 2 is?

    Student: Of course, it’s 16.

    Teacher: Do you know what 8 times 3 is?

    Student: Of course, it’s 24.

    Teacher: And what about 8 times 5?

    Student: It’s 40.

    Teacher: And 3 plus 2?

    Student: 5, of

    course.

    Teacher: And 3 times 8 plus 2 times 8.

    Student: …40.

    Teacher: So to compute 5 times 8, we can add two numbers that equal 5, eight times, then add their

    products?

    Student: It seems so.

    Teacher: Does it work with 1 times 8 and 4 times 8?

    Student: Yes!

    Teacher: It should always work, since we know that multiplication is a complex form of addition. How

    might we multiply 72 times 8?

    Student: Multiply some numbers that add to 72 by 8 and add their products.

    Teacher: And which numbers might be easier?

    Student: The ones I know.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 36

    Teacher: Good, so you already know 8 times 2.

    Student: Yes, 16.

    Teacher: What would we have to add to 2 to get 72?

    Student: 70.

    Teacher: What is 8 times 70?

    Student: I don’t know.

    Teacher: What is 8 times 7?

    Student: 56.

    Teacher: So if 70 is seven tens, isn’t 8 times 70, 56 tens?

    Student: It must be!

    Teacher: So what is 8 times 70?

    Student: 560!

    Teacher: And what is 8 times 72?

    Student: 576!!!

    In this example, the teacher has taught the student something new. This new knowledge will be the basis for
    solving longer multiplication problems. The teacher demonstrated how new knowledge can be achieved,
    starting from what the student already knows. This teaching method has two advantages: Student who have
    accomplished some basic learning don’t need to “reinvent the wheel” when attempting to answer more
    difficult questions. They can leverage what they already know.

    Additionally (and more importantly, with respect to philosophy, and to life), by beginning with what he or she
    already knows, and comprehending why the answer is what it is, students understand that an answer is true.
    This is the advantage of the Socratic Method. It is still used in schools, from the elementary through the
    doctoral level. It is an effective tool for teaching understanding because it leads the student to knowledge,
    instead of dictating it. It shows students how to achieve knowledge on their own, rather than simply giving
    them a collection of facts.

    Socrates is not only known for his constant quest for wisdom, and his rigorous commitment to right

    living, but also for his teaching method. He believed that truth and wisdom should be shared, not

    hoarded. He used dialectic to discover truth, and the Socratic Method to help others find it.

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 37

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Quotation from “The Phaedo” | Author: Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain


    Dialectic

    A discourse between two or more people of opposing viewpoints, the ultimate goal of which is to

    discover the truth of the matter through reasoning

    Socratic Method

    The pedagogical method of teaching by asking questions to which the student knows the answer and

    thereby leading them to the truth being conveyed

    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 38

    http://www.gutenberg.org/ebooks/1658?msg=welcome_stranger

    Introducing Arguments
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Philosophy uses argumentation to attain truth. To learn how to evaluate arguments, we must first

    define argument.

    This tutorial examines argumentation and its role in philosophy, in two parts:

    1. What is an Argument?

    2. The Basics of Evaluation

    1. What is an Argument?

    In philosophy, arguments provide justification for proposed positions. When successful, an argument provides
    a reason (or reasons) to believe that something is true. Aristotle provided the following example of a simple
    argument:

    All men are mortal.

    Socrates is a man.

    Therefore, Socrates is mortal.

    Think of the argument as an equation. The first two statements (both of which are called premises) combine to
    yield the third (the conclusion). Hence, if we know the two premises, we also know the conclusion.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Premise

    A statement presented in an argument for acceptance or rejection without support, but that is

    intended

    to support a conclusion

    Conclusion

    A statement that is intended to be supported by the premises of an argument

    As we will see, the argument above provides justification for thinking that Socrates is mortal. To do so, it must

    accomplish two things. Every argument makes both a factual claim and an inferential claim.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Factual Claim

    A claim that some fact (or facts) corresponds to reality

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 39

    Inferential Claim

    A claim that the premises support the conclusion

    Note that we are currently defining what makes an argument, not what makes a good argument. It is important

    to understand that claiming that a fact corresponds to reality does not guarantee that it does (“Socrates was a

    fire-breathing lizard who ravaged the streets of Tokyo” is a factual claim), and claiming that premises support a

    conclusion does not mean that they do. These two claims must be evaluated to determine the success of an

    argument, as will be discussed below. An argument is defined as follows:

     TERM TO KNOW

    Argument

    A group of statements containing both a factual claim or claims and an inferential claim or

    claims

    An argument must contain both types of claims; and all groups of statements that contain both types of claims

    are arguments. Regarding the statements provided above, in order for them to form an argument, they

    (together) must make a factual claim or claims.

     TRY IT

    See if you can find the factual claims in Aristotle’s argument, above.

     HINT

    Factual claims are submitted as true, but without support. The argument itself (i.e., the three sentences

    provided above) includes no reasons to support the claims made in it.

    The two factual claims in this argument are “All men are mortal” and “Socrates is a man”. Notice that they are
    presented as givens with no support or reason to believe them. However, “Socrates is mortal” is not a factual
    claim. Why not? Think in terms of support. Does Aristotle’s argument (just those three sentences, not your
    beliefs) provide any reason to believe that “All men are mortal” is true? It is simply an assertion about the way
    the world is.

    The same can be said about “Socrates is a man.” However, we are provided with a reason to believe that
    Socrates is mortal: it follows from the two claims which precede it. In an argument, a factual claim is the same
    as a premise.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    See if you can find the inferential claim.

     HINT

    Although a premise is the same as a factual claim, a conclusion is not the same as an inferential claim.

    Why not? Look at the definition of an inferential claim. Since the inferential claim links the premises and

    the conclusion, it cannot be synonymous with either.

    In this argument, the inferential claim is the word, “therefore.” An inferential claim is the assertion that the
    premises support the conclusion. That’s what “therefore” does in this argument. It tells you that an inference is
    being made, that something has been supported rather than simply presented. However, not every argument
    uses “therefore.” It’s best to think of the parts of an argument in terms of how they support (the premises) and
    supported (the conclusion). The inferential claim asserts that such support is available.

    All men are mortal.

    Premise/Factual Claim

    Socrates is a man. Premise/Factual Claim

    Therefore, Inferential Claim

    Socrates is mortal. Conclusion

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 40

     TRY IT

    Identify the factual and inferential claims in the following argument by first identifying the premises and

    the conclusion:

    No dogs are crocodiles, because all dogs are

    mammals and no crocodiles are mammals.

     HINT

    The conclusion is not always at the end.

     HINT

    Does “because” indicate that something is supported or supporting?
    In the argument above, “all dogs are mammals” and “no crocodiles are mammals” are the premises and are,
    therefore, factual claims. The conclusion is “no dogs are crocodiles”, since it follows from the two premises.
    What is the inferential claim? In this argument, it is implicit. The word, “because” indicates that the latter two
    statements are premises which support the prior statement. As a result, the inferential claim would be
    something like, “the fact that no dogs are crocodiles follows from the facts that all dogs are mammals and no
    crocodiles are mammals.” It is important to understand that not every argument will include inferential
    indicators. Readers must recognize what supports what.

    All dogs are mammals. Premise/Factual Claim

    No crocodiles are mammals. Premise/Factual Claim

    No dogs are crocodiles. Conclusion

    The fact that no dogs are crocodiles follows from the facts that all dogs are

    mammals and no crocodiles are mammals.
    Inferential Claim
    2. The Basics of Evaluation

    As mentioned above, every argument makes both a factual and an inferential claim. It must do both of these
    things well in order to succeed (i.e., to provide reason to believe the conclusion). This means that we must
    evaluate both the factual and inferential claims, separately. The inferential claim must be evaluated first, for
    two reasons: 1) it is the fastest way to evaluate an argument; 2) if the inference is bad, the facts don’t matter.

    Consider the following argument:

    There are 21,354,751 people in Ohio. Therefore, there are more than 10,000,000 people in Ohio.

    It is simple to check the inference — that 21,354,751 is greater than 10,000,000 — but checking the fact would
    require more research. We’d have to determine whether there are truly 21,354,751 people in Ohio, a time-
    consuming task. However, there is a much more important reason to check the inference first. Suppose
    someone made the following argument:

    Kim Kardashian wore a purple hat today. Therefore, there will be a blizzard in the Northeast tomorrow.

    Suppose you lived in the Northeast, and were planning your activities for next few days. If someone made this
    argument to you, would you check the color of Kim Kardashian’s hat to see whether you need to change your
    plans? Probably not, because if the inference is bad, the facts do not matter. Even if the hat claim is true (i.e.,
    Kim Kardashian wore a purple hat today), it provides no reason to believe the conclusion (i.e., that there will be
    a blizzard). The inferential claim of the argument must be evaluated first.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 41

    When evaluating an inference, the question is never, “Are the premises true?” Instead, questions of inference
    ask, “Assuming the premises are true, do they support the conclusion?” Consider this argument:

    All Republicans are space aliens.

    Barack Obama is a Republican.

    Therefore, Barack Obama is a

    space alien.

    Obviously, there is something wrong with this argument. However, let’s check the inference. We ask,
    “Assuming it’s true that all Republicans are space aliens and Barack Obama is a Republican, would this
    support the conclusion that Barack Obama is a space alien?” The answer is yes. This inference here is sound
    (notice that it is the same inference used by Aristotle in his argument above). The problem with this argument
    is the factual claim.

    To test the factual claim, ask, “Are all of the premises true?” Aristotle’s argument contains a good inferential
    claim and a good factual claim. The Obama argument includes a good inferential claim but a bad factual claim.
    See if you can provide the proper (but separate) evaluations of the inferential and factual claims of the
    following three arguments:

     TRY IT

    LeBron James is over five feet tall. (Premise)

    Therefore, LeBron James is over seven feet tall. (Conclusion)
    The inference in this argument is unsound. From the fact that a person is over five feet tall, it does not follow
    that he or she is over seven feet tall, (or that he or she is over six feet tall). However, the factual claim is sound,
    because LeBron James is over five feet tall (note that the factual claim verifies the premises, not the
    conclusion).

     TRY IT

    LeBron James is over twelve feet tall. (Premise)

    Therefore, Lebron James is over seven feet tall. (Conclusion)
    We can determine whether the inference is sound by asking, “Assuming that it is true that LeBron James is
    over twelve feet tall, does it follow that he is over seven feet tall?” In this case, the answer is “yes,” so the
    inference is a good one. However, since he is not over twelve feet tall, the factual claim falls short.

     TRY IT
    LeBron James is over five feet tall. (Premise)

    Therefore, LeBron James is over six feet tall. (Conclusion)
    This argument can be evaluated in the same way as the first argument in this example. Even though LeBron
    James is over six feet tall, it does not follow from the fact that he is over five feet tall. Therefore, even if you
    believe that he is over six feet tall, this argument provides no support for that

    belief.

     MAKE THE CONNECTION

    Why bother trying to understand philosophical arguments? Whether or not you realize it, you make

    arguments in everyday life. Even something as simple as this qualifies as an argument: “When it is cold

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 42

    outside, I wear my jacket. Today it is cold outside. Therefore I should wear my jacket.” Understanding and

    evaluating arguments are useful abilities. See if you can recognize examples of arguments in your day-to-

    day life.

    Philosophical analysis is not required to evaluate the argument involving your jacket. As we begin to realize
    when we (or others) are making an argument, we will also begin to evaluate them: to determine when their
    conclusions follow from their premises, and when they do not.

    Suppose someone told you, “We should use capital punishment because it is cheaper than imprisonment for
    life.” They have made an argument. They only support their conclusion that we should use capital punishment
    by claiming that it is cheaper. If we were only interested in financial costs, this would be a good inferential
    claim. However, since it costs more money to execute someone than to imprison them for life, it is a bad
    factual claim. This could be the focus of further discussion of the issue.

    Argumentation is the way that philosophy seeks truth. Understanding how to evaluate an argument is

    an important skill. Every argument makes both a factual and an inferential claim. In order to be

    successful (i.e., to provide reason to accept the conclusion), it must do both well. Therefore, every

    argument requires two independent evaluations.


    Argument
    A group of statements containing both a factual claim or claims and an inferential claim or claims
    Conclusion
    A statement that is intended to be supported by the premises of an argument
    Factual Claim

    A claim that some fact or facts obtained in the world is true

    Premise

    A statement presented for acceptance or rejection in an argument (without support) but that is intended

    to support a conclusion

    ​Inferential Claim
    A claim that the premises support the conclusion

    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 43

    Evaluation and Analysis of Arguments
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Every argument must make both an inferential and a factual claim. To succeed, an argument must do

    both things well, but each must be evaluated separately. However, before we can precisely evaluate

    an argument, we must know whether it is deductive or inductive. Knowing this tells us how strict the

    standards are for the inference, and enables us to evaluate each argument accordingly.

    This tutorial examines the evaluation and analysis of arguments in three parts:

    1. Deduction and Induction

    2. Evaluating Deductive Arguments

    3. Evaluating Inductive Arguments

    1. Deduction and Induction

    Consider this argument: “People are under seven feet tall, so the next person to come through the door will
    be under seven feet tall.” Is this reasonable or unreasonable? The answer depends on what was intended. If
    the intention was to assert that “All people are under seven feet tall, so it is guaranteed that the next person
    to come through the door will be under seven feet tall,” then this is a foolish argument. However, if the
    intended meaning was “People are generally under seven feet tall, so the next person to come through the
    door will likely be under seven feet tall,” the argument is reasonable. Note that these two different evaluations
    depend on whether the claim was about certainty or likelihood.

    These considerations are closely linked to the concepts of deductive and inductive arguments. Reviewing the
    terms below will help you to understand these concepts.

     TERMS TO KNOW
    Argument

    A group of statements containing both a factual claim (or claims), and an inferential claim (or claims)

    Factual Claim
    A claim that some fact (or facts) corresponds to reality
    Inferential Claim
    A claim that the premises support the conclusion

    Deductive Argument

    A type of argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty

    Logical Certainty

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 44

    A state in which it is inconceivable that the conclusion is not supported by the premises

    Inductive Argument

    An argument in which the inferential claim is of less than logical certainty

    Premise

    A statement presented for acceptance or rejection in an argument without support, but that is

    intended to support a conclusion

    Conclusion
    A statement that is intended to be supported by the premises of an argument

    You cannot properly evaluate a sophisticated argument without first identifying whether it is deductive or

    inductive. This is so because the evaluations are different. All evaluation is based on kind.

     EXAMPLE When someone asks, “Is 6’10” inches tall?” the only proper answer is, “It depends on
    what kind of thing you’re asking about” because “tall” is an evaluative term. Is 6’10” tall? For a human,

    yes. For a giraffe, no. Similarly, if someone asks, “is this a good inference,” the only proper answer is,

    “it depends on the kind of inference.” And as the first argument in this section demonstrates, we

    evaluate differently depending on whether we are trying to achieve logical certainty or probability.

    For the original example, a statement that “People are generally under seven feet tall, so the next person to
    come through the door will likely be under seven feet tall” indicates that most people who pass through the
    door will be shorter than seven feet tall, but some of them may be taller.

    People are generally under 7 feet tall. Premise/Factual Claim

    So, Inferential Claim

    the next person to come through the door will likely be under 7 feet tall. Conclusion

    Is this argument intending logical certainty? Does it assert that, because people are usually under seven feet
    tall, it is not possible that a person over seven feet tall will walk through the door? It does not. Therefore, this is
    an inductive argument (a generalization) that does not convey logical certainty, only probability. We must
    evaluate it accordingly.

    Now consider the following argument:

    The sun has risen every day for the past billion years.

    Our current understanding of the laws of astrophysics tell us that this phenomenon

    should continue.

    Therefore, the sun will rise tomorrow.

    The sun has risen every day for the past billion years. Premise/Factual Claim

    Our current understanding of the laws of astrophysics tell us that this phenomenon

    should continue.
    Premise/Factual Claim
    Therefore, Inferential Claim

    the sun will rise tomorrow. Conclusion

    Before we evaluate this argument, we must first determine whether it is deductive or inductive: whether the
    conclusion is intended to follow with logical certainty. Can you imagine not only that the premises are true
    (which should not be difficult because they are true), but also the conclusion being false (at the same time)?
    You can.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 45

    Imagine that a meteor obliterates Earth tonight, or a religious apocalypse occurs, or the sun enters the “red
    giant” phase of its life-cycle and consumes Mercury, Venus, and Earth. In all of these cases the conclusion will
    not be reached.

    Based on what we have just learned, this argument is inductive because it makes no claim to logical

    certainty.

    However, certainty that the sun will rise tomorrow is inductive certainty. This indicates two things: First, there is
    nothing wrong with induction, just because it is induction. It is not unreasonable to believe that the sun will rise
    tomorrow. (Problems generally arise only when people evaluate induction deductively, or vice versa.) Second,
    the vast majority of our reasoning is inductive, so the vast majority of our beliefs are justified inductively.

    Consider some more of your beliefs that are based on induction: that your parents really are your parents; that
    Julius Caesar lived; that summer is warm and winter is cold; that your arm won’t fall off in the next 30 seconds;
    etc.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Consider the arguments that you would use to justify these beliefs, and why none of them achieve logical

    certainty.

    But if the majority of our reasoning is inductive, what is deduction? Note that induction always involves cause
    and effect, and the world, in making inferences. Deduction involves neither of these. The inferences of
    deduction rely on definition and form.

     EXAMPLE LeBron James is over six feet tall. Therefore, he is over five feet tall.
    It would be incorrect to assert that the fact that LeBron James is over six feet tall causes him to be over five
    feet tall. Instead, it is part of the definition of being over six feet tall, an entailment. Note that this type of
    argument does attain logical certainty, but remember that logical certainty is about the relationship between
    the premises and the conclusion, not just about the conclusion. Therefore, the question is not “can I imagine
    LeBron James not being over five feet tall?” (you can). Instead, it is “can I imagine him being over six feet tall”
    and “not being over five feet tall?” No, this is impossible. This argument attains logical certainty because it is
    about definitions, rather than the world. Other common deductive arguments are categorical (from the
    definitions of “all”, “no”, and “some”), hypothetical (from the definition of “if…then”) and disjunctive (from the
    meaning of “either/or”).

    2. Evaluating Deductive Arguments

    Once we have determined whether an argument is deductive or inductive, the evaluation follows the pattern
    discussed in previous tutorials, but with more precision. We still ask the inferential question first: “Assuming all
    premises are true, do they support the conclusion?” However, now we understand the notion of support
    deductively, that is, as guaranteeing or logically entailing the conclusion. When considering an inferential
    claim deductively, we label the argument as valid or in

    valid.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Valid

    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) logically guarantee their conclusion

    Invalid

    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) do not logically guarantee their conclusion

    A valid argument must have good deductive structure; an invalid argument has bad deductive structure and

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 46

    that is all. Whether the premises are true or false (i.e., whether the factual claim is a good one or not), does not

    have anything to do with the argument’s validity. Consider this categorical syllogism:

    All Republicans are space aliens.
    Barack Obama is a Republican.
    Therefore, Barack Obama is a space alien.

    This argument is valid. We ask, “If it is true that all Republicans are space aliens and it is true that Barack
    Obama is a Republican, does that guarantee that Barack Obama is a space alien?” The answer is yes. We
    must establish an argument’s validity (or lack of it) before checking the factual claims. Now try to evaluate
    these three arguments (the solutions are provided below):

     TRY IT

    1. LeBron James is over five feet tall.

    Therefore, LeBron James is over seven feet tall.

    2. LeBron James is over twelve feet tall.

    Therefore, Lebron James is over seven feet tall.

    3. LeBron James is over five feet tall.

    Therefore, LeBron James is over six feet tall.
    Solutions

    1. Ask yourself, if it is true that Lebron James is over five feet tall, then does it guarantee that he is over seven
    feet tall?
    The answer is “no”, so this argument is invalid.

    2. Ask yourself, if it is true that Lebron James is over twelve feet tall, then does it guarantee that he is over
    seven feet tall?
    The answer is “yes”, so this is argument is valid.

    3. Ask yourself, if it is true that Lebron James is over five feet tall, then does it guarantee that he is over six
    feet tall?
    The answer is no, so

    this is an invalid argument.

    Whether or not the premises or conclusion are true does not enter into the determination of validity. However,
    validity is important because it means that the premises guarantee the conclusion. When validity has been
    established, we simply have to decide whether we accept the premises. If the argument is valid, we only need
    to ask a question of fact: “Are all of the premises true?” This will determine the soundness or unsoundness of
    the argument.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Sound

    A deductively valid argument in which all premises are true

    Unsound

    A deductive argument that is not sound

    Note that a sound argument must be valid. Think of a sound argument as a good deductive argument. Since

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 47

    an argument must do two things, a sound argument is a deductive argument that does both of them well. It

    makes a good (i.e., valid) inferential claim and a good factual claim. As a result, a sound argument has a

    conclusion that is guaranteed, that cannot be resisted. That’s why soundness matters.

    An unsound argument is a bad deductive argument. It falls short of soundness by either making a bad (i.e.,
    invalid) inferential claim or by containing at least one false premise. It does not provide an adequate reason to
    accept its conclusion. Invalid arguments — and valid arguments with at least one false premise — are
    unsound. Each of these types of arguments gives reason to not accept its conclusion.

    Note that if one wants to reject the conclusion of a valid argument, one must reject a premise. Try to evaluate
    the following argument:

    If there is gratuitous evil, there is no God.
    There is gratuitous evil.
    Ergo, there is no God.

    This is a deductively valid argument known as the Logical Problem of Evil. To reject the conclusion, that is, to
    maintain that there is a God, we must show that a premise is false or (as is more generally the case in a
    philosophical debate), that there is a better reason to believe that the premise is false than to believe it is true.
    Because this argument is valid, we are left with no other options if we want to reject the conclusion.

    3. Evaluating Inductive Arguments

    With a few minor changes, everything that applies to deductive arguments also applies to inductive
    arguments. The inferential question must be asked first: “Assuming all premises are true, do they support the
    conclusion?” However, in the case of inductive arguments, the notion of support is understood inductively,
    that is, as making probable the conclusion. When considering an inferential claim inductively, we say that the
    argument is strong or weak.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Strong

    An inductive argument in which the premises render the conclusion probable

    Weak

    An inductive argument in which the premises do not render the conclusion probable

    Hence, a strong argument has a good inductive structure; a weak argument has a bad inductive structure and

    that is all. Whether the premises are true or false does not have anything to do with an argument’s strength.

    Consider the following argument:

    The overwhelming majority of climate scientists believe that there is climate change caused by humans.
    Therefore, there is climate change caused by humans.

    This is an inductive argument called an “argument from authority.” To determine its strength, the question to
    be asked isn’t whether scientists believe such a thing but, if they do believe such a thing, does that make the
    conclusion probable? In this case, the answer is yes, so the argument is strong.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Arguments from authority are some of the strongest we have. Consider the following things you believe

    that are based on authority:

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 48

    You’ve never met Julius Caesar, but you believe he existed

    You’ve never been to Uranus, but you believe it exists

    You cannot predict the weather, but you believe the meteorologist’s prediction

    The fact that authorities are occasionally wrong doesn’t make the argument weak, it makes it

    inductive.

    Now consider three more inductive arguments and see if you can determine their strength or weakness:

     TRY IT

    Kim Kardashian says X about healthcare.

    Therefore, X about healthcare.

     HINT

    “X” doesn’t need to be filled in because that is only relevant to the factual claim.

    The answer is that this argument is weak. Kim Kardashian may be an authority about some things, but she is
    not generally considered an authority on healthcare, even if you agree with her. Agreeing with her means that
    you accept the conclusion, not that the argument establishes it. If the only reason we have to believe X about
    healthcare is that Kim Kardashian said X, that is not enough for us to believe that X is true.

     TRY IT

    The Browns have played terribly so far this season.

    Therefore, they will lose this

    week.

    This argument is strong (it is a prediction, in which we use the past to assert the future). If it is true that the
    Browns have played terribly all season, we might bet (perhaps literally) that they will lose this week. It is a
    good bet. If we lose our bet, it’s because induction involves chance, not because our bet is irrational.

     TRY IT

    Some people got sick from eating at the restaurant.

    Therefore, I will get sick from eating

    there.

    This argument is weak because the conclusion is possible, not probable. Because induction deals in
    probability, it also involves scaling, because it makes sense to talk about stronger arguments and weaker
    arguments. This is unlike a deduction, in which premises establish their conclusion with either 100% or 0%
    certainty. For example, both the conclusion that the sun will rise tomorrow, and that the Browns will lose this
    week, are supported by strong arguments, but we should be more certain of one than the other.

    After we have determined strength, we must check the factual claim and ask, “Are all of the premises true?” to
    establish whether the final evaluation is cogent or uncogent.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Cogent

    An inductively strong argument in which all premises are true

    Uncogent

    An inductive argument that is not cogent

    Note that a cogent argument must be strong. Cogent arguments are good inductive arguments. Since an

    argument must do two things, a cogent argument is an inductive argument that does both of them well. It

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 49

    makes a good (i.e., strong) inferential claim and a good factual claim. Therefore, a cogent argument provides

    us with reason to believe that its conclusion is probably true (how probable is proportionate to how strong).
    An uncogent argument is a bad inductive argument. It falls short of cogency by either making a bad (i.e.,
    weak) inferential claim or by containing at least one false premise. It does not provide an adequate reason to
    accept its conclusion. Therefore, weak arguments, and strong arguments with at least one false premise, are
    uncogent. Either of them gives us reason to not accept their conclusions.

    The flow chart below is a useful tool to which you can refer when evaluating arguments.

    Before we evaluate an argument, we must first determine whether it attempts to establish its

    conclusion using logical certainty, which (therefore) makes it deductive, or something less, which

    makes it inductive. Once we have determined this, we can check the inferential claims in a more

    refined way, using the concepts of valid and invalid for deduction, and strong and weak for induction.

    We then consider the factual claim to arrive at a final evaluation of the argument: sound and unsound

    for deductive arguments; cogent and uncogent for inductive arguments.


    Argument
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 50

    A group of statements containing both a factual claim or claims and an inferential claim or claims
    Cogent
    An inductively strong argument in which all premises are true
    Conclusion
    A statement that is intended to be supported by the premises of an argument
    Deductive Argument
    A type of argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty
    Factual Claim
    A claim that some fact or facts obtained in the world is true
    Inductive Argument
    An argument in which the inferential claim is of less than logical certainty
    Inferential Claim
    A claim that the premises support the conclusion
    Invalid
    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) do not logically guarantee their conclusion
    Logical Certainty
    A state in which it is inconceivable that the conclusion is not supported by the premises
    Premise

    A statement presented for acceptance of rejection in an argument without support but that is intended

    to support a conclusion
    Sound
    A deductively valid argument in which all premises are true
    Strong
    An inductive argument in which the premises render the conclusion probable
    Uncogent
    An inductive argument that is not cogent
    Unsound
    A deductive argument that is not sound
    Valid
    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) logically guarantee their conclusion
    Weak
    An inductive argument in which the premises do not render the conclusion probable

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 51

    Evaluating an Argument in Action
    by Sophia Tutorial

    In this tutorial, we will use what we’ve learned about arguments to evaluate an argument. We will

    review the types of arguments and related terminology, and evaluate several sample arguments in

    context.

    This tutorial considers the evaluation of arguments in three parts:

    1. Deduction and Induction

    2. Evaluating Inductive and Deductive Arguments

    3. Practice Evaluating an Argument

    1. Deduction and Induction

    Recall the definitions of inductive and deductive, as they relate to arguments.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Deductive

    An argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty

    Inductive

    An argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of less than logical certainty

    When determining whether an argument is inductive or deductive, ask this question: “Is the inferential claim a

    claim of logical certainty?” If the answer is yes, the argument is deductive. If the answer is no, the argument is

    inductive.

    You cannot properly evaluate a sophisticated argument without first identifying whether it is deductive or
    inductive.

    2. Evaluating Inductive and Deductive Arguments

    Once you have determined whether an argument is inductive or deductive, ask this question: “Assuming all
    premises are true, do they support the conclusion?” For deductive arguments, is it possible for all of the
    premises to be true, and the conclusion false? For inductive arguments, is it probable for all premises to be
    true and the conclusion false? You are essentially trying to determine whether the premises guarantee the
    conclusion, or not.

    For deductive arguments, we use the terms valid and invalid. For inductive arguments we use the terms

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 52

    strong and weak.

     TERMS TO KNOW
    Valid
    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) logically guarantee their conclusion
    Invalid
    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) do not logically guarantee their conclusion
    Strong
    An inductive argument in which the premises render the conclusion probable
    Weak
    An inductive argument in which the premises do not render the conclusion probable

    A valid argument has a good deductive structure, and an invalid argument has a bad deductive structure and

    that is all. Whether the premises are true or false (i.e., whether the factual claim is a good one or not), does not

    have anything to do with validity. Likewise, a strong argument is one that has good inductive structure; a weak

    one has bad inductive structure and that is all. Whether the premises are true or false does not have anything

    to do with strength.

    Here are some examples:

    Sample Argument Deductive

    or

    Inductive?

    Valid, Invalid, Strong, or Weak?

    All Republicans are

    space aliens. Barack

    Obama is a

    Republican. Therefore,

    Barack Obama is a

    space alien.

    Deductive. Valid. Ask yourself, “If it is true that all Republicans are space aliens, and

    it is true that Barack Obama is a Republican, does that guarantee that

    Barack Obama is a space alien?” The answer is yes. The argument is

    valid.

    LeBron James is over

    five feet tall. Therefore,

    LeBron James is over

    seven feet tall.

    Deductive. Invalid. Ask yourself, “If it is true that Lebron James is over five feet tall,

    does it guarantee that he is over seven feet tall?” The answer is “no”, so

    this is an invalid argument.

    Some people got sick

    eating at the

    restaurant. Therefore, I

    will get sick eating

    there.

    Inductive. Weak. This argument is weak because the conclusion is possible, but it

    is not probable.

    The Browns have

    played terribly all

    season. Therefore,

    they will lose this

    week.

    Inductive. Strong. Ask yourself, “Is it probable for all of the premises to be true and

    the conclusion to be false?” The answer is no, so it is a strong argument.

    If it was true that the Browns have played terribly all season, I would bet

    they would lose. it is a good bet. If I lose my bet, it’s because induction

    involves chance, not because I have done something irrational.

    The last step in evaluating an argument is to check the factual claims. Whether the premises or conclusion are
    true or not does not enter into the determination of validity (deductive arguments) or strength (inductive

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 53

    arguments). However, validity and strength are important because they indicate that the premises lead to the
    conclusion.

    After that, we simply have to decide whether we accept the premises. If the argument has been determined to
    be valid or strong, we simply need to ask our question of fact: “Are all of the premises true?” This will
    determine whether a valid argument is sound or unsound (deductive arguments), or a strong argument is
    cogent or uncogent (inductive arguments).

     TERMS TO KNOW
    Sound
    A deductively valid argument in which all premises are true
    Unsound
    A deductive argument that is not sound
    Cogent
    An inductively strong argument in which all premises are true
    Uncogent
    An inductive argument that is not cogent

    This flow chart can be a helpful tool when evaluating an argument.

    3. Practice Evaluating an Argument

    Let’s apply what you’ve learned to a few examples. In these examples evaluate the argument by determining
    if it is:

    1. Inductive or deductive

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 54

    2. Valid, invalid, weak, or strong

    3. Sound, unsound, cogent, or uncogent

     TRY IT

    Evaluate the following two arguments by first determining whether they are deductive or inductive, then

    evaluating their inferential claim and, finally, evaluating their factual claims.

     EXAMPLE If you are in Texas, you are in the United States. You are in the United States.
    Therefore, you are in Texas

    This is a deductive argument. The conclusion follows from the meaning of an if-then statement, not from facts
    about geography. Note that the argument includes nothing related to causation. It is about definition. Next,
    evaluate the inferential claim: does the inference attain logical certainty, or can you imagine the premises
    being true, and the conclusion false? For most students, both premises are true and the conclusion is false
    (e.g., if you are in Michigan). This means that it is invalid, because even if you happen to be in Texas, that is
    not entailed by the premises. Since it is invalid, it must be unsound because it is not a satisfactory deductive
    argument.

     EXAMPLE In the past, when I have had more than five drinks, I have become ill. Therefore, if I
    have ten drinks, I will become extremely ill

    This argument is inductive because it relies on cause and effect (it is a prediction, because it is forecasting a
    similar cause and effect in the future). When we ask our inference question, we see that the conclusion is
    likely, given the premise. Therefore, the argument is strong. If the single premise is true, it is cogent;
    otherwise, it is uncogent.

     EXAMPLE All birds can fly. Polly is a bird. Therefore, Polly can fly
    This is a deductive argument because it proceeds from the definition of “all” rather than facts about biology.
    Next, evaluate the inferential claim. Can you imagine an instance in which the premises are true, but the
    conclusion is false? The answer is no, therefore, this argument is valid. Finally, evaluate the factual claims.
    While “Polly is a bird” might be true, the statement that “all birds can fly” is not. There are several species of
    flightless birds (penguins, ostriches, kiwis, etc.). Therefore, this argument is unsound.

    Before evaluating an argument, we must determine whether it tries to establish its conclusion using

    logical certainty (which makes it a deductive argument), or something less (which makes it an

    inductive argument). Once we have made this determination, we check the inferential claim in a more

    refined way, using the concepts of valid and invalid for deduction, and strong and weak for induction.

    We then consider the factual claim to render a final evaluation of the argument: sound or unsound for

    deductive arguments; cogent or uncogent for inductive arguments.


    Cogent

    An inductively strong argument with all true premises

    Deductive
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 55

    An argument whose inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty

    Inductive

    An argument whose inferential claim is a claim less than logical certainty

    Invalid
    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) do not logically guarantee their conclusion
    Sound

    A deductively valid argument with all true premises

    Strong
    An inductive argument in which the premises render the conclusion probable
    Uncogent
    An inductive argument that is not cogent
    Unsound
    A deductive argument that is not sound
    Valid

    A deductive argument whose premise(s) logically guarantee their conclusion

    Weak
    An inductive argument in which the premises do not render the conclusion probable

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 56

    The Apology: A Defense of Philosophy
    by Sophia Tutorial

    The Apology, a mistranslation of apologia, Greek for “defense,” is a transcript of the defense Socrates’

    presented at his trial on charges of “denying the gods” and, more seriously, “corrupting the youth of

    Athens.” As Socrates pointed out, however, his real crimes were unpopularity and making enemies of

    the wrong people. Since his practice of philosophy led to the charges against him, Socrates sought to

    prove his innocence by demonstrating that philosophy is a right and worthwhile pursuit. He made

    concise arguments to support his claim that he did not corrupt the youth of Athens, and let his

    accusers know that he did not fear death. This tutorial examines The Apology in four parts:

    1. The Apology

    2. Socrates’ Argued That He Did Not Corrupt the Youth

    3. The Unexamined Life Is Not Worth Living

    4. Death Is Nothing or Something

    1. The Apology

    The Apology takes the form of a long, complex dialogue. It is Plato’s account of the defense Socrates’
    presented at his trial. Remember, Socrates produced no written work. Most accounts of his life and philosophy
    were recorded by Plato.

    The Apology begins after the prosecution presented its case, as Socrates offered his defense. He started by
    distinguishing between the “old charges” and the “new charges.” By “new charges,” he meant the official
    charges: denying the gods and corrupting the youth of Athens. But what were the “old charges?”

    To grasp their significance, understand that Athens, at that time, was a direct democracy with no constitution.
    This resulted in mob rule, or rule by the bottom 51%. If someone was sufficiently unpopular, an enemy could
    make up charges against him and demand a court hearing. This is what happened to Socrates. The “old
    charges” were, collectively, an attack on his reputation as a philosopher, teacher, and honorable man.

    Socrates’ unpopularity, for the most part, was the result of a peculiar occurrence. One of his friends was told
    by the Oracle of Delphi, who was believed to speak for Apollo, that there was no one wiser than Socrates.
    Socrates was puzzled by this message. He had always thought of himself as being without wisdom. He asked
    the philosopher’s question — why? — and worked to decipher the Oracle’s proclamation. He began by
    attempting to discover why three groups that were thought to be wise — the poets, the politicians, and the
    craftsmen — weren’t, according to the Oracle, wiser than Socrates.

    Socrates found the poets to be unwise because, although they created beautiful poems, they relied on others
    to interpret and provide meaning (poetry was composed differently at that time). As to the politicians, consider
    who would be elected in a direct democracy with no constitution. Those who could sway the mob to support

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 57

    them would win. Most successful politicians were members of a group of private tutors called sophists, who
    taught rhetoric. The goal of rhetoric is persuasion, not the attainment of truth. Socrates believed that winning
    at any cost, without regard for truth, was unwise and immoral. He made enemies of the sophists when he
    revealed that they would say anything to gain political power. The sophists turned the masses against
    Socrates, and originated the charges against him.

    The artisans, the remaining group that was thought to be wise, but wasn’t, regularly made a particular mistake.
    They believed that their expertise within their fields of endeavor made them experts in other fields. Anyone
    who has been condescended to by an I.T. expert, or who has watched an actor lecture about economics,
    knows why Socrates found this group to be unwise.

    Upon completing his investigation of the three groups, Socrates discovered why the Oracle declared that he
    was wise: It was because he knew that he was not wise. He knew what he did not know, a concept that is now
    called Socratic Wisdom. Socrates solved the Oracle’s puzzle but, in doing so, made many influential enemies.

     DID YOU KNOW

    Another source of Socrates’ reputation is The Clouds — a play by the comedic playwright Aristophanes. It

    portrays an over-the-top (fictitious) school of philosophy, led by a comedic, highly-exaggerated Socrates.

    2. Socrates’ Argued That He Did Not Corrupt the
    Youth

    After explaining why he had been charged (and was being tried), Socrates focused on the new charges:
    denying the gods and corrupting the youth of Athens. After indicating why anyone who cares about ethics
    and wisdom (and oracles) pays homage to the divine, he addressed the charge of corrupting the youth of
    Athens. Socrates raised two arguments against the charge, directing a dialectic against the chief prosecutor,
    Meletus.

    In the course of his arguments with Meletus, Socrates proves that he did not corrupt the youth of Athens.
    Unfortunately, the jury did not agree. We will examine Socrates’ arguments in detail in a subsequent tutorial.

    3. The Unexamined Life Is Not Worth Living

    Socrates failed to persuade the jury, which found him guilty. Meletus asked for a penalty of death; Socrates
    did not suggest an alternative. As a result, he was sentenced to die. However, both before and after his
    sentence was pronounced, Socrates presented compelling reasons why he did not fear death.

    Most importantly, he had done what he thought was right: he had pursued wisdom and taught others to do so;
    he had lived according to the moral principles of his philosophy. Socrates stated that “The difficulty, my
    friends, is not to avoid death, but to avoid unrighteousness; for that runs faster than death.” He maintained
    that a good person does what he or she knows to be right, regardless of personal consequences.

    The possibility that he might be executed should not influence his determination of what he ought to do.
    Socrates believed that he, and everyone, should perform the “godly” pursuit of philosophy, of seeking wisdom
    and right living. This kind of life can only be lived by humans, but without it, we fall short of humanity. As
    Socrates famously said, “the unexamined life is not worth living.”

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 58

    4. Death Is Nothing or Something

    Determined to do what he knew was right, Socrates made a final, deductive, either-or argument to show why
    we should not fear death:

    Death is either nothing or something.
    If it is nothing, it is akin to a long, dreamless sleep (which is nothing to fear).
    If it is something, then it is a transmigration in which one can converse with those who have died (which is
    nothing to fear.)
    Therefore, either way, death is nothing to fear.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Deductive Argument
    A type of argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty

    Some have noted that, in maintaining the third premise, Socrates ignored the possibility of a negative afterlife

    (e.g., hell). However, concepts of eternal damnation were not hypothesized until centuries after his death.

    Additionally (and more importantly), it was then believed that the afterlife would be ruled by true judges, who

    would not fault or punish him for having dedicated his life to the pursuit of wisdom and moral philosophy. If we

    agree with Socrates that everyone should pursue wisdom, the third premise is appropriate.

    In the Apology, Socrates defends himself from the charges that have been made against him and, in

    so doing, defends philosophy. In pursuing truth — a pursuit that led to the discovery of Socratic

    Wisdom — he made enemies of the sophists, who condemned him. He refuted the charge of

    “corrupting the youth” with two good arguments but was sentenced to death. However, the sentence

    did not upset Socrates, because he knew that he had lived rightly.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Excerpt from “The Apology” | Author: By Plato, retrieved from Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain


    Deductive Argument
    A type of argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 59

    https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1656/1656-h/1656-h.htm

    The Apology — Socrates’ Arguments
    by Sophia Tutorial

    This tutorial provides a review of the key points of The Apology, and demonstrates how to extract

    arguments from it.

    This review and consideration of the arguments in the Apology is provided in two parts:

    1. Review of The Apology

    2. Extracting Arguments from The Apology

    a. Inductive Argument

    b. Deductive Argument

    c. Deductive Either-Or Argument

    1. Review of The Apology

    Recall that The Apology is a transcript (recorded by Plato) of Socrates’ trial. In it, Socrates presents his
    defense. He had been charged with denying the gods and, more seriously, corrupting the youth of Athens.

    As Socrates indicates, the real charges against him were unpopularity and making powerful enemies. Since it
    was his practice of philosophy that led to the charges, he needed to prove that his search for truth, and his
    attempts to lead others to it, were good and worthwhile occupations. He had to prove that he did not corrupt
    the youth and to let his accusers know that he did not fear death.

    The Apology begins after the prosecution has presented its case. Socrates began his defense by making a
    distinction between the “old charges” and the “new charges.” By “new charges,” he meant the official charges:
    denying the gods and corrupting the youth of Athens. The “old charges” were, collectively, his reputation.

    2. Extracting Arguments from The Apology

    In addressing the “new charges,” particularly the charge that he had corrupted the youth of Athens, Socrates
    (using his dialectic method), argued with the chief prosecutor, Meletus. In their exchange, Socrates makes two
    arguments: one inductive, one deductive.

     TERMS TO KNOW
    Inductive
    An argument in which the inferential claim is of less than logical certainty
    Deductive
    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 60

    An argument in which the inferential claim is of logical certainty

    Review the following text and see if you can reconstruct Socrates’ arguments before evaluating

    them.

    2a. Inductive Argument

    In the first (inductive) argument, Socrates led Meletus to state his claim precisely:

    Socrates: Then every Athenian improves and elevates them; all with the exception of myself; and I

    alone am their corrupter? Is that what you affirm?

    Meletus: That is what I stoutly affirm.

    This passage indicates the direction Socrates’ argument would take. Meletus’s assertion was that everyone
    else improved the youth; only Socrates corrupted them. Socrates next showed that this assertion was bizarre:

    But suppose I ask you a question: How about horses? Does one man do them harm and all the world

    good? Is not the exact opposite the truth? One man is able to do them good, or at least not many —

    the trainer of horses, that is to say, does them good, and others who have to do with them rather

    injure them?…Happy indeed would be the condition of youth if they had one corrupter only, and all

    the rest of the world were their improvers. But you, Meletus, have sufficiently shown that you never

    had a thought about the young: your carelessness is seen in your not caring about the very things

    which you bring against me.

    Extraction of premises and a conclusion from the preceding text produces the following:

    1. If Meletus is correct, everyone else improves the youth. Only Socrates corrupts them

    2. With horses, the opposite situation is in effect (i.e., one person, or very few people, improve them; most

    do nothing to improve them)

    Combining (1) and (2) yields the following:

    3. It is easier to raise a good human than a good horse (a ridiculous conclusion).

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 61

    The statement that it is much easier to raise a good human than a good horse is clearly false. As a result, we
    must reject Meletus’ original assertion.

    Socrates’ argument is inductive because it is based on cause-and-effect relationships. The conclusion
    resulting from Meletus’ premise is logically sound. Absurd conclusions are improbable; they should not be
    believed unless overwhelming evidence compels us to do so. No youth (or their parents) accused Socrates.
    Therefore, there is no evidence to support the absurd conclusion (much less “overwhelming” evidence). We
    must reject the premise which led to it.

    2b. Deductive Argument

    Socrates next made a deductive argument:

    Socrates: And when you accuse me of corrupting and deteriorating the youth, do you allege that I

    corrupt them intentionally or unintentionally?

    Meletus: Intentionally, I say.

    Socrates: But you have just admitted that the good do their neighbours good, and the evil do them

    evil. Now, is that a truth which your superior wisdom has recognized thus early in life, and am I, at my

    age, in such darkness and ignorance as not to know that if a man with whom I have to live is

    corrupted by me, I am very likely to be harmed by him; and yet I corrupt him, and intentionally,

    too….But either I do not corrupt them, or I corrupt them unintentionally; and on either view of the

    case you lie. If my offense is unintentional, the law has no cognizance of unintentional offenses: you

    ought to have taken me privately, and warned and admonished me.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 62

    Look for Socrates’ main point in this passage: Corruption of the youth is either intentional or unintentional.
    Socrates must show why either of those options leads to a not guilty verdict.

     TRY IT

    See if you can reconstruct the argument, starting with the premise:

    Corruption is either intentional or unintentional.

     HINT

    There should be two more premises (one related to each option) leading to a conclusion

    The argument may be reconstructed as follows:

    This leads to a not guilty verdict either way. Note that these three premises deductively entail this conclusion
    and Meletus has granted all three of them. This means that he has also granted the conclusion. Unfortunately
    for Socrates, the jury did not agree.

    The jury was not persuaded by Socrates’ arguments and found him guilty. Meletus asked for a penalty of
    death; Socrates did not suggest a viable alternative. As a result, he was sentenced to death.

    Before and after his sentence was pronounced, Socrates presented the reasons why he did not fear death.
    Most importantly, he had done what he thought was right: he had pursued wisdom and taught others to do so,
    and he had lived according to the principles of his moral philosophy.

    Socrates stated, “The difficulty, my friends, is not to avoid death, but to avoid unrighteousness; for that runs
    faster than death.” He indicated that good people do what they know is right, regardless of negative personal
    consequences. Even the risk of execution should not influence what good people ought to do.

    Socrates maintained that all people are obligated to perform the “godly” pursuit of philosophy, of seeking
    wisdom and practicing right living. These activities are peculiar to humans. Without them, we fall short of our
    humanity. As Socrates famously stated, “the unexamined life is not worth living.”

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 63

    2c. Deductive Either-Or Argument

    As a final statement indicating his determination to do what he knows is right, Socrates made another
    deductive, either-or argument about why we should not fear death.

    [T]here is great reason to hope that death is a good; for one of two things — either death is a state of

    nothingness and utter unconsciousness, or, as men say, there is a change and migration of the soul

    from this world to another. Now if you suppose that there is no consciousness, but a sleep like the

    sleep of him who is undisturbed even by dreams, death will be an unspeakable gain….Now if death

    be of such a nature, I say that to die is gain; for eternity is then only a single night. But if death is the

    journey to another place, and there, as men say, all the dead abide, what good, O my friends and

    judges, can be greater than this? If indeed when the pilgrim arrives in the world below, he is

    delivered from the professors of justice in this world, and finds the true judges who are said to give

    judgment there….What would not a man give if he might converse with Orpheus and Musaeus and

    Hesiod and Homer?…Above all, I shall then be able to continue my search into true and false

    knowledge….What would not a man give, O judges, to be able to examine the leader of the great

    Trojan expedition; or Odysseus or Sisyphus, or numberless others, men and women too! What

    infinite delight would there be in conversing with them and asking them questions!

    Like his deductive argument as to why he did not corrupt the youth, this argument is presented in an either-or
    format.

     TRY IT

    Reconstruct Socrates’ argument from the text.

     HINT

    Its structure is very similar to the either-or argument that Socrates made to show that was not guilty of

    corrupting the youth. Find the either-or statement, and show why neither option should be feared.

    The argument can be reconstructed as follows:

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 64

    In maintaining the third premise, Socrates ignored the possibility of a negative afterlife (e.g., hell). However,
    concepts of eternal damnation were not hypothesized until centuries later. Additionally (and more
    importantly), Socrates described an afterworld ruled by true judges, who would not fault or punish him for
    dedicating his life to pursuing wisdom and moral philosophy. If we believed Socrates when he told us that we
    should pursue wisdom, this third premise is appropriate.

    In the Apology, Socrates defended himself against the charges directed at him and, in so doing,

    defended philosophy. While pursuing truth that led to the discovery of Socratic Wisdom, he made

    himself unpopular and enabled the sophists to condemn him. Although he refuted the charge of

    corrupting the youth with two strong arguments, Socrates was sentenced to death. The sentence did

    not upset him, because he knew he had lived rightly.

     ATTRIBUTIONS
    Excerpt from “The Apology” | Author: By Plato, retrieved from Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain

    Deductive
    An argument whose inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty
    Inductive
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 65

    https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1656/1656-h/1656-h.htm

    An argument whose inferential claim is a claim less than logical certainty

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 66

    The Crito: The Duties of the Social Contract
    by Sophia Tutorial

    The Crito continues Plato’s account (begun in the Apology) of Socrates’ trial, conviction and eventual

    death sentence. It takes place in the prison where Socrates awaited execution. Crito, one of Socrates’

    wealthy students, used his influence to provide Socrates with an opportunity to escape. Socrates did

    not immediately seize the opportunity.

    Remember that, as described in the Apology, Socrates was unwilling to compromise his ideals and

    use rhetoric (instead of reason), to present his defense during his trial. His subsequent conviction,

    sentence, and imprisonment did not increase his willingness to compromise them. Socrates stated

    that he would only escape if it was the right thing to do (i.e., the “right thing” in a moral, rather than

    legal, sense).

    Crito tried to convince him to leave with arguments based on popular opinion regarding his (Crito’s)

    efforts (or lack of efforts) to free his friend, and the intrinsic value of human life. Socrates rejects Crito’s

    arguments, and makes a compelling argument of his own: one that may be the first expression of the

    Social Contract in history.

    This tutorial examines Socrates’ view of the duties of the social contract in three parts:

    1. Whose Opinion Counts

    2. The Value of Human Life

    3.

    The Social Contract

    1. Whose Opinion Counts

    In trying to free his friend Socrates, Crito first presented an argumentum ad populum; an appeal to the
    majority. He told Socrates that people would think ill of him (i.e., Crito) if he, with all of his influence, allowed
    his friend Socrates to die. (Note that Crito’s appeal implied that public opinion may have shifted after Socrates
    was convicted and condemned to death.) Crito told Socrates that, “the opinion of the many must be
    regarded.”

    Socrates, as always, begins to formulate his reply by asking the philosophical question: why? Instead of
    immediately accepting the majority view, he referred to a concept that he discussed in the Apology: difficult
    endeavors require expertise. We shouldn’t listen to the majority in complicated situations; we should listen to
    the experts.

     EXAMPLE If you want to know about economics, ask an economist. If you want to know about
    climate change, consult a climate scientist.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 67

    In this case, the question involved a matter of ethics. To gain the knowledge needed to answer it rightly, an
    expert in ethics must be consulted (e.g., a philosopher). Socrates stated,

    “In questions of just and unjust, fair and foul, good and evil, which are the subjects of our present consultation,
    ought we to follow the opinion of the many and to fear them; or the opinion of the one man who has
    understanding?”

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Does ethics require expertise? Would cases involving abortion and capital punishment be best resolved

    by experts — without the input of people who are not experts? Would this provide better results than

    Crito’s call for ethical decisions based on majority vote? As you consider this, remember that Socrates’

    position wasn’t that non-experts can’t say anything about ethical matters, but that their input is opinion,

    while the contribution of experts is knowledge. Socrates pointed out that we must always distinguish times

    when (and situations in which) we possess knowledge, from those when all we can contribute is our

    opinion. Would it be better to begin a debate on abortion with, “I don’t know, so this is only my opinion,

    but….” than with an emotional, inflexible statement? This approach might at least reduce the shouting.

    2. The Value of Human Life

    After failing to convince Socrates to follow the will of the majority, Crito tried a different (and familiar)
    approach. He made an appeal based on the intrinsic value of human life: “Nor can I think that you are at all
    justified, Socrates, in betraying your own life when you might be saved; in acting thus you are playing into the
    hands of your enemies, who are hurrying on your destruction.” He went on to tell Socrates that escaping
    would enable him to accomplish much good. He would be able to continue to teach philosophy and instill
    ethics in his pupils.

    Socrates once again responded in a way that might seem strange to contemporary readers. He asked Crito
    the following questions:

    “…will life be worth having, if that higher part of man be destroyed, which is improved by justice and depraved
    by injustice? Do we suppose that principle, whatever it may be in man, which has to do with justice and
    injustice, to be inferior to the body?”

    Socrates took a position that was commonly-held in ancient Greece: not all life has value. Only the good life
    has value. As a result, it is absurd to put the value of a life above what is right.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Is all life worth saving? Does all life have intrinsic value? Does something beyond our actions (and

    potential actions) add value, or are we only the sum of what we do and might do? Saying that life has

    intrinsic value has important repercussions in discussions regarding moral worth (e.g., discussions about

    capital punishment). For example, was the state of New York wrong to execute Albert Fish, one of the

    evilest serial killers of all time? If human beings have intrinsic worth, what gives them that worth? Your

    answer to this question will inform your view on euthanasia and other topics. What is the “right” solution

    when someone who is suffering, and can only look forward to more suffering, wants to die? What about a

    coma patient who will never regain consciousness? What about someone who severely mentally

    disabled?

    If Socrates was correct in believing that only the good life is worth saving, and escaping from prison was in

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 68

    opposition to the principles of the good life he’d tried to live, then escaping from prison would make his life
    one that was not worth living. This returns us to the original topic: it must first be determined whether escape
    is the right thing to do before proceeding.

    3. The Social Contract

    The last argument Socrates made in the Crito is the most important: He imagines a dialogue between himself
    and Athens, personified as the Laws, which ask him the following:

    “‘And was that our agreement with you?… What complaint have you to make against us which justifies you in
    attempting to destroy us and the state? In the first place did we not bring you into existence? Your father
    married your mother by our aid and begat you…. Or against those of us who after birth regulate the nurture
    and education of children, in which you also were trained? Were not the laws, which have the charge of
    education, right in commanding your father to train you in music and gymnastic?’ Right, I should reply. ‘Well
    then, since you were brought into the world and nurtured and educated by us, can you deny in the first place
    that you are our child and slave, as your fathers were before you?…. Then the laws will say: ‘Consider,
    Socrates, if we are speaking truly that in your present attempt you are going to do us an injury. For, having
    brought you into the world, and nurtured and educated you, and given you and every other citizen a share in
    every good which we had to give, we further proclaim to any Athenian by the liberty which we allow him, that if
    he does not like us when he has become of age and has seen the ways of the city, and made our
    acquaintance, he may go where he pleases and take his goods with him. None of us laws will forbid him or
    interfere with him. Anyone who does not like us and the city, and who wants to emigrate to a colony or to any
    other city, may go where he likes, retaining his property. But he who has experience of the manner in which
    we order justice and administer the state, and still remains, has entered into an implied contract that he will do
    as we command him.”

    Here we have a first approximation of an extremely important concept in political philosophy and justice
    studies, the Social Contract.

     TERM TO KNOW
    The Social Contract

    An implicit agreement between the citizen and the state in which the citizen agrees to follow the law

    in exchange for benefits provided by the state

    Based on the Social Contract, Socrates did not believe he should escape. Why?

     TRY IT

    Try to construct a Socratic argument, the conclusion of which is that Socrates should not escape, and the

    premises of which involve a social contract.

    Consider that, of every entity on earth, your government is the only one that can legitimately (i.e., without
    doing anything wrong) take away your rights. It can (and does) claim some of your wealth, and can, in certain
    circumstances, limit your freedom and take your life. Few people believe that the government does wrong
    when it penalizes criminals and collects taxes, but where does the government’s authority come from? A
    thousand years ago, someone may have claimed that a god gave a king his authority. Today, the answer is
    almost always the Social Contract, which is viewed as the sole basis for legitimate government authority. In
    this respect, Socrates’ conclusions regarding his relationship to the laws of Athens were over 2,000 years
    ahead of their time.

    What is the Social Contract? It is an agreement in which one side provides what the other receives. In most

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 69

    cases, the government gives the citizen internal and external protection (by means of police and armed
    forces), education (through public schools and universities), and infrastructure (roads, public utilities, hospitals,
    regulations to ensure breathable air and drinkable water, courts, and more). If you consider everything the
    government provides, you might conclude that the Social Contract is a very good deal for citizens. The
    government asks one thing in return: follow the laws.

    As Socrates indicated, in a democracy, the agreement is even better than the description provided in the last
    paragraph. Citizens can leave the government’s jurisdiction any time they want to do so, taking all of their
    property with them. If a law is unjust in the view of one or more citizens, (i.e., if a citizen — or citizens — does
    not like the current terms of the social contract, they can attempt to change it through a political process).

    However, consider the situation in which Socrates found himself. The state had upheld its obligations. It had
    provided him with protection, education, and infrastructure. In addition, Socrates did not leave the jurisdiction,
    and did not seek to change the laws (including the laws he was found to have broken). The state upheld its
    end of the contract, and Socrates made no effort to get out of, or change, it. As a result, the Social Contract
    was still binding. It would not only be illegal for him to escape, but also immoral. Because the contract was still
    in effect, Socrates must abide by its terms.

    Socrates’ argument as to why he should not try to escape can be reconstructed as follows:

    A contract is binding when the terms are agreed upon and the other party involved has met

    them.
    Premise

    By neither leaving nor seeking to change the laws, Socrates gives consent to the terms of the

    Social Contract with Athens.

    Premise

    Athens upheld its terms of the Social Contract. Premise

    Therefore, Socrates is still bound to his obligations in the Social Contract with Athens. Conclusion

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Should Socrates have left Athens when he had an opportunity to do so? Answer by deciding when a

    Social Contract with the state is binding, and when it is not. Does the contract require anything of the

    government besides protection, infrastructure, and education? What about rights? A reasonable court of

    law? Are you bound to obey a law to which you have strenuously objected and tried to change? What is

    the role of civil disobedience and nonviolent protest with respect to the Social Contract?

    Crito wanted to save Socrates, but could not convince him to save himself at the expense of his moral

    beliefs. Crito’s argument did not convince Socrates that it would not be wrong to escape. When we

    must resolve difficult problems, we rely on experts, not popular opinion. In the Crito, the ethical expert

    (i.e., the philosopher, Socrates) concluded that only the good life — not all life — has value. So if it

    would be wrong to escape, it would not add value to do so. Socrates provided a compelling concept

    to support his position that escape would be wrong: a Social Contract between him and the state.

    Socrates demonstrated that the state had upheld its end of the contract. He believed that he must do

    his part by obeying its laws.

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 70

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Excerpt from “The Crito” | Author: By Plato, retrieved from Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain


    The Social Contract

    An implicit agreement between the citizen and the state in which the citizen agrees to follow the law in

    exchange for all the benefits provided by the state

    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 71

    https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1657/1657-h/1657-h.htm

    The Phaedo: The Death of Socrates

    by Sophia Tutorial

    In the Apology, Socrates is (wrongfully) convicted of denying the gods and corrupting the youth of

    Athens, and is sentenced to death. In the Crito, Socrates is provided with a chance to escape his

    sentence, but chooses not to do so because it would be wrong.

    In the Phaedo, the sentence is carried out. Socrates is executed by imbibing hemlock (i.e., drinking

    poison). Before his demise, however, he taught a large group of his students one last time.

    In the Phaedo, the conversation is about death, although it takes place in a manner that may seem

    backwards. Socrates attempted to console his friends, rather than the other way around. He made a

    more nuanced argument than he did in the Apology regarding why we should not fear death, and

    defined death as the separation of the soul from the body.

    This tutorial investigates the death of Socrates

    in two parts:

    1. A Philosopher Does Not Fear Death

    2. On Souls and Bodies

    1. A Philosopher Does Not Fear Death

    Socrates accepted his death sentence, although he had at least three opportunities to delay it. He considered
    the topic of suicide (which was taboo at that time) philosophically. One of his students asked him, “Why do
    you say…that a man ought not to take his own life, but that the philosopher will be ready to follow the dying?”.
    Socrates responded with a religious answer: Our bodies are not our own. It is up to the gods, not us, to decide
    when and how to end our lives. We don’t have a right to take what belongs to them.

    This raises an interesting (and perennial) question: why don’t the gods take better care of those who are
    under their protection? (Note that, in the Phaedo, the student who asked the question was referring to the
    gods’ protection of Socrates, but the question can also be asked about all of those who serve the gods, e.g.,
    good people.) Since the gods didn’t seem to take good care of good people, why couldn’t Socrates take
    better care of himself by avoiding (or at least delaying) his death?

    Socrates answered by relying on the rationale he developed in the Apology and the Crito: he does what is
    right because it is right and because, following his death, he will be judged by the “true” judges, gods who are
    wise and good. For this reason, a philosopher not only does not fear death (and is willing to die when it is right
    for him to do so), but can even look forward to it.

    2. On Souls and Bodies
    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 72

    Why might a philosopher look forward to death? To answer, it is important to recognize what death is.
    According to Socrates, death is “the separation of soul and body. And to be dead is the completion of this;
    when the soul exists in herself, and is released from the body and the body is released from the soul, what is
    this but death?”

    Socrates challenged his students to consider what a philosopher cares about. He or she is not concerned with
    sensory pleasure. Instead, the philosopher “is entirely concerned with the soul and not with the body.” This
    establishes that a philosopher doesn’t lose anything by resigning his or her body and entering a state of pure
    soul.

    But why think that it is an advantage to do so? Why think that a philosopher improves his or her position by
    doing so? Socrates answered these questions in the following dialectic with the student:

    “What again shall we say of the actual acquirement of knowledge? — is the body, if invited to share in the
    enquiry, a hinderer or a helper? I mean to say, have sight and hearing any truth in them? Are they not, as the
    poets are always telling us, inaccurate witnesses? and yet, if even they are inaccurate and indistinct, what is to
    be said of the other senses? — for you will allow that they are the best of them?

    Certainly, he replied.

    Then when does the soul attain truth? — for in attempting to consider anything in company with the body she
    is obviously deceived.

    True.

    Then must not true existence be revealed to her in thought, if at all?

    Yes.

    And thought is best when the mind is gathered into herself and none of these things trouble her — neither
    sounds nor sights nor pain nor any pleasure, — when she takes leave of the body, and has as little as possible
    to do with it, when she has no bodily sense or desire, but is aspiring after true being?

    Certainly.

    And in this the philosopher dishonours the body; his soul runs away from his body and desires to be alone and
    by herself?

    That is true.

    Well, but there is another thing, Simmias: Is there or is there not an absolute justice?

    Assuredly there is.

    And an absolute beauty and absolute good?

    Of course.

    But did you ever behold any of them with your eyes?

    Certainly not.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 73

    Or did you ever reach them with any other bodily sense? — and I speak not of these alone, but of absolute
    greatness, and health, and strength, and of the essence or true nature of everything. Has the reality of them
    ever been perceived by you through the bodily organs? Or rather, is not the nearest approach to the
    knowledge of their several natures made by him who so orders his intellectual vision as to have the most
    exact conception of the essence of each thing which he considers?

    Certainly.

    And he attains to the purest knowledge of them who goes to each with the mind alone, not introducing or
    intruding in the act of thought sight or any other sense together with reason, but with the very light of the
    mind in her own clearness searches into the very truth of each; he who has got rid, as far as he can, of eyes
    and ears and, so to speak, of the whole body, these being in his opinion distracting elements which when
    they infect the soul hinder her from acquiring truth and knowledge….”

    What Socrates alluded to in the preceding excerpt from the Phaedo is of deep and abiding interest to
    philosophers: the notion of an essence. An essence is what makes a thing what it is.

     EXAMPLE The essence of humanity is what makes humans human. The essence of justice is what
    makes just acts just.

    This is what Socrates meant when he mentioned “absolute justice.” This is the philosopher’s genuine interest.
    We know when an act is obviously just, and we know when an act is obviously unjust. However, to make true
    judgments in difficult cases (i.e., cases in which it is not obvious), we must know justice as it truly is. We must
    know the essence of justice independent of any particular act or just person.

    In this endeavor, the empirical world may sometimes get in the way. We cannot access humanity in general,
    only individual humans. Socrates maintained that, without these individual cases clouding our vision, we might
    get a clear view of humanity in its pure form, justice in its absolute form, etc. This is a topic about which
    Socrates’ student, Plato, had much to say, as we will see in subsequent tutorials. In death, Socrates believed,
    the questions in which he was most interested would be answered. Having gained this insight, he drank the
    hemlock with equanimity, and took the next step in his philosophical journey: death.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 74

    This painting, titled The Death of Socrates was painted by Jacques-Louis David in 1787. It depicts Socrates, as he

    accepts the poison hemlock his sentence for being convicted as guilty for denying the gods and corrupting the

    youth of Athens. Rather than trying to escape his fate, he uses it as a final lesson to his pupils. The medium for the

    painting was oil on canvas and can be found in the Metropolitan Museum of Art in New York, NY.

    In the Phaedo, Socrates instructed his pupils regarding death. Although human beings have no right

    to end their own lives (because our lives are the property of the gods), the philosopher does not fear

    death. He or she is not afraid to do what is right and, therefore, has nothing to fear from the “true”

    judges he or she will face in the afterlife. Death is a separation of the soul and body, but the

    philosopher’s primary interest is to cultivate the former. Without a body to impede the soul’s progress,

    we may see things as they truly are.

     ATTRIBUTIONS
    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 75

    Excerpt from “The Phaedo” | Author: By Plato, retrieved from Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain

    Image of “The Death of Socrates” | License: Public Domain

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 76

    https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1658/1658-h/1658-h.htm

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Trial_of_Socrates#/media/File:He_drank_the_contents_as_though_it_were_a_draught_of_Wine

    Plato: An academic approach to concepts
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Plato was the most famous student of Socrates. Like his mentor, he was interested in clear and distinct

    concepts: they were the cornerstone of his approach to philosophy. After a brief introduction to

    Plato’s philosophy, we will explore the basics of conceptual analysis and its application in one of

    Plato’s best-known works.

    This tutorial examines Plato’s academic approach to concepts in three parts:

    1. An Introduction to Plato

    2. Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

    a. Defining Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

    b. Determining Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

    c. Practice

    3. The Euthyphro

    1. An Introduction to Plato

    Plato, born circa 427 B.C.E., was Socrates’ pupil until Socrates’ was executed in 399 B.C.E. During their time
    together, Plato recorded dialogues between Socrates and various Athenians. It is as a result of these written
    records that we know the philosophy of Socrates.

    After Socrates’ death, Plato wrote his own philosophical works, using the dialogue format that had been
    employed by his teacher. To honor Socrates (and to present his ideas in an unbiased way), Plato’s fictional
    dialogues involved Socrates, usually as the one pronouncing Plato’s philosophical views. As a result, Plato’s
    early dialogues include historical conversations of Socrates. In his mature work, however, Plato used fictitious
    Socratic dialogues to develop and defend his philosophy.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 77

    Roman copy of a portrait bust of Plato by Silanion for the Academia in Athens (c. 370 BC)

    Plato founded a school of philosophy called the Academy.

     DID YOU KNOW

    Plato (which means “broad” in ancient Greek) was a nickname. His birth name was Aristocles. Plato

    founded the Academy in Athens, which was one of the first institutions of higher learning in the western

    world.

    Although the Academy played a major role in the development of western philosophy, it is important to realize
    that much of what Plato wrote was intended to educate his students (i.e., they were philosophical texts to be
    read and discussed at the Academy). His books, including the Euthyphro, were teaching tools, used to impart

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 78

    important lessons.

    The Euthyphro enables us to begin to realize the importance of clear and accurate concepts, and how we can
    identify them. In the Dialogue, Plato describes how Socrates engaged Euthyphro, an Athenian who charged
    his father with murder in a case that was far from black and white. Socrates was interested in what he could
    learn from this case regarding the essence of piety, or godliness.

     TERM TO KNOW

    Essence

    What makes a thing what it is

    An essence is a concept of metaphysics, not of language. An essence is more than a definition. For example,
    the essence of humanity is what makes a human, human. Whether or not an essence can be captured in
    words is irrelevant to the fact that every human must possess the human essence in order to be human. Plato
    was interested in essences, and they play an important role in philosophy. However, not every philosopher
    agrees that essences exist. Those who believe they do, sometimes disagree on the details. This was true of
    Plato and Aristotle, as will be discussed in other tutorials.

    Why are essences so important to philosophy? Essences are not definitions because they are unchanging,
    even when language changes. That which makes a human a human will always do so. It is irrelevant whether
    “human” has been defined in different ways at different times. Essences are the grounds for truth and falsity.
    If I ask, “Why are Bob and Sheila humans?” I am seeking an answer that is deeper than a dictionary definition.
    Any claim that “Bob and Sheila are humans” is true will involve a human essence in some way. The same is
    true if we replace “human” with important philosophical concepts including “justice” and “goodness.”

    In order to identify and make use of essences, it is essential to use clear, accurate terms. To identify the
    essence of justice, we must make accurate claims of the form, x is just or y is unjust. We do not need to know
    much about philosophy to know that grading student work based on hair color is unjust, or that assigning
    grades based on merit is just. We don’t need philosophical analysis in the easy cases. But what about the gray
    areas? Is it just to give an oral exam — one that is ordinarily given as a written test — to accommodate one
    student’s disability? If we can accurately identify the essence of justice, we can eliminate gray areas and
    provide the correct answer. Essences are crucial to philosophy because they enable us to clarify gray areas
    and discover the truth.

     EXAMPLE Essences can help us to discover the truth in gray areas including the morality of
    abortion, capital punishment, and wealth inequality.

    2. Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

    2a. Defining Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

    How can we identify essences? Examination of natural categories of how things are in nature is a good way to

    begin. For example, what is the relationship between dogs and mammals? This is not a relationship between

    words or statements, but between real things. When considering realities, there are two basic ways in which

    categories can be related.

    The first is a sufficient condition:

     TERM TO KNOW

    Sufficient Condition

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 79

    A is a Sufficient Condition for B, if membership in A logically guarantees membership in B

    Note that a sufficient condition is a relation, like saying “taller than.” It always applies to two things, not one.
    Since this is so, think of a sufficient condition as a logical guarantee. For example, getting caught stealing is a
    guarantee that you were breaking the law. Therefore, getting caught stealing is a sufficient condition for
    breaking the law.

    What other types of things are logical guarantees? Recall the previous example of dogs and mammals. Being
    a dog is a sufficient condition for being a mammal. In general, any subclass is a sufficient condition. Being a
    square is a sufficient condition for being a quadrilateral, etc. Other examples involve a special type of
    subclass. Being Sacramento is sufficient for being a state capital. Being Socrates is a sufficient condition for
    being a philosopher. Being Socrates guarantees membership into the class of philosophers.

    The other type of basic relation that may occur in the world is a necessary condition.

     TERM TO KNOW

    Necessary Condition

    X is a Necessary Condition for Y if membership in X is logically required for membership in Y

    Think of a necessary condition as a logical requirement. Completing your coursework is a necessary condition
    for receiving your degree. What kinds of things are logical requirements? First, a supertype is a rarely-used
    word that means the opposite of a subtype or subclass. Being an animal is a necessary

    condition for being a

    starfish. Another type of necessary condition is the “part of” relation. This can be a physical part (e.g., having a
    spine is a necessary condition for being a human), or a conceptual component (e.g., fairness is a

    necessary

    condition for justice).

    2b. Determining Necessary and Sufficient Conditions

    If this is confusing, there is a simple procedure for determining whether either of these relations exists

    between two things:

     STEP BY STEP

    Step 1: Set up the question as follows:

    (1) is a (blank) condition for (2), where (1) and (2) are the two objects, concepts, etc. that you are relating.

    Step 2: Ask two simple questions:

    Question 1: “Are all cases of (1) also cases of (2)?”

    If you answer yes, then (1) is sufficient for (2).

    If you answer no, then (1) is not sufficient for (2).

     HINT

    Note that this first question only determines sufficiency. To determine necessity, change the order.

    Question 2: “Are all cases of (2) cases of (1)?”

    If you answer yes, then (1) is necessary for (2).

    If you answer no, then (1) is not necessary for (2).

    Step 3: Determine conditions. Note that this produces four possible answers relating any two categories:

    (A) Sufficient, not necessary

    (B) Necessary, not

    sufficient

    (C) Both necessary and sufficient

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 80

    (D) Neither necessary nor sufficient

    The whole of reality has just become a multiple choice question, because one of these four possible relations
    must always exist between any two things.

    The following table categorizes the four possibilities based on the answers to the above questions.

    (1) is a (blank) condition for (2).

    Sufficient Condition:

    Are all cases of (1) also cases of (2)?

    Yes No

    Necessary Condition:

    Are all cases of (2)

    also cases of (1)?

    Yes
    Both Sufficient

    and Necessary

    Necessary,

    not Sufficient

    No

    Sufficient,

    not Necessary

    Neither Necessary

    nor Sufficient

    2c. Practice

    Return to the examples of sufficient conditions above, and see how they all come out as option (A), sufficient,

    not necessary.

    Next, try all of the previous examples of necessary conditions and see how they come up as option (B),
    necessary, not sufficient.

    So we have seen some examples of relations that fall into the category of sufficient, not necessary and others
    that are necessary, not sufficient. But what about the last two categories?

    To answer (D) (i.e., neither necessary nor sufficient ) that there is no logical relation between two entities. For
    example, being a pirate is neither necessary nor sufficient for being a ninja. This is an example of no relation
    at all. Note that statistical relationships fall into category (D) as well. For instance, being tall is neither
    necessary nor sufficient for being a professional basketball player. Why? There are tall people who are not
    basketball players, and there are basketball players who are not tall. Being tall is neither a requirement nor a
    guarantee for being a basketball player.

    The most important category in conceptual analysis is (C) (i.e., both necessary and sufficient). What kind of
    things are both necessary and sufficient? Cases of identity fall into this category. Being Socrates is both
    necessary and sufficient for being Plato’s mentor. More important, however, are two things of interest to
    philosophy: good definitions (linguistic) and essences (metaphysical). Being a bachelor is both necessary and
    sufficient for being an unmarried male who has reached the age of consent. Using necessary and sufficient
    conditions is a simple way to begin using conceptual analysis.

     TRY IT

    Try the following six problems:

    Problem Answer Explanation

    Being furniture is a

    (blank) condition for

    being a chair.

    Necessary,
    not
    sufficient

    Being furniture is a necessary, not sufficient condition for being a chair

    because not all cases of furniture are chairs, but all cases of chairs are

    furniture.

    Being a good driver is

    a (blank) condition for

    Neither

    necessary

    Being a good driver is neither necessary nor sufficient for having a

    driver’s license. There are good drivers who do not have a driver’s

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 81

    having a driver’s

    license.

    nor

    sufficient

    license and there are plenty of people with a driver’s license who are

    not good drivers.

    Being a regular

    quadrilateral is a

    (blank) condition for

    being a square.

    Both

    necessary
    and
    sufficient

    Being a regular quadrilateral is both sufficient and necessary for being a

    square. This is a case of identity. When you do the test, one is trivially all

    so you answer yes, yes.

    Having a heart is a

    (blank) condition for

    being a human.

    Necessary,
    not
    sufficient

    Having a heart is a necessary, not sufficient condition for being a human

    because not all cases of having a heart are being a human, but all cases

    of being a human are having a heart.

    Eating Thanksgiving

    dinner is a (blank)

    condition for being

    full.

    Sufficient,
    not
    necessary

    Eating Thanksgiving dinner is sufficient, not necessary for being full

    because if you eat Thanksgiving dinner, you will be full. However, you

    just being full doesn’t guarantee that you ate Thanksgiving dinner.

    Being enrolled in this

    course is a (blank)

    condition for being a

    student.

    Sufficient,
    not
    necessary

    Being enrolled in this course is sufficient, not necessary for being a

    student because your enrollment guarantees you are a student, but

    being a student doesn’t necessarily mean you are enrolled in this

    course.
    3. The Euthyphro

    Though the terminology used for these categories did not exist during Plato’s time, Plato taught his students
    many of these concepts (and a few more) in the Euthyphro. In that dialogue, Socrates asked what is the
    essence of piety (i.e., holiness or goodness). He therefore asked Euthyphro for the necessary and sufficient
    conditions for piety. In the dialogue, Euthyphro presented six unsatisfactory definitions. Plato’s students
    learned the fundamentals of conceptual analysis from Socrates’ rejection of the unsatisfactory answers. We
    will examine some of them briefly.

    The first definition Euthyphro proposed is that piety is to do what he was doing, that is prosecuting the
    wrongdoer.

    Socrates quickly pointed out that this was merely an example, or to use our terminology, sufficient, but not
    necessary. There are other ways of being pious, so an example, while helpful, does not grasp the essence of
    piety. (Imagine that someone asked you what it meant to be human and, in response, you pointed at a
    passerby.)

    Euthyphro next stated that piety is what is loved by the gods. Socrates replied that this wouldn’t do, because
    the gods disagree (which probably makes it neither necessary nor sufficient). What is loved by Aphrodite,
    goddess of love, is different from what is loved by Ares, god of war. The important lesson is that, when
    dealing with concepts, say what you mean (i.e., say what you are willing and able to defend), nothing more,
    nothing less.

     EXAMPLE Consider this claim: “Abortion is wrong.” Does this mean all abortions are wrong? What
    about cases of rape? What about cases in which continuing the pregnancy will kill the mother? Surely it

    was not intended to include cases in which continuing the pregnancy will kill the mother and the fetus.

    Only claim what you are willing to support.

    The third definition, therefore, is that piety is what is loved by all of the gods. Things which satisfy these

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 82

    conditions may exist, (the Greek virtues of courage, wisdom, justice, and moderation, for example), but there
    is a problem, which has come to be known as the Euthyphro Dilemma: Is a thing pious because the gods love
    it, or do the gods love it because it is pious? The former makes piety arbitrary and uninteresting. The latter
    means we must look beyond the gods to isolate the concept.

    This is what Euthyphro tries to accomplish in presenting his fourth definition: piety is part of justice, and all that
    is pious is just. Once more, however, the “part of” relation is incomplete (recall that “part of” is necessary, not
    sufficient). In this instance, Euthyphro tried to define a tricky concept by introducing a trickier concept, which is
    unhelpful.

    Euthyphro moved on to another religious definition of piety: piety is doing what is required by the gods or care
    of the gods. This is vague. Care how? We have not adequately defined the concept.

    Euthyphro clarifies this in his sixth (and final) definition: piety is service to the gods. This is also vague. Even
    worse, we can remove the vagueness. We serve the gods by doing what they wish, but this is the same as
    saying “doing what pleases them.” Euthyphro has simply restated his third definition.

    The results of the dialogue were not all failures, however; Socrates provided a positive notion of what the
    essence of piety may be (i.e., the virtue of living in a way that fulfills one’s duties to humanity, and to the gods).
    What is important to realize is how to approach precise philosophical concepts, while avoiding standard
    pitfalls, and why precision matters.

    Philosophy is a pursuit of truth, but this means we need to identify the truth-makers of categories —

    essences. A good way to do this is to learn necessary and sufficient conditions: logical guarantees

    and requirements that relate categories of being. In Plato’s Euthyphro, he taught his students in this

    way, using the concept of piety. By doing so he emphasized the importance of precise concepts.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Bust of Plato | License: Public Domain


    Essence
    What makes a thing what it is
    Necessary Condition

    “X” is a Necessary Condition for “Y” if membership in “X” is logically required for

    membership in “Y.”

    Sufficient Condition

    “A” is a Sufficient Condition for “B” if membership in “A” logically guarantees membership in

    “B.”

    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 83

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Plato

    Plato’s Forms: The Objects of Knowledge
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Plato was interested in concepts — not just the terminology used to refer to them, but metaphysically.

    He wanted to know how they exist in reality, their essences. Plato’s notion of essences was

    connected to his epistemology, and is how knowledge becomes possible. Before discussing the

    connection between essences and knowledge, we need to examine knowledge.

    This tutorial considers forms, the objects of knowledge, in two parts:

    1. The Platonic Conception of Knowledge

    2. Plato’s Forms as the Grounds of Knowledge

    1. The Platonic Conception of Knowledge

    In a dialogue called the Theaetetus, Plato provided perhaps the first, and certainly the most influential,
    account of knowledge in western philosophy. In it, he asserted that knowledge consists of three components.

    What kind of thing is knowledge? To answer, let’s consider an example. We know that the Titanic was over
    100 feet long. However, this knowledge is something that exists in our minds, not in the world. It must be true,
    because we know that the Titanic was over 100 feet long, but not everyone knows this. There are people who
    don’t know what the Titanic was. There are many people who don’t know the English measuring system, and
    don’t know what 100 feet is. However, since the Titanic was over 100 feet long independent of whether a
    person or persons know it or not, then knowledge must be distinct from the object itself. Knowledge is in our
    minds as a posture we hold toward the statement, “The Titanic was over 100 feet long.” Knowledge is a type
    of belief. This was Plato’s first component of knowledge (“belief” is the term used now, but Socrates and Plato
    sometimes used “opinion” instead).

    However, people have believed lots of things. 1,000 years ago, people believed that the sun revolved around
    the earth. Before that, some believed that the earth was flat. Children believe that Santa Claus exists.
    Believers, however, don’t know these things. They can’t know them. They may think that they know them, but
    they are wrong in thinking so. You cannot know that which is false. Therefore, Plato’s second component of
    knowledge is truth. Knowledge must be a true belief (or true opinion).

    However, this definition of knowledge is still insufficient. For example, suppose you are at a party chatting with
    a stranger who makes a request. He puts his hands behind his back and asks you to guess (i.e., to form a
    belief about) how many fingers he is holding up. Arbitrarily, you guess two. He takes his hand from behind his
    back and shows you that he is holding up two fingers. In this case, you had a true belief, but you didn’t know
    that he was holding up two fingers. Therefore, having a true belief falls short of knowledge. Something is
    missing.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 84

     BRAINSTORM

    Think about the situation just described. Can you imagine a few alterations in the scenario that would

    enable you to say that you knew how many fingers he was holding up behind his back?
    There are many things we can imagine that might provide us with knowledge. Imagine if the stranger had
    been standing by a bar, above which hung a large mirror, enabling you to view a reflection of his hand behind
    his back. Or imagine that you have seen him ask the same question of everyone else at the party and noticed
    that he always holds up two fingers. Or perhaps your friend is standing behind him and signals you that he is
    holding up two. What do all of these possibilities have in common? They all provide good reasons to believe
    that he is holding up two fingers.

     BRAINSTORM

    Think about the situation just described. Can you imagine reasons that you might guess two, that are bad

    reasons?

    Imagine that you threw a dart at a dartboard and it stuck in the “two” area of the board. You used the dart’s
    landing location as your answer to the stranger when he asked how many fingers he was holding up. This is a
    reason to answer “two,” but is it a good reason? No, it is not. Does the fact that the dart landed on two enable
    you to claim that you knew he was holding up two fingers? No.

    Note what these two examples teach us. When we have good reasons for our true belief, we say we know it.
    When we have bad reasons, we don’t (we can’t) say we know it, even if it happens to be true.

    Plato’s third component of knowledge is called justification. This term indicates situations in which we have
    good reasons for our belief. (Note that, when talking about knowledge, justification always applies to beliefs,
    not actions.) What makes a reason “good” is one of the main focuses of the field of epistemology.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Epistemology

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge, and the methodologies

    by which it is attained

    Plato’s Components of Knowledge
    Knowledge is a type of belief
    Knowledge must be a true belief
    Knowledge is a justified true belief

     BIG IDEA

    Plato defined knowledge as justified true belief. This definition (at least as an approximation) is still used

    and defended 2,400 years later.

    2. Plato’s Forms as the Grounds of Knowledge

    How can we justify a belief? Consider the justifications included in the examples above: seeing the mirror,
    being signaled by a friend, watching for patterns, etc. In broad terms, what they all have in common is that
    they are grounded in the world. Justification is tied to seeing the world as it is, properly relating a belief to the
    world as it exists. When you properly connect a belief to the world as it is, that belief is justified.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 85

    Therefore, in order to justify a belief, one must access the world as it really is. For Plato, this meant knowing
    the essence of things. In order to say, “I know Jen is a human,” the speaker must know what a human truly is
    (i.e., what makes a human, human: its essence). This is true of essences generally, but Plato developed a
    nuanced and influential view of essences. It is called Plato’s doctrine of the Forms or Ideas, or the Platonic
    Forms (initial capitalization is used when referring to this concept).

    In Plato’s view, essences are real entities. A real thing that is the essence of goodness, called the Form of
    Goodness, exists. The same is true of Justice, Humanity, and other important essences. These essences exist
    not in the world, but in an intellectual realm sometimes called Platonic Heaven (because it is analogous to the
    Christian heaven in many ways, including its lack of a physical location). Everything that is good is good
    because it is related to this essence, the Form of Goodness.

    It may seem strange to think that there is a Form of Goodness that is everywhere/nowhere in Platonic Heaven.
    But let’s consider something more familiar. Do you believe in the law of gravity? If so, where is it?
    Everywhere? Nowhere? Platonic Heaven? All we know is that, when something is dropped, we expect it to fall.
    It always has, always does, always will.

    Belief in the law of gravity is a standard, everyday belief. But if you replace “law of gravity” with “Form of
    Justice,” you may begin to realize that, just as there is something that makes dropped objects fall, there is
    something that makes a just act just. This “something” is the Platonic Form.

    If there are such entities, they will play an important role in our theory of knowledge. Return to the law of
    gravity analogy. If we can accurately describe the law of gravity, then we can also know the way an object
    behaves when it is dropped. If we know the law of gravity, then our belief about what will happen when an
    object is dropped is justified. Similarly, if we can describe the Form of Justice accurately, then we can be
    justified in beliefs that particular acts, policies, or governments are just or unjust. If we know the Form of
    Humanity, then we can be justified in believing that someone is or is not human (and what makes a good
    human.)

    Since Platonic Forms are the metaphysical grounding of reality, knowledge of reality is grounded in
    knowledge of the Forms. The Forms are the entities through which all knowledge comes. If we can access
    them and know their true nature, then we are justified in any beliefs to which they apply.

    Plato’s epistemology was, and continues to be, significant and influential. He identified the crucial

    components of knowledge: to have knowledge is to have a justified true belief. However, justification

    involves properly relating a belief to the world. For Plato, this meant relating it to his metaphysical

    notion of essences, the Forms. To have an accurate grasp of one of these metaphysically-real

    essences is to be able to justify beliefs to which it applies.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Image of Plato | License: Public Domain

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 86

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Plato#/media/File:Platon


    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies
    that attain it
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 87

    Plato Forms: The Foundations of Being
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Central to all of Plato’s philosophy is his Doctrine of the Forms (or, sometimes, Ideas — note the

    capital letters). Forms are the basis of both his metaphysics and his epistemology: they are the

    grounds for all truth. If I say that “Bruiser is a dog” is true, it is because there are truths about what

    makes a dog a dog. This tutorial begins by providing an overview of Plato’s theory, before we

    consider why we should believe that there are such truths, the roles they fulfill, and how they interact

    with the world.

    The tutorial examines forms as the foundations of being in Plato’s philosophy, in three parts:

    1. A Beginning Approximation

    2. Forms as the Grounds for Reality

    3. Participation and Particulars

    1. A Beginning Approximation

    Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms is central to his epistemology and metaphysics, because they ground both
    knowledge and being. Recall that Plato considers essences as real entities. A real thing that is the essence of
    goodness, and is called the Form of Goodness, exists. The same is true of justice, humanity, and other
    important essences. These things exist in an intellectual realm sometimes referred to as Platonic Heaven
    (because it is analogous in many ways to the Christian heaven — e.g., it has no physical location.) Everything
    that is good is good because it has some relation to the Form of Goodness.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Metaphysics
    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality
    It may seem strange to think that there is a Form of Goodness that is everywhere/nowhere in Platonic Heaven.
    But let’s consider something more familiar. Do you believe in the law of gravity? If so, where is it?
    Everywhere? Nowhere? Platonic Heaven? All we know is that, when something is dropped, we expect it to fall.
    It always has, always does, always will.
    Belief in the law of gravity is a standard, everyday belief. But if you replace “law of gravity” with “Form of
    Justice,” you may begin to realize that, just as there is something that makes dropped objects fall, there is
    something that makes a just act just. This “something” is the Platonic Form.

    Perhaps an even clearer example is provided by numbers and mathematical entities.

     THINK ABOUT IT
    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 88

    Have you ever considered what is a number? It isn’t a physical thing, but we know it exists in some way.

    But where and how does it exist?

    What makes the truths of mathematics true? Considering all of the things that have been accomplished with
    applied mathematics, it would be strange to claim that “the fact that two plus two is four is true because
    concepts such as ‘two’ and ‘four’ are human inventions. They are completely dependent on the human mind,
    human language and how we have chosen to designate things.”

    Instead, most of us believe that the laws of mathematics were true even before humans existed, that the
    number two is a genuine entity of some sort that has an independent reality, perhaps as a Platonic Form.
    (Note that many mathematicians identify themselves as Platonists with respect to numbers, and make this
    claim about numbers.) It can be helpful to consider mathematics in this way when attempting to understand
    Forms and Platonic Heaven. Plato developed a theory of mathematical Forms later in his life.

    2. Forms as the Grounds for Reality

    Why believe that there entities? Plato proposed that they must exist in order for knowledge to be possible. In
    the Cratylus, he argued as follows:

    “Nor can we reasonably say, Cratylus, that there is knowledge at all, if everything is in a state of transition and
    there is nothing abiding; for knowledge too cannot continue to be knowledge unless continuing always to
    abide and exist. But if the very nature of knowledge changes, at the time when the change occurs there will
    be no knowledge; and if the transition is always going on, there will always be no knowledge, and, according
    to this view, there will be no one to know and nothing to be known: but if that which knows and that which is
    known exists ever, and the beautiful and the good and every other thing also exist, then I do not think that
    they can resemble a process or flux….”

    Plato agreed with Heraclitus that the world we encounter through our senses is in flux (in fact, Plato cited
    Heraclitus when he made this point in the dialogue). However, if this applies to everything, then knowledge is
    not possible. If every human is always changing, and humanity itself is changing, how can claims that “Bob is
    human,” or “Bruiser is not human” be true?

    Since we can attain knowledge, it must be true that not everything is in flux. However, since the world of the
    senses is in flux as Heraclitus described, it follows that what is not in flux cannot be of this world, but must
    belong to a metaphysical world, a world behind the world, a Platonic Heaven of essences. Plato accepted
    Heraclitian Flux, but only in the world of the senses. Platonic Heaven, like the world posited by Parmenides, is
    eternal and unchanging.

    If we were to construct an argument about this, it would be as follows:

    The world of experience is in flux. Premise/Factual Claim

    If everything were in flux, knowledge wouldn’t be possible. Premise/Factual Claim

    Knowledge is possible. Premise/Factual Claim

    Therefore, something outside our experience is not in flux. Conclusion

    As we’ve discussed so far, Forms are essences that exist as individual entities in an intellectual realm. But
    what are Forms like? What kind of things are they? Think of them as perfect objects — as paradigms or ideals.

    The analogous relationship between mathematical objects and Forms can help us to understand what Forms
    are like. Consider a circle. In all of the world, is there a perfect circle? The answer is “no.” If we examined the

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 89

    most precisely-drawn circles with a sufficiently-powerful microscope, we would find that their curves are not
    perfectly smooth. Also, we know that space itself curves slightly so, therefore, no Euclidian shape exists in the
    world (i.e., the world of the senses). There are no perfect circles in the world. However, there is perfection in
    Platonic Heaven. The Form of Circle is perfectly circular, and serves as the exemplar for all worldly circles.

    3. Participation and Particulars

    What then, is the relation between the Form of Circle and worldly, imperfect circles? Plato’s answer is
    “participation.” Worldly circles participate in the Form of Circle just as humans participate in the Form of
    Human. But what does participation mean?

    As indicated above, participation is grounding in truth. “Bob is human” is true, because Bob participates in the
    Form of Human. In this way, Plato’s Forms are similar to other philosophical accounts of essences. Plato,
    however, went beyond those accounts of essences by assigning a cause-and-effect relationship. For
    example, the Form of Human is the cause of Bob, as a human. Bob only exists as a human because of the
    Platonic Form. This relation is also one of imitation. The worldly human imitates the ideal Form of

    Human.

    Key aspects of participation

    include…

    Example

    …a grounding of truth “Bob is human” is true because Bob participates in the Form of

    Human.

    …a cause-and-effect relationship The Form of Human is the cause of Bob, as a human.

    …an exemplar The worldly human imitates the more genuine, more real Form of

    Human.

    These are complex concepts. As a result, they have been involved in many interpretive challenges and
    scholarly disputes. For example, Plato insisted that there are mathematical Forms, ethical Forms (e.g., the
    Forms of Justice and Goodness), and logical and metaphysical Forms (e.g., the Form of Being; the Form of
    Equality). However, some of Plato’s works seem to establish a Form any time there is a universal (e.g., a Form
    of Wheel or Taco), which has some undesirable consequences. There are also logical problems (e.g., Forms
    participating in other Forms).

    This does not mean that Plato’s system is indefensible or broken. However, It is not possible to consider all of
    the details involved in this issue in this introductory course. We must be satisfied with acquiring an
    understanding of the general concepts.

    Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms is central to his epistemology and metaphysics, since Forms ground

    both

    knowledge and being. Forms exist in an intellectual realm that, unlike the world of the senses, is

    eternal and unchanging. There, they serve as both the cause and exemplar of the worldly entities that

    participate in the Forms.

     ATTRIBUTIONS
    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 90

    Excerpt from “The Cratylus” | Author: By Plato, retrieved from Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain


    Metaphysics

    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality.

    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 91

    https://www.gutenberg.org/files/1616/1616-h/1616-h.htm

    Applying Plato’s Metaphysics

    by Sophia Tutorial

    In this tutorial, we’ll review both the central epistemological and metaphysical tenets of Plato’s

    doctrine of the Forms, and consider these ideas in context.

    This tutorial examines the application of Plato’s Metaphysics in four parts:

    1. Review of Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms

    2. Forms as the Grounds of Knowledge

    3. Forms as the Grounds for Reality

    4. Participation and Particulars

    1. Review of Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms

    Central to all of Plato’s philosophy is his Doctrine of the Forms (or Ideas — note the use of capitalization).
    Forms are the basis of his metaphysics and epistemology, because they are the grounds for all truth. Recall
    that Plato was interested in concepts, not only as terminology, but metaphysically. He wanted to understand
    how they exist in reality, their essences.

    Plato’s notion of essences is connected to his epistemology, and is the way in which knowledge becomes
    possible. Recall that, in Plato’s philosophy, knowledge is justified true belief. This definition (or an
    approximation of it) is still used and defended 2,400 years later.

     TERMS TO KNOW
    Metaphysics
    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality
    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge, and the methodologies
    by which it is attained
    2. Forms as the Grounds of Knowledge

    How can we justify a belief? Recall the examples provided in the previous tutorial, which involved guessing
    the number of fingers held up behind someone’s back: seeing the fingers reflected in a mirror, being signaled
    by a friend, observing patterns, etc. What all had in common was that they were somehow grounded in the
    world. Justification is tied to seeing the world as it is, to properly relating a belief to the world as it exists.
    When you properly connect a belief to the world as it is, your belief is justified.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 92

    Therefore, in order to justify a belief, one must access the world as it really is. For Plato, this meant that he
    must know the essence of things. If someone says, “I know that Jen is a human,” that person must know what
    a human is, what makes a human a human: its essence. This is generally true of essences, but Plato held a
    nuanced (and influential) view of essences, his doctrine of the Forms or Ideas (i.e., the Platonic Forms — note
    how capitalization is used when referring to Plato’s concepts).

    In Plato’s philosophy, essences are real entities. A real thing exists that is the essence of goodness: it called
    the Form of Goodness. The same is true of Justice, Humanity, and other important essences. The essences of
    these things do not exist in the world, but in an intellectual realm sometimes called Platonic Heaven (because
    it is, in some ways analogous to the Christian heaven — e.g., it has no physical location). Everything that is
    good is good because it has some relation to this essence, the Form of Goodness.

    It may seem strange that there is a Form of Goodness that is everywhere/nowhere in Platonic Heaven. Let’s
    consider an example that involves something more familiar. Do you believe in the law of gravity? If so, where
    is it? Everywhere? Nowhere? Platonic Heaven? All we know is that, when an object is dropped, it falls. If you
    replace “law of gravity” with “Form of Goodness,” Plato’s concept may begin to seem less strange to you. Just
    as there is something that makes objects fall when we remove support from them (e.g., when we drop them),
    there is something that makes a good act good. This is the Platonic Form.

    If there are such entities as Forms, they must play an important role in our theory of knowledge. Let’s return to
    the law-of-gravity analogy. If we can accurately describe the law of gravity, then we can also know the way an
    object behaves when it is dropped. If we know the law of gravity, then we are justified in our belief about what
    will happen when an object is dropped. Similarly, if we can describe the Form of Justice accurately, we can be
    justified believing that a particular act, policy, or government is just or unjust. If we know the Form of
    Humanity, then we can be justified in a belief as to whether someone is or is not a human being (and what
    makes a good human being.)

    Since Platonic Forms are the metaphysical grounding of reality, knowledge of reality is grounded in
    knowledge of the Forms. They are the entities through which all knowledge comes. If we can access them
    and know their true nature, then we are justified in any belief to which they apply.

    3. Forms as the Grounds for Reality

    Recall that it can be helpful to consider mathematical entities and the realm of mathematics when attempting
    to understand Forms and Platonic Heaven. Plato himself developed a theory of mathematical Forms later in
    his life.

    Why should we believe that there are such entities as Forms? Plato maintained that Forms must exist in order
    for knowledge to be possible. In an important way, Plato agrees with Heraclitus that the world we encounter
    through our senses is constantly in flux. However, if this applied to everything, then knowledge would not be
    possible. If every human being is always changing, and humanity itself is changing, then how can claims that
    “Bob is human,” or “Bruiser is not human” be true?

    Since we can have knowledge, not everything is in constant flux. Since the world of the senses is in flux (as
    Heraclitus indicated), what is not in flux cannot be of this world: it must belong, instead, to a metaphysical
    world, a world behind this world, a Platonic Heaven of essences. Plato adopted Heraclitan Flux, but only with
    respect to the world of the senses. Platonic Heaven, like the world posited by Parmenides, is eternal and
    unchanging.

    As we’ve discussed, Forms are essences that exist as individual entities in an intellectual realm. But what are

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 93

    Forms like? What kind of things are they? Think of them as perfect objects: as ideals, or paradigms. For
    example, consider a circle. In all of the world, is there a perfect circle? The answer is no. Examination of the
    most-accurately drawn circles with a sufficiently-powerful microscope will reveal that their curves are not
    perfectly smooth. Furthermore, we know that space itself curves slightly. As a result, no flawless Euclidian
    shape exists in the world. In the world, there are no perfect circles. But perfection exists in Platonic Heaven.
    The Form of Circle — the essence of Circle — is perfectly circular, serving as an exemplar for circles in the
    world of the senses.

    4. Participation and Particulars

    What is the relationship between the Form of Circle and worldly, imperfect circles? Plato’s answer was
    “participation.” Worldly circles participate in the Form of Circle, just as humans participate in the Form of
    Human. But what is participation? As indicated above, it is a grounding of truth. “Bob is human” is true,
    because Bob participates in the Form of Human. In this way, Plato’s Forms are similar to other philosophical
    accounts of essences. Plato, however, went further by assigning a cause-and-effect relationship. According to
    Plato, the Form of Human is the cause of Bob, as a human. Bob only exists as a human because of the Platonic
    Form. This relationship also involves imitation. The human in the world of the senses imitates the real Form of
    Human.

    Key Aspects of Participation

    include…
    Example
    …a grounding of truth “Bob is human” is true because Bob participates in the Form of
    Human.

    …a cause and effect relationship The Form of Human is the cause of Bob, as a human.

    …an exemplar The worldly human imitates the real Form of Human.

    These are complex concepts and, therefore, there have been (and continue to be) interpretive challenges and
    scholarly disputes. For example, Plato maintained that there are mathematical Forms, ethical Forms (e.g., the
    Forms of Justice and Goodness), and logical and metaphysical Forms (e.g., the Form of Being and the Form of
    Equality). However, some of Plato’s works seem to indicate a Form any time there is a universal (e.g., a Form
    of Wheel or Taco). This can have undesirable consequences. Some logic issues are also involved, such as
    Forms participating in other Forms. This does not mean that Plato’s system is indefensible. It is not possible
    for us to consider all of the details of these disputes in this introductory course. We must be satisfied with
    acquiring a general understanding of these concepts.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Think about the main metaphysical and epistemological tenets of Plato’s doctrine of the Forms. How can

    we apply them to real-world examples? According to Plato, what makes it true that a tree is a tree? Or that

    knowledge is possible? According to Plato, what makes you a human being, and not something else?

    How does being able to answer these questions advance personal knowledge, and knowledge within the

    sciences?

    Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms is central to his epistemology and metaphysics, since they ground both

    knowledge and being. Forms exist in an intellectual realm that, unlike the world of the senses, is
    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 94

    eternal and unchanging. There, they serve as both the cause and exemplars of worldly entities that

    participate in the Forms.

    Epistemology
    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the methodologies
    that attain it
    Metaphysics
    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 95

    The Footnotes to Plato
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Alfred North Whitehead stated that the whole of European philosophical tradition “consists of a series

    of footnotes to Plato.” To explain what he meant, Whitehead said, “I allude to the wealth of general

    ideas scattered through them. His personal endowments, his wide opportunities for experience at a

    great period of civilization, his inheritance of an intellectual tradition not yet stiffened by excessive

    systematization, have made his writing an inexhaustible mine of suggestion.”

    Plato’s philosophy is a mine from which other philosophers, thinkers, religions, and cultures have

    extracted riches over the centuries. In this lecture, we will consider some of Plato’s legacies in

    philosophy, mathematics, and how human endeavors ought to be pursued. This selection of topics is

    not comprehensive, but is sufficient to convey the extent of his influence.

    This tutorial considers the scope of Plato’s intellectual legacy in three parts:

    1. Philosophical Legacy

    2. Platonism in Mathematics

    3. Pursuing Truth Over Appearance

    1. Philosophical Legacy

    Plato left an indelible mark on philosophy. His Doctrine of the Forms was a landmark that connected
    epistemology to the way things are, including essences. He was also (perhaps) the first to provide a
    comprehensive, interconnected and coherent metaphysics, cosmogony, and ontology (i.e., the branch of
    metaphysics that examines the nature of being). His historical legacy includes the foundation of the Academy
    and his instruction of Aristotle. When studying Plato, we don’t only consider his work in terms of its depth, or
    historical accuracy (a practice 20th century philosopher Gilbert Ryle disparagingly called “tombstone
    polishing”). Instead, we rely on Plato when we attempt to understand the metaphysical realities of the world.

    Methodologically, Plato taught the importance of conceptual analysis and how to conduct it. His metaphysical
    accounts are also influential. Every philosopher who develops a notion of essences must begin with Plato.
    Every epistemologist starts with Plato’s account of knowledge. Many theologians have adopted his account of
    the Forms entirely, or have accepted aspects of his intellectual realm and intellectual objects. Some
    theologians have gone so far as to define God as the personified Form of the Good.

    Plato influenced (and continues to influence) many other areas of philosophy, too many to list here.
    Whitehead did not overstate his case. Much of philosophy, and theology, implicitly or explicitly begins with
    Plato. However, his philosophy has also impacted other disciplines.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 96

    2. Platonism in Mathematics

    Recall that Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms is highly compatible with mathematical idealization. This applies to
    geometry (Platonic Forms as the basis of geometric shapes) and arithmetic (numerals as Platonic Forms).

    In higher mathematics, some have posited the existence of sets as Platonic objects. Positing Platonic objects
    enables mathematicians to solve otherwise-unsolvable problems. For example, a Platonist account enables
    the solution of a number of problems including why mathematical approximations seem to obtain in reality;
    and why it seems like mathematical truths are discovered, not created (and that those discoveries seem to be
    independent of the physical sciences — mathematical entities seem to be abstract, but also seem to exist).

    Mathematical Platonism is so useful that even mathematicians who do not want to commit to Platonist
    metaphysics sometimes take a position called “working realism.” This means that they perform their work in
    theoretical mathematics as if Platonism is true. This methodology is helpful in many ways, including its
    implication that all mathematical problems are solvable.

     DID YOU KNOW

    A famous mathematical Platonist, Kurt Gödel, made such claims much more difficult by proving that

    mathematical systems display a certain type of incompleteness.

    3. Pursuing Truth Over Appearance

    In a dialogue called the Gorgias, Plato asked (and attempted to answer) an interesting question: what is a
    genuine techne, or “craft”?

     DID YOU KNOW

    The term, “technology” comes from the Greek words techne and logos.
    The question was important to Plato because it involves the distinction between philosophy and rhetoric. He
    viewed the former as genuine craft, and the latter as a pseudocraft.

    Plato argued that philosophy is a genuine craft because its subject matter is a Form or Forms, specifically, the
    Forms of Wisdom and Truth. Rhetoric, which superficially resembles philosophy in its emphasis on
    argumentation, fails to have a Form as its subject matter. As we have seen, rhetoric is concerned with
    appearances. (Plato didn’t have a high regard for simply “winning debates,” so he relegated rhetoric to the
    realm of appearances.)

    Plato provided other pairs of activities in which the first is a genuine techne or craft, and the second is a
    pseudocraft. One of the genuine crafts is medicine, which takes as its subject the Form of Health. The
    corresponding pseudocraft (which only looks like medicine) is called “cookery” — what we would call “quack
    remedies.” These remedies might create an appearance of health without really producing that state. Plato
    also paired gymnastic or exercise, which aims to produce bodily Health, with a pseudocraft called
    “beautification” or makeup. Makeup, like cookery, might create an appearance of physical health, but nothing
    more. Consider people who visit a gym to build up their arms, but never another part of their bodies, or those
    who inject substances to enhance muscle appearance (e.g., Synthol).

     THINK ABOUT IT

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 97

    Try to think of some more pairs of crafts which seek to attain truth and corresponding psuedocrafts that

    focus on appearances. Consider diets formulated by a dietician vs. fad diets; genuine relationship

    compatibility vs. ineffective computer matching; using proper grammar vs. common slang expressions,

    etc. What all of these pairs have in common is that the pseudocraft is focused on achieving what is

    appealing/marketable. This describes the activity in which the sophists were involved in Socrates’ time: it

    was focused on appearances, not truth.

    These examples of genuine crafts have been presented to emphasize that philosophy, in light of its regard for
    wisdom and truth, is a model activity for a human being, nourishment for the soul and the rational side of our
    nature. Any craft should, as a proper human activity, involve the pursuit of truth.

    Humanity’s debt to Plato’s philosophy cannot be overstated. Those who become involved in

    metaphysics and epistemology in the course of studying philosophy and theology, are deeply

    engaged with Plato’s work — implicitly or explicitly. A Platonic conception of mathematical objects has

    been of great value in theoretical mathematics. Plato’s account of techne helps us to distinguish (and

    value) genuine human endeavor from mere marketing ploys.

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 98

    Aristotle: The Dissection of Reality
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Plato’s student, Aristotle, was one of the most influential thinkers of all time. We say “thinker” rather

    than “philosopher” because his influence stretches far beyond philosophy. His groundbreaking work

    in astronomy, biology, physics, and formal logic had a greater impact on science than that of any other

    individual in history. In this tutorial, we investigate Aristotle’s work, focusing on the differences and

    similarities between his philosophical approach and Plato’s.

    This tutorial examines Aristotle’s approach to, and interpretation of, reality in two parts:

    1. Aristotle’s Scientific Approach

    2. The Mathematician and the Biologist

    1. Aristotle’s Scientific Approach

    When attempting to gain an overview of Aristotle’s work, it is helpful to think of him as, first and foremost, a
    biologist. Though not all of Aristotle’s writings have been preserved, he wrote twice as much on biology as he
    did on philosophy (and he wrote a lot on philosophy). That is not to say that all of his philosophical questions
    have been answered in terms of biology, but it does help us to understand his perspective.

    Aristotle took a “hands on” approach to the search for knowledge.

     DID YOU KNOW

    As far as we know, Aristotle was the first scientist to dissect animals. Also, he identified approximately

    500 species of fish, mammals, and birds using binomial nomenclature, a method that is still used by

    biologists today.

    In philosophy, Aristotle began his investigations with specific knowns (i.e., examples found in the world). When
    Aristotle wanted to understand goodness he began by researching past approaches to ethics (i.e., accounts of
    goodness) to determine whether they were satisfactory, before developing a system of his own.

    Aristotle can be credited with the invention of academic research. The school he founded, the Lyceum,
    became a repository of knowledge. When his research led him to conclude that existing accounts were
    unsatisfactory, he developed an account of his own. When he did so, Aristotle used a known (i.e., something
    he knew could be, or was, true), as the starting point for his inquiry. If we want to know about the human
    essence, Aristotle’s research method directs us to begin with individual humans rather than an abstract Form
    of Humanity. Aristotle held that starting with the known world (i.e., the one we encounter through our senses)
    rather than an abstract realm of metaphysics, was the best way to begin a philosophical inquiry.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 99

    2. The Mathematician and the Biologist

    When attempting to gain an understanding of Aristotle’s approach and accomplishments, it may be helpful to
    consider two later epistemological viewpoints: empiricism and rationalism. These two perspectives are
    distinguished by their identification of the source of knowledge.

     TERM TO KNOW

    Empiricism

    The epistemological view based on the claim that all knowledge is grounded in

    experience

    Note the “grounded” qualification included in this definition. Empiricists do not claim that everything one can
    conceive of must have been experienced by that person. For example, a person does not have to have seen
    a golden mountain in order to refer to, or think about, one. He or she only needs ideas of “gold” and
    “mountain” to combine. Empiricism maintains that all of our building blocks come from experience, and that
    those building blocks can be combined into ideas we have not experienced. This epistemological viewpoint is
    contrasted with rationalism:

     TERM TO KNOW

    Rationalism

    The epistemological view based on the claim that humans can access certain conceptual truths

    independent of experience

    It is important to understand that rationalism is not the opposite of empiricism. Empiricism maintains that
    knowledge only comes from the senses. That does not mean, however, that rationalism denies that the
    senses are a source of knowledge. Instead, rationalism denies that knowledge only comes from the senses.
    Empiricism claims that there is one source of knowledge. Rationalism asserts that there are two.

    Empiricism and rationalism are in agreement on most issues. Rationalists grant all of the empirical truths of the
    sciences learned through experience, all knowledge of the senses, etc. The area of disagreement is mostly
    involved with concepts — but not all concepts. For example, empiricism and rationalism both grant that human
    minds have the power of abstraction. Humans can conceive and discuss a concept of horse derived from
    individual horses. What kind of concept, then, does the rationalist propose as knowable, independent of
    experience? The primary area of digression involves large metaphysical concepts about causation. Many
    rationalists hold that claims like “nothing comes into existence un-caused” are conceptual truths that must be
    true independent of experience. However, empiricists maintain that this is something that is known only
    through experience.

    The following example provides only a rough overview of these distinctions, but if we think of epistemology
    as a scale, with pure empiricism at one end and pure rationalism at the other, we can place Aristotle very
    close to the empiricism end of the scale, and Plato close to the rationalist end.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 100

    Aristotle’s scientific approach is primarily empirical. He maintained that we learn about humanity by
    abstracting from particular humans. This is what we would expect from a biologist. Plato, however, frequently
    appealed to a realm of pure intellect, known as Platonic Heaven, where the Forms reside. Recall that the
    Forms are analogous to mathematical objects or entities. Plato, in some of his writings, implied that we may
    learn about the Forms in between lives and later recollect them, or access them through pure philosophical
    reasoning. Either of these methods, as a result of the topics involved, are unsatisfactory to empiricists.
    Empiricists don’t object to mathematical entities, but do not accept mathematical entities that interact causally
    with the world.

    Raphael di Santi captured the contrast of approaches between Plato and Aristotle in his painting, The School
    of Athens.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 101

    Raphael’s The School of Athens, painted between 1509 and 1511. The fresco painting resides in the Apostolic Palace,

    Vatican City. It is a remarkable size, measuring approximately 16.5 feet across and 25 feet tall!

    The painting depicts a number of Greek philosophers, each of them engaged in an activity related to their
    philosophy and/or life. Take a look at the two figures in the middle of the painting.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 102

    Close-up view of Plato and Aristotle in Raphael’s The School of Athens”

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Study the image above and consider the differences in approaches between Plato and Aristotle. Which of

    the figures do you think is Plato, and which one is Aristotle? Why? In what ways has Raphael depicted the

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 103

    differences between the approaches of Plato and Aristotle?

    On the left is Plato, pointing to the heavens. Aristotle, on the right, gestures at the ground (trying to bring Plato
    down to earth). This indicates the fundamental difference in their approaches to learning. For Plato, inquiry
    begins in the metaphysical realm of the Forms. Aristotle’s approach begins with the world around him.

     LEARN MORE

    Click the link to explore Raphael’s painting “School of Athens” and learn more about the other Greek

    philosophers depicted in it.

    http://www.hellenicaworld.com/Greece/Science/en/SchoolAthens.html

    Aristotle studied under Plato for years. Although he was a brilliant student, he was not an uncritical

    disciple. The most fundamental difference between teacher and student was in their approaches to

    learning, their starting points in the quest for knowledge. Plato, who was epistemologically closer to

    what would later be called rationalism, sought knowledge in near-mathematical Forms and the realm

    of metaphysics, the world behind the world. Aristotle began his search with the world around him.

    Unsurprisingly, Aristotle’s work involves the sciences to a great extent. His epistemological view was

    closer to what was later called empiricism.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Image “The School of Athens” | Author: Raphael | License: Public Domain

    Plato and Aristotle from “School of Athens” | Author: Raphael | License: Public Domain

    Bust of Plato | License: Public Domain

    Bust of Aristotle | License: Public Domain


    Rationalism

    The epistemological view centering around the claim that humans can access certain conceptual truths

    independently of experience

    ​Empiricism
    The epistemological view centering around the claim that all knowledge is grounded in experience

    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 104

    http://www.hellenicaworld.com/Greece/Science/en/SchoolAthens.html

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/The_School_of_Athens#/media/File:Sanzio_01

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Plato#/media/File:Sanzio_01_Plato_Aristotle

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Plato#/media/File:Plato_Silanion_Musei_Capitolini_MC1377

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/File:Aristotle_Altemps_Inv8575

    Aristotle on What There Is
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Recall that Aristotle based his philosophy on his perceptions of the material world, on what he could

    observe. In this tutorial, we will consider Aristotle’s Categories, which provide his account of what we

    can infer about reality, based on what we can observe.

    This tutorial investigates Aristotle’s conclusions about the nature of reality in five parts:

    1. First Philosophy:

    Ontology

    2. Universals and Particulars

    3.

    Substance

    4. Aristotelian Essences

    5.

    Hylomorphism

    1. First Philosophy: Ontology

    Throughout history, philosophers have discussed first philosophy. This is a pedagogical concept, indicating
    what must be studied and learned first in order to advance in the field of philosophy. Philosophers have
    defended different candidates for first philosophy — many believed that it is logic. It has been asserted that
    Plato’s rule was that no one could become a student of the Academy until he or she had first mastered
    mathematics. Much later, Descartes said that epistemology was first philosophy. Aristotle’s selection, however,
    was ontology.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Ontology

    The branch of metaphysics that examines the nature of being

    Ontological questions center around what kinds of things exist, and how they exist. “Does x depend on y in
    order to exist?” is an ontological question. Ontology is, therefore, a good candidate for first philosophy.
    Knowing what kinds of things exist is a good place to begin for anyone who wants to advance in any field.
    This is especially important if you consider the nature of truth. What makes a statement true? Most people
    would answer that it is because the statement corresponds with reality in some way. What makes “Don is
    bald” true? Most would think that it is because a person named Don exists, and this person lacks hair on his
    head. If our interest is in truth, then we must give an account of what is.

    2. Universals and Particulars

    Consider this assertion: “The chair is broken.” What is required in order to be able to say that this statement is

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 105

    true? You would need to assert that there is an object that it is a chair, and that it exists in a certain state. But
    notice that three things have been asserted in saying that the chair is broken:

    There is a specific object that exists

    That object is a chair

    That object (the chair) exists in the state of brokenness

    You need two concepts, the concept of “chair” and the concept of the state of “broken”, and you need an
    existence claim, that the chair exists in this state, in order to make this assertion.

    Let’s set aside brokenness and focus on the claims involved in saying “there is a chair” (i.e., “there is an object
    that exists, and it is a chair”). To say “there is a chair” is to say that this specific object matches the concept of
    chair. To say there is a chair, you therefore need “this object (chair)” and also the concept, “chair.” In terms of
    philosophy, this illustrates the difference between a particular and a universal.

     TERMS TO KNOW

    Particular

    A concrete, extant entity

    Universal

    An ontological category that is common to multiple particulars

    Aristotle’s definition of a particular is a little simpler than the one above. He called a particular a “this,” which
    seems vague and unhelpful until you think it through. We can refer to “chair” (the universal entity which
    applies to multiple chairs) or this chair (a particular chair). “Human” or “this human,” and so on. We can even
    talk about properties, such as the universal “blue,” versus the particular, “this blue.”

    As a result, a “this” is very helpful in thinking about particulars. Take any concept for which we have a general
    term (e.g., “car”), and put “this” before it (i.e., “this car”). When you do so, you move from referring to the
    universal concept to the particular. Note that “universal,” in this instance, means “more than one,” not “all” or
    “every.”

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 106

    This diagram helps to visually differentiate between universals and particulars. While the universal “car” refers

    generally to cars, the particular “car” refers to one specific car.

    All of this is to say that, if we grant that it is true that the chair is broken, we have entered three kinds of thing
    into our ontology: particular chairs, the universal chair, and the universal quality of being broken. All are
    required in order to say that the statement is true. Similar categories are involved whenever we make a claim
    to truth. Consider claims like, “humans are rational.” We posit particular humans, humanity, and rationality. As
    we continue to make claims to truth we will notice a pattern.

    3. Substance

    We should notice that these simple statements contain a subject and a predicate.

     HINT

    Dust off those grammar skills! Remember that subjects and predicates are parts of a sentence. The

    subject of a sentence is what (or who) the sentence is about. The predicate tells you what the subject is

    doing or has done or will do. In this sentence — “The chair is broken.” — the chair is the subject, and “is

    broken” is the predicate. The subject and predicate are used to describe reality accurately.

    Likewise, in reality, we have a thing, and a property attributed to that thing. To accurately describe that
    property as belonging to that thing is to speak truly. Therefore, our ontology includes a collection of things.
    The technical term Aristotle used is for this category is “substance,” which indicates any subject. Shoes and

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 107

    ships and sealing wax are substances, as are you and I. There are also ways (states or conditions in which)
    those things can be: dented, blue, over 12 feet tall, etc. Aristotle established nine categories of ways things
    can be:

    Ways of Being Example

    Quantity Five

    Quality Blue

    Relation Greater than

    Place In front of the TV

    Time Last year

    Position Sitting

    State Unarmed

    Action Reading

    Affection To be read

    Anything that can be said to exist falls into one of these ten categories, either a substance or a way of being.
    However, substance has ontological primacy over the other nine ways of being. That is, substance can exist
    without the other nine, but they cannot exist independent of substance. They are, therefore, ontologically
    dependent on substance.

     EXAMPLE There can be a fender without a dent, but there cannot be a dent without a fender.
    Blueness cannot exist by itself: There are only blue things.

    Note that by making individual substances ontologically primary, Aristotle disagreed significantly with Plato.
    Plato posited a Form of goodness, for example, that is independent of any individual good person. Aristotle
    asserted that there cannot be goodness without any good individuals.

    4. Aristotelian Essences

    Aristotle’s ways of being are related to his notion of essence. As an example, consider the essence of
    humanity. Since it applies to many humans, it must be a universal entity. However, since you can truly assign
    properties to the universal humanity (as in the assertion that “humanity is rational”), the universal humanity
    must be substantial. But because humanity, like blueness, cannot exist independently, the human essence
    (i.e., humanity) must exist in individual humans. Unlike Plato, Aristotle discovered humanity in people.

    Aristotle’s ontology provides us with an easy way to identify an essence — a way to quickly identify what Plato
    agonized over. If we want to discover and describe the human essence, all we need to do is isolate two
    things: a genus and a differentia. The genus tells us what kind of thing it is. The differentia tells us what sets it
    apart from other things of the same kind. Let’s take a look at two examples:

     EXAMPLE Suppose we want to identify the essence of a hammer. We can ask, what kind of thing
    is it? Our answer would be that it is a tool. Next, we might ask, what distinguishes hammers from other

    tools? The answer in this instance might be that they are used for pounding. Our investigation leads us

    to conclude that the essence of a hammer (i.e., what makes a hammer a hammer) is that it is a tool

    used for pounding.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 108

     EXAMPLE Let’s try another example and identify the essence of a professor. What kind of thing is
    a professor? A professor is a teacher. What distinguishes professors from other teachers? They teach

    at the collegiate level. Therefore, to be a professor is to be a college-level teacher.

    So what kind of thing is a human? A human is a biped (i.e., walks on two legs). What separates humans from
    other bipeds? Rationality separates humans from other bipeds. Therefore, a human is a rational biped (or a
    rational animal, depending on whether Aristotle was writing about philosophy or biology).

     MAKE THE CONNECTION

    If this sounds familiar, it is because we still use Aristotle’s concept in biology. In the system of binomial

    nomenclature, an organism is named with a genus and a species. Homo sapiens is Latin for rational biped,

    or wise man, which distinguishes them from Neanderthals, Cro-Magnons, and other hominids. We still use

    genus and differentia to determine what kind of thing an organism is.

    5. Hylomorphism

    What is a human? According to Aristotle, a human is a union of form (essence) and matter. This is an instance
    of hylomorphism.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Hylomorphism

    The metaphysical theory that posits being as a union of form and matter

    This is the foundation of the concept, but more needs to be understood to define it fully. Although we have
    been using humans as an example, this is a theory of being. It therefore applies to everything, to every
    Aristotelian substance: any subject— animal, vegetable, or mineral; any individual item that is an instance of a
    natural kind (i.e., species, in Aristotle’s system).

    As a theory of being, hylomorphism involves an intimate, possibly essential, relationship. The standard
    interpretation of Aristotle’s theory is that existence is a package deal: You don’t have formless matter waiting
    to be shaped. Instead, you get matter and form, or nothing at all. There is no formless matter, we can only talk
    about it conceptually (when doing so, it is referred to as “prime matter”). There is no matterless form either.
    There is no such thing as humanity independent of individual humans (despite Plato’s assertions).

    Aristotle explains this by using an analogy with wax. Conceptually, we can separate wax into its matter, the
    stuff of which it is composed, and its shape. However, this distinction is purely conceptual. There is no such
    thing as shapeless wax (meaning that it has no shape whatsoever), and there is likewise no such thing as
    shape without something to be shaped.

    Based on this overview of hylomorphism, it is evident that there can be interpretive difficulties with this theory.
    First, we need to inquire as to the nature of the form. Is the form of a living thing just a structure (i.e., a
    blueprint for producing humans, like DNA), or is it more than this? In living things, Aristotle equated “form” with
    “soul.” However, it would be wrong to assume that Aristotle used “soul” in the same way we use it today.

    The ancient Greek word he used was “anima,” which is etymologically related to “animal” and “animate.”
    Aristotle’s notion of soul/anima is that which makes a living thing alive: an animating force. When considered
    in this way, it is clear that he did not intend to define hylomorphism in quasi-religious terms. Aristotle was not
    convinced that there was an afterlife (though in some of his works, he left open the possibility that intellectual
    thought may survive physical death because thought does not belong to any part of the body, but is somehow

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 109

    independent of it). However, that only tells us what the anima is not. We know that souls provide an
    organizing principle. We don’t know what else, if anything, they provide.

    Aristotle held that first philosophy was ontology: that we must determine what kinds of things exist in

    order to progress in our studies. As grounds for truth, he posited ten categories of being, of which

    substance was the primary category. One important kind of substance is species, which is a universal

    entity that exists in particulars (e.g., universal humanity existing in particular humans). An easy way to

    identify these essences is to discover the genus and differentia, a technique so useful that it is one of

    the few that have continued to be used in science for over two millennia.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Car Image | Author: Xinh Studio | License: CC

    Car Image | Author: Hopkins | License: CC

    Car Image | Author: Alrigel | License: CC


    Hylomorphism
    The metaphysical theory that posits being as a union of form and matter
    Ontology
    The branch of metaphysics that examines the nature of being
    Particular
    A concrete, extant entity
    Universal
    An ontological category that is common to multiple particulars
    SUMMARY
    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 110

    https://thenounproject.com/search/?q=car&i=33039

    https://thenounproject.com/search/?q=car&i=884883

    https://thenounproject.com/search/?q=car&i=1168315

    Plato vs. Aristotle: The Mathematician or the
    Biologist

    by Sophia Tutorial

    Plato and Aristotle, teacher and student, are two of the most influential thinkers in history. Their

    systems of metaphysics are extremely different in some ways, but they have important commonalities

    as well. In this tutorial, we will highlight their similarities, then contrast their differences.

    This tutorial examines the similarities and differences between the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle

    in two parts:

    1. Some Important Similarities

    2. Their Main Points of Disagreement

    1. Some Important Similarities

    At first, it may seem that Plato and Aristotle, the mathematician and the biologist, took radically different
    approaches in searching for the truth. However, this is usually the result of over-emphasizing their differences.
    It would be surprising if Plato and Aristotle were completely opposed in all of their beliefs, since Aristotle
    studied under Plato at the Academy for 20 years. Clearly, Aristotle found the study of Plato’s philosophy to be
    a good use of his time.

    To identify their significant similarities then, we must understand that Plato taught Aristotle traditional
    philosophy. As a result, there are more similarities in their views than differences. Those who study (and
    teach) philosophy — as both of them did — pursue truth, above all else.

     DID YOU KNOW

    When Aristotle criticized or disagreed with Plato in his writings, he sometimes prefaced his criticism with a

    reminder that Plato taught him to value truth above all else, including friendship. Since Plato was also a

    philosopher, he would have approved of Aristotle’s reminder.

    Plato and Aristotle agreed that we must pursue truth by using reason and logic, rather than passion, emotion,
    and bias.

    Both of them were metaphysicians, who proposed metaphysical entities which grounded the known world.
    For example, both Plato and Aristotle were realists with respect to essences. They maintained that essences
    existed, and that they were genuine truth-grounding entities.

    However, not all philosophers believe this. Nominalists, for example, deny that essences exist in this way.
    Instead, they maintain that “essences” exist in name only, as linguistic coincidences, or that they are
    determined by biology, not metaphysics. Nominalists claim that what makes a just act just is that humans have

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 111

    defined what justice means. Acts which satisfy the definition’s criteria are just acts.

    The work of Plato and Aristotle shares additional metaphysical commonalities. For example, their accounts of
    the cosmos considered notions like cause-and-effect metaphysically, rather than scientifically (recall that this
    is why we did not identify Aristotle as a complete empiricist). They also used metaphysics to explain how
    entities in the world should be. These points continue to be debated by philosophers, but Plato and Aristotle
    did not disagree on them.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Essence
    What makes a thing what it is
    2. Their Main Points of Disagreement

    The primary differences between the philosophies of Plato and Aristotle are differences within metaphysics
    and epistemology. Most of them are related to Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms, a doctrine that Aristotle rejects
    almost completely.

    Remember that Forms are Platonic essences. As mentioned above, both Plato and Aristotle believed that
    essences exist, and that they are the grounds for truth. Plato’s essences are Platonic Forms — real,
    metaphysical entities that exist in a non-physical realm. Individual entities are who or what they are because
    of their participation in the relevant Form. For example, consider the Form of Humanity. It is the human
    essence, which determines what it is to be a human. It represents humanity in its truest sense. Human beings
    are human because they participate in (and are, therefore, imperfect imitations of) the Form of Humanity.

    Although Aristotle agreed that humanity is a genuine entity (a substance in Aristotle’s terminology), it is not a
    Platonic Entity. First, Aristotle maintained that humanity was not located in Platonic Heaven, but in every
    individual human being. One human is different from another, not because they are both imperfect copies of a
    perfect Form of Humanity, but because they are composed of different matter.

    Another important difference between Plato and Aristotle regarding Forms is an ontological point. (Recall that
    ontology is the branch of metaphysics that examines the nature of being.) In Plato’s view, the Form of
    Humanity (and, therefore, the human essence) exists whether or not there are any individual humans. Aristotle
    believed that, in the absence of individual humans, there is no humanity: there is no longer a human essence.
    How essences exist was an area of significant difference between the two thinkers.

     TERM TO KNOW
    Substance

    The “what it is” of any given thing.

    Remember that essences ground truth. Therefore, where and how essences exist determine the way we
    come to know truth. These metaphysical differences lead to important epistemological differences. Aristotle
    believed that essences are in the world. In order to learn the true nature of humans, we must examine
    individual humans and identify their essential features. Aristotle searched for truth empirically: by examining
    the world.

    Plato maintained that essences exist independently of the world, in a metaphysical realm, a world behind the
    world. Therefore, knowledge of things as they truly are requires us to go beyond the changing realm of
    appearances and contemplate the unchanging realm of the Forms. This is a rationalist approach.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 112

    For example, Plato’s ethics begins with a contemplation of the nature of goodness and justice. Aristotle’s
    account of ethics begins biologically, with a consideration of human physical characteristics.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Whose approach to philosophy seems better, Plato’s or Aristotle’s? Here are a few questions that may

    help you to decide:

    If you remove all humans, are there still truths about human essence (not to be confused with truths

    of human history)? Plato says yes, Aristotle says no.

    What is the best way to study mathematics? Should you begin with pure math or applied math? Plato

    says pure math, Aristotle says applied math.

    Can I say 5 is greater than 3, or only that 5 apples is greater than 3 apples? Aristotle is limited to the

    latter response.

    Consider gravity. We know that every object falls because of the law of gravity, but is the law of

    gravity contained in each bit of matter in the universe, or does the law of gravity exist outside of, and

    act upon, all matter? This is not an easy question to answer. Even physicists are split on the point.

    However, Aristotle would say the former, and Plato, the latter. The question to ask yourself is, if there

    were no matter in the universe, would the law of gravity still be true? Plato says yes, Aristotle says no.

    Plato and Aristotle are philosophers who committed their lives to realizing truth through reason.

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 113

    Although both of them posited essences as genuine metaphysical entities, their accounts of

    metaphysics led to very different metaphysical, epistemological and methodological results. Most of

    these differences involve the ontological status of essences. Plato says that essences exist outside of,

    and are independent of, particulars. Aristotle maintains that they are within particulars, and only exist

    if some of the particulars do.

    ​Essence
    What makes a thing what it is

    ​Substance
    The “what it is” of any given thing

    TERMS TO KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 114

    Aristotelianism: The Naturalistic Worldview
    by Sophia Tutorial

    In Aristotle’s lifetime, he was known as “the man who knew everything,” with no sarcasm intended.

    His breadth of knowledge was the reason that Alexander of Macedonia (i.e., Alexander the Great)

    sought him out as his private tutor. During the Middle Ages, Aristotle was referred to as, “the

    Philosopher” (note the capital “P”). In this tutorial, we will examine some of Aristotle’s intellectual

    legacy.

    This tutorial provides an overview of Aristotle’s worldview in two parts:

    1. Aristotle’s Intellectual Legacy: Naturalism

    2. Formal Logic

    1. Aristotle’s Intellectual Legacy: Naturalism

    If you were asked to summarize Aristotle’s contributions to humanity in a single word, “science” would be a
    good answer. He was not the first philosopher to consider topics that are now seen as scientific (recall the
    contributions of the Pre-Socratics), but Aristotle was innovative in keeping science self-contained. Like the
    Pre-Socratics, he did not use divine involvement to account for phenomena he could not explain. He also did
    not rely on metaphysical abstractions like “humanity”. Although Aristotle used metaphysics (even in his
    biology), his descriptions of reality and explanations of phenomena were based in this world. They could —
    and should — be studied, measured, quantified, and tested.

    Today, we call this kind of worldview naturalism. The naturalistic worldview specifically excludes the
    supernatural and, in so doing, forces us to deepen our understanding of the natural world. Naturalism does
    not necessarily exclude any notion of, or belief in, the supernatural. Instead, it denies the supernatural any role
    when explaining natural phenomena. This is the standard observed by science today.

    When we assume that there are natural explanations, we look for them, and science advances. When we
    accept a supernatural explanation, we cease looking for natural causes, and science stagnates. For example,
    if, when crops fail, witches are blamed, natural causes are not investigated. Areas including irrigation,
    fertilizer, crop rotation, and more are not explored. Potential remedies and improvements are left
    undiscovered. The same thing happens when metaphysical abstractions are accepted as explanations.
    Someone who believes (without foundation) that it is human nature to degenerate, will not discover medical
    treatments for diseases.

    This approach is called methodological naturalism. It doesn’t deny the existence of supernatural entities, but
    asserts that science must not accept non-natural explanations for phenomena. As a result of this contribution
    by Aristotle, the sciences have enjoyed much success.

    Consider an example from Aristotle’s ethics. Aristotle didn’t look for the foundations of ethics by performing

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 115

    conceptual analyses on the good and the just (as Plato did). Instead, he grounded his ethics in biology, on the
    kind of entities that humans are, and should be, according to their biological nature. He applied this
    naturalistic method with great success, especially when combined with his introduction of research.

    Aristotle was one of the first (if not the first) investigators to gather and analyze works on a topic before
    beginning his analysis, and before coming to any conclusions. This research methodology, combined with his
    methodological naturalism, led him to become known as the Father of Biology, the Father of Physics, and
    (sometimes) the Father of Astronomy. The need to precisely define natural kinds led him to develop binomial
    nomenclature, and to perform some of the first dissections.

    This painting, titled Aristotle with a bust of Homer also known as Aristotle Contemplating a Bust of Homer, was

    painted in 1653 by Rembrandt. Rembrandt painted it on a canvas with oil paints.

     DID YOU KNOW

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 116

    Aristotle studied ocean creatures by examining, and sometimes dissecting, the fish and other animals

    caught by fishermen. He described the hectocotyl arm of the male octopus, which is used in sexual

    reproduction. He also accurately differentiated aquatic mammals from fish, including sharks.

    Aristotle’s contributions to the sciences cannot be overstated. In addition to almost single-handedly creating
    the science of biology, he introduced the use of formal research processes and methodological naturalism,
    which benefited all of the sciences.

    2. Formal Logic

    Aristotle is also known as the Father of Logic. Although every philosopher before Aristotle used logic,
    argument, and reasoning to pursue truth (e.g., Socrates), Aristotle was the first to treat logic as a separate
    discipline, analogous to mathematics (i.e., it can be studied, formalized, and proven). He was the first to use
    logic according to precise rules that determined validity. This was a significant advance in the development of
    reasoning. Knowing which conclusions follow from which premises is crucial. Here is an example of how
    Aristotelian logic can help us to make valid arguments.

     EXAMPLE People often like to give one-premise arguments that are, in fact, two-premise
    arguments. For example, “Some immigrants from country X have committed crimes. Therefore, we

    should not allow people from that country to enter the U.S.” Aristotelian syllogistic logic enables us to

    understand that, in order for this conclusion to be valid, we must have an implicit first premise, of the

    form, “We should not let people enter the U.S. who are from a county whose immigrants have

    committed a crime.” But is this premise defensible? No. If this premise was accepted, no one would be

    allowed to enter the U.S., including U.S. citizens.

    Aristotle’s formal system of syllogistic logic is good at detecting weak reasoning, and teaches us to base our
    thinking and our arguments on reason, not emotion. In developing formal logic, Aristotle also introduced
    purely syntactical methods (that is, focusing entirely on structure, without any need to examine semantic
    content) for determining logical consequences. This was the first step in the development of computers (and
    computer programming). Aristotelian syllogism represents the beginnings of formal logic, but it is not only of
    historical interest. It continues to be studied in courses on logic and critical thinking, and questions involving
    its use are included in standardized testing.

    Aristotle’s philosophical legacy is only a small part of his overall intellectual legacy. His approach to

    questions and explanations resulted in the establishment and accomplishments of science as we

    know it. His formalization of logic improved the process of reasoning and led to the development of

    advanced logical systems used in electronic circuitry and computers. His contributions continue to

    impact modern lives in a variety of ways.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Aristotle with a Bust of Homer | Author: Rembrandt | License: Public Domain

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 117

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Aristotle#/media/File:Rembrandt_-_Aristotle_with_a_Bust_of_Homer_-_WGA19232

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 118

    Aristotle’s Highest Good
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Anyone who wants to relate ethics to how humans should be (in the biological sense) will confront —

    and use — Aristotelian ethics. As a result, many neo-Aristotelians are involved in the field of

    contemporary ethics. In this tutorial, we will investigate three major components of Aristotle’s ethics:

    the Function Argument, the relevance of virtues to ethics, and the Doctrine of the Mean.

    This tutorial examines Aristotle’s ethical philosophy, in three parts:

    1. The Function Argument

    2. Virtue Ethics

    3. The Doctrine of the Mean

    1. The Function Argument

    In order to advance your ability to understand and apply ethics, you must provide a plausible answer to this
    question: “What makes an action good?” If you cannot state what makes an action right or wrong in general,
    you cannot participate in a meaningful discussion of any moral issue. If you cannot say why an action is right
    or wrong, then (for example), a debate about abortion is simply an exercise to determine who can talk louder.

    However, if you can identify what it is that makes an action right or wrong, you can use that standard to
    evaluate any potential action. Aristotle’s Function Argument provides an answer to “What makes an action
    good?” (i.e., what makes an act right or wrong), and to “Where does value comes from?”

    The Function Argument takes this form: Start with something you know can be good, or not. For example, a
    steak knife. Next, ask, “When is it good?” The steak knife is not good when it cuts meat, but when it cuts meat
    well. Something is good when it excels at its function. This is true of everything.

     TRY IT

    Take several examples of something you know can be good, but isn’t always good. Is it true that the

    difference between times when the thing is good, and times when it is not good, is whether it fulfills its

    function well (or not)?

    When considering examples (e.g., a good meal, a good cell phone), it quickly becomes clear that a thing’s
    function is tied to what kind of thing it is. Function follows essence. What makes a thing what it is tells us how
    that thing should be.

    Since no one wants to be an excellent steak knife or an excellent puppy, we must consider the human
    essence, which is to be a rational animal. To be a good human is to excel at being a rational animal or, more
    precisely, to cultivate the virtues conducive to excellence as a rational animal.

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 119

    2. Virtue Ethics

    Aristotle’s Function Argument connects function to excellence. The word Aristotle used is “arête,” which is
    translated as “virtue” or “personal excellence.” Aristotelian ethics is concerned with answering this question —
    “What kind of person should I be?” — rather than “How should I act?” (the question that is now the norm in
    ethics). These two questions are clearly related, but differ in their primary consideration. For Aristotle,
    character was primary. Actions are evaluated based on how they inform your character (e.g., Does an action
    make you greedy? Smug? Generous? Brave?).

    Aristotle used biology to answer “What kind of person should I be?” in a way that, when we must act, we will
    act according to our individual characters. The kind of character to be evaluated is based on what kind of
    thing we are (i.e., rational animals). By “rational,” Aristotle meant something very specific. Since rational is of
    our essence, it is what separates humans from other animals. Humans are the kind of thing that can think
    abstractly (not just of what to do in a particular case, but in general). Humans can plan the best ways to
    achieve their goals (which are focused on their happiness).

    For this reason, an essential component of rational choice is deliberation. We deliberate on how we can best
    achieve the good life, and on what kind of person each of us should be. This tells us the way we should be,
    and the virtues we should have.

    3. The Doctrine of the Mean

    Once we have determined the virtues we must cultivate, and have cultivated them, we must begin to manifest
    them. This is not easy, because virtue comes in degrees. For example, courage is a virtue we should cultivate.
    Rational deliberation indicates that we should be courageous people, as part of human excellence. However,
    we must determine how courageous we should be.

    To answer this question, Aristotle provided the Doctrine of the Mean. Like other Aristotelian arguments, it
    begins with something we know: First, take something we know can be a virtue, such as courage. Next, ask
    “when is courage not a virtue (i.e., when is it a vice)?” Too little courage and you are a coward. Too much
    courage and you are foolhardy. (Note that there is nothing admirable about picking fights with tough people,
    or taking other unnecessary risks.) Courage, therefore, must be cultivated as a mean between

    extremes.

     MAKE THE CONNECTION

    In mathematics, the mean is the average of a set of numbers. In Aristotle’s Doctrine of the Mean, it is

    defined differently, but it indicates a somewhat similar concept: an average or midpoint between two

    extremes.

    As with the Function Argument, Aristotle used a specific example for a general claim: Any virtue is turned into
    a vice when developed to the point of excess or deficiency.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 120

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Think of some virtues (i.e., character traits of positive value). Are there any that do not become vices when

    practiced to excess? For example, justice becomes a vice when it excludes forgiveness. However, people

    can certainly be overly forgiving too.

    Aristotle indicated that this ideal is a rational mean, not a numeric mean. What does this mean? Let’s consider
    an example. It is a virtue to be financially productive (i.e., the trait involved in becoming rich)? What’s the least I
    can earn in a year? Zero. What is the most? Currently, the record is about $12.7 billion. The numeric mean of
    financial productivity would be a trait that leads to earning $6.35 billion dollars a year, but it would be absurd
    to make this a personal goal. It is clearly excessive. What did Aristotle mean by “rational mean?” To answer,
    recall rational deliberation, and the process involved in determining what kind of person I should be. If I
    dedicate too much of my effort to developing my financial productivity, I will fall short of the good life because
    other aspects of my life will suffer. I will not expend enough effort to develop other positive traits.

    Aristotle’s ethics are naturalistic, because he believed that the kind of thing we are was the source of

    ethics. Since humans are rational animals, we must cultivate the virtues conducive to the rational

    pursuit of happiness in a complete life. We develop virtues by manifesting them as a rational mean

    between extremes.

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 121

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Image of scales | Author: Wira | License: CC

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 122

    https://thenounproject.com/search/?q=balanced scale&i=1205972

    Applying Aristotle’s Ethics

    by Sophia Tutorial

    In this tutorial, we will review three major components of Aristotle’s ethics: the Function Argument, the

    relevance of virtues to ethics, and the Doctrine of the Mean. We’ll also examine some examples of

    these components.

    This tutorial considers the application of Aristotle’s ethics in four parts:

    1. The Function Argument
    2. Virtue Ethics
    3. The Doctrine of the Mean

    4. Applying Aristotle’s Ethics

    1. The Function Argument

    Recall that Aristotle’s Function Argument answers the question of what makes an act right or wrong, or where
    value comes from.

    The Function Argument demonstrates that function is tied to what kind of thing it is that is being considered.
    Function follows essence. What makes a thing what it is tells us how that thing should be. Accordingly, to be a
    good human is to excel at being a rational animal or, more precisely, to cultivate the virtues conducive to
    excelling at being a rational animal.

    2. Virtue Ethics

    Aristotle’s Function Argument relates function to excellence. Aristotelian ethics answered this question: “What
    kind of person should I be?” — not the question that is now the norm in ethics: “How should I act?” Although
    these two questions are related, they differ as to which consideration is primary. Aristotle believed that
    character is primary. In his system of ethics, actions are evaluated based on how they inform character: Does
    this action make a person greedy? Smug? Generous? Brave?

    Aristotle used biology to answer, “What kind of person should I be?” so that, when it is time to act, a person
    will act according to his or her character. The kind of character we should evaluate is based on what kind of
    thing we are (i.e., rational animals). By “rational,” Aristotle meant something very specific. Since reason is of
    our essence, it is what distinguishes humans from other animals. Human beings are the kind of thing that can
    think abstractly, not only of what to do in a specific case, but in general. Humans can plan the best ways to
    achieve our goals, which are focused on our happiness.

    For this reason, deliberation is an essential part of rational choice. Humans deliberate on how to best achieve

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 123

    the good life, and on what kind of people they should be. Doing so tells us the way we should be, and the
    virtues we should have.

    3. The Doctrine of the Mean

    Once we have determined the virtues we must cultivate, we must manifest them. This is not easy, because
    virtue comes in degrees. Aristotle formulated the Doctrine of the Mean to determine the degree to which one
    should cultivate a virtue. The Doctrine of the Mean states that a virtue must be cultivated as a mean between
    extremes.

    As he did in making the Function Argument, Aristotle used a specific example to establish a general claim:
    Any virtue becomes a vice when it is developed to the point of excess or deficiency.

    4. Applying Aristotle’s Ethics

    Let’s consider some real-life examples to which Aristotle’s ethics can be applied.

    Let’s say that you’re terrified of heights. Your fear is so great that it prevents you from doing certain things.
    You cannot go mountain hiking with your friends, you refuse to fly, and even climbing steep flights of stairs
    makes you uneasy. Your fear of heights, because it is extreme, is a vice.

    According to Aristotle, you should find the mean between your excessive fear (or cowardice), and too little
    fear (foolhardiness). Note that if you were insufficiently afraid of heights, you might be careless, which could
    cause you harm. Courage is the mean between these two extremes. You have enough fear of heights to keep
    you safe, but not so much that it prevents you from enjoying life.

     BRAINSTORM

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 124

    What are the extremes of virtues like ambition, justice, love, confidence? What are other virtues for which

    you can identify extremes?

    Consider the table below, which illustrates several virtues and vices. These are just a few examples; many
    others exist.

    Too Little (Vice) Mean (Virtue) Too Much (Vice)

    Cowardly Courageous Foolhardy

    Shy Modest Shameless

    Stingy Generous Extravagant

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Can you think of other applications of Aristotle’s ethics? How can the Doctrine of the Mean be applied to

    your life? Consider some of your vices. How could you moderate them to turn them into Aristotelian

    virtues?

    Aristotle’s ethics are naturalistic, because he believed that the source of ethics comes from what kind

    of thing we are. Since humans are rational animals, we must cultivate the virtues conducive to the

    rational pursuit of happiness in a complete life. We develop virtues by manifesting them as a rational

    mean between extremes.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Images of Scales | Author: Wira | License: CC

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 125

    https://thenounproject.com/search/?q=balanced scale&i=1205972

    Stoicism: The Ethics of Dispassion
    by Sophia Tutorial

    Stoicism was a school of philosophy that flourished in ancient Rome. It was not the philosophy of one

    philosopher, but of a group of like-minded individuals. In fact, the Roman emperor Marcus Aurelius

    was a stoic philosopher and author. However, Stoicism was not only a set of philosophical beliefs, but

    a way of life based upon those beliefs. Therefore, “Stoicism” is a legitimate answer to the question,

    “what’s your philosophy?”

    In this tutorial, we will investigate the central tenets of Stoicism and how it served as the basis of a

    system of ethics (and a way of life). We will focus on the teachings of Epictetus who, though he was

    not one of the first Stoics, was one of the most influential and admirable. Beginning as a crippled

    slave, Epictetus became a sought-after thinker. Like Socrates, he wrote nothing, but his work was

    recorded by his followers.

    This tutorial examines “the ethics of dispassion” in three parts:

    1. Focusing on What Is in Our Power

    2. How We Direct What Is in Our Power

    3. Ethics as a Role

    1. Focusing on What Is in Our Power
     BIG IDEA

    The most important tenet of Stoicism is to focus on what we can control, and to not be upset by things

    that are beyond our control.

    It is important to realize that the Stoic definition of “control” is limited, that “the things in our power are by
    nature free, not subject to restraint or hindrance.” However, more things are within our control than most of us
    realize.

     EXAMPLE Am I free to drive to work? Only if my car starts. Therefore, I am free to choose to drive
    to work, or want to drive to work but, despite my choice or desire, there may be limits to my freedom.

    As a result, there is an important sense in which I am not free to drive to work.

    Our main freedoms lie in how we react to the world, rather than in the world itself.

    Let’s revisit the example above, and consider all of the aspects of your drive that are not under your control.
    One aspect is red lights. You cannot control when a traffic light turns red (or doesn’t), but how you respond to
    the light turning red is under your control, including whether you get angry, upset, or worried.

    This illustrates what is perhaps the most helpful insight of Stoicism: No good comes from getting upset at

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 126

    things you cannot change. We cannot change the past, or the laws of physics. This seems like a trivial insight
    until we consider how much energy we waste in worrying about things that we cannot change.

     THINK ABOUT IT

    In what situations have you seen people become upset by things that are out of their control? Consider

    politics, and the extent to which people are upset by things that are out of their control. Have you

    observed this response by friends, family, or on social media? People spend months (or years) lamenting

    the fact that their candidate didn’t win. But you cannot control what other voters do, or how Congress

    votes. To focus on things like this, or to allow them to upset us, is absurd. Instead, what can we control?

    The answer is, we can control our actions and reactions.

    2. How We Direct What Is in Our Power

    The preceding example may have led you to think of things about politics that you can control, such as
    canvassing your neighborhood, trying to persuade your friends, voting, writing to your congressional
    representatives, signing petitions, etc. (i.e., activities related to active citizenship). However, Stoicism suggests
    something more basic than this. As indicated above, what is in our control is our desires, emotions, and
    judgments. Everything else depends on things that are outside of us in the world, which may not proceed as
    we intend. As a result, we must focus on our desires, reactions, and judgments.

    Controlling these things is not as easy as flipping a switch. That’s why, as a first step, Epictetus tells us, “Take
    away then aversion from all things which are not in our power, and transfer it to the things contrary to nature
    which are in our power. But destroy desire completely for the present. For if you desire anything which is not
    in our power, you must be unfortunate; but of the things in our power, and which it would be good to desire,
    nothing yet is before you.” A Stoic begins by eradicating all desire — not permanently, but only for the
    present. We must remove the old house before building a new one. We must eliminate all desires, then
    reintroduce those desires that are appropriate and helpful.

    Easier said than done. But consider the benefit to be obtained if you didn’t start your morning commute with a
    desire to get where you need to go quickly. Without that desire, red lights are of no concern to you. Neither is
    the driver who refuses to pass in the passing lane. Without that desire (note that it is a desire for something
    you cannot control), your morning commute can be pleasant. Epictetus maintained that the bad things we
    encounter (e.g., red lights) are the price we pay for tranquility, for freedom from disturbance.

     DID YOU KNOW

    Stoicism is popular in military training because it emphasizes self-control and the control of emotions, of

    doing the job you are assigned skillfully and dispassionately.

    This leads to a second point: we must realize that reality is neither bad nor good. It is our judgment about
    reality that upsets us. For example, are traffic lights bad? Of course not. But if traffic lights are in use on the
    roads, someone must need to stop for a red light at all times. So I don’t claim that it is bad that there are traffic
    lights on the road, or even that a particular traffic light is bad. Instead, I judge that it is bad for me (e.g.,
    because I must wait for this light to change, I may be late for work). Stoics maintain that this is true of
    everything (including death, as we will consider below). Reality is value-neutral. It is our judgments about
    reality that assign (dis)value to it.

    Consider a familiar example: food. Suppose I am in the mood for some foie gras from the French Riviera, and
    am lamenting the fact that all I have in my lunchbox is a peanut butter sandwich. The foie gras seems good,

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 127

    the peanut butter sandwich does not. However, if Epictetus was right, this is merely a judgment.

    To prove this, let’s replace “I” with a child in this example. The child loves the peanut butter sandwich much
    more than the foie gras. This shows that “good” is not a property of the foie gras itself. Rather, it is my
    judgment regarding the meal. If I put my mind to it, I can genuinely relish the peanut butter sandwich as much
    as the French delicacy, because it is my judgment, not the food itself, that makes it desirable (or not).
    Judgments (with practice) are under my control.

    Therefore, two crucial steps to becoming a good Stoic (i.e., to focusing on what is in our control) are:

    1. Eliminating desires

    2. Realizing that value is in our judgments, not in the world

    To further illustrate the Stoic way of thinking, let’s consider a topic they discussed often: death.

    Death is something we cannot control. We all must die. Since we cannot control it, there is no advantage to
    getting upset about it. Instead, as Stoics, we must focus on what we can control: what we feel about death.
    The Stoic neither fears death nor hides from it.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 128

    Epictetus says that we should think of death every day to discourage ourselves from desiring anything too much.

    Having the largest U-Haul trailer attached to your hearse is not a worthwhile goal. To Epictetus and the other Stoics,

    a desire to accumulate riches is the wrong kind of desire.

    How can we avoid the fear of death? First, by making sure that we only desire what is within our power. We
    cannot control how long our lives will be, so our focus should be not to live long, but to live well. We must
    understand that death, like everything else in the world, is neither bad nor good. Those are only our
    judgments. Living well is the basis of Stoic ethics.

    3. Ethics as a Role

    Epictetus explained the need to live well, given what is under our control, with an analogy. He wrote,
    “Remember that thou art an actor in a play, of such a kind as the teacher (author) may choose; if short, of a
    short one; if long, of a long one: if he wishes you to act the part of a poor man, see that you act the part
    naturally; if the part of a lame man, of a magistrate, of a private person, (do the same). For this is your duty, to
    act well the part that is given to you; but to select the part, belongs to another.” We cannot control where we
    are born, who is in our lives, how long we will live, etc. Our duty is to play our part well.

    “Playing a role well” may seem like a less-than-substantial basis for ethics, but it is not. Our “role” is deeply
    connected to the relationships we have with other people, and those relationships determine our duties.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 129

    For example, as a philosophy professor, I have a specific relationship to my students which entails many
    duties (e.g., providing a satisfactory learning environment, conveying class materials, grading fairly). However,
    I also play the role of husband, which entails many other duties, as do my roles of son, brother, uncle, etc.
    Additionally, I am a citizen of the U.S., which entails a relationship (and therefore duties) to other citizens. If I
    am to play the role of citizen well, I must follow the laws, be active politically, defend the country as needed,
    respect fellow citizens, etc. Therefore, it is not difficult to derive an extensive, robust system of ethics from the
    duties that must be fulfilled, based on our relationships.

     MAKE THE CONNECTION

    If you have studied Confucianism, you may notice that Confucius made a similar connection between

    ethics and our natural duties.

    Stoicism is a philosophical way of life that focuses on what is in our power, while remaining impassive

    towards what is not. Although this can be difficult to put into practice, Stoicism helps us to minimize

    desire in general, but especially the desire to seek benefit through external things. Stoicism also

    maintains that that (dis)value exists in judgment, not in the world.

     ATTRIBUTIONS

    Image of Epictetus | License: Public Domain

    Epictetus dialogue | Author: Retrieved from Project Gutenberg | License: Public Domain

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 130

    https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Epictetus#/media/File:Epicteti_Enchiridion_Latinis_versibus_adumbratum_(Oxford_1715)_frontispiece

    https://www.gutenberg.org/files/10661/10661-h/10661-h.htm

    Philosophical Analysis as a Way of Life
    by Sophia Tutorial

    In this tutorial, we will pull together some of the essential threads of this course, which have been

    taught to us by some of the greatest thinkers in history:

    the value of the pursuit of truth, especially in answering the big questions: “What is the nature of

    reality?” “What can we know?” “What is right?”

    the use of truth to develop a worldview, and then acting according to belief

    This tutorial examines the relationship of philosophy to the way in which we live our lives, in three

    parts:

    1. The Pursuit of Truth

    2. Philosophical Worldviews

    3. Acting According to Belief

    1. The Pursuit of Truth

    Recall that philosophy involves pursuit of the truth. The implicit assumption is that truth has value, that it is
    worth knowing. While the immediate reaction may be to say, “of course truth has value,” this is a superficial
    response.

    Philosophers maintain that it is always better to know. But is this what we believe? Do you want to know
    whether your spouse of ten years cheated on you once, several years ago? Perhaps all that knowing this truth
    can do is cause harm. Consider Socrates’ requirement that we examine all of our beliefs. How eager are you
    to discover that you are wrong? If you believe that a right to own guns reduces crime and/or makes you safer,
    how willing are you to perform the objective research necessary to determine whether your beliefs are
    correct? Are you willing to try your best to prove yourself wrong?

    The requirement to value truth is also a requirement to reject bias. If all of our beliefs are subject to scrutiny,
    then no belief is sacred. Consider the advantage in this requirement. There are two possibilities: your strong
    belief will be proven correct, or incorrect.

    If your belief is found to be incorrect, you may be upset for a time, but ultimately, it is better to know that you
    were wrong. For example, you will no longer foolishly defend a falsehood in conversations with others. Your
    improved knowledge of the world will enable you to better navigate it. You will be less biased, and more
    understanding.

    If, however, your belief turns out to be correct, it is no longer only your opinion, but genuine knowledge. You
    not only know that it is true, but you also know why it is true. This enables you to defend it properly, and
    enriches your life as a result of your close examination of the belief. Meeting the Socratic challenge is a win-

    WHAT’S COVERED

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 131

    win.

    Note the role of logic, reason, and reasoning in the search for truth. They are the tools and methods of
    philosophy. Reason discovers truth, and resists bias and emotion.

    2. Philosophical Worldviews

    One of the unique aspects of the pursuit of philosophy is that we are its subject and object. As subjects, we
    are the ones doing the thinking. With respect to the really big questions, however, we are usually among the
    objects studied as well. For example, in pursuing ethics, we determine how a person ought to act. That also
    entails how we ought to act. If, while investigating the metaphysics of free will, we conclude that free will is an
    illusion and the will is determined, our conclusion includes each of our wills. If we determine that there are no
    supernatural entities, then we have also confirmed that our deaths will be the end of our existence.

    By practicing philosophy — by trying to figure out what is true about the world — we place ourselves in the
    world, as part of the system rather than outside of it. Why is this an advantage? In addition to the benefits of
    pursuing truth listed above, it forces us to be consistent.

     EXAMPLE If I determine that it is morally wrong to text and drive, my determination includes me.
    People believe that it is unsafe to text and drive, and studies show that it causes more accidents (and

    fatalities) than drunk driving. Most people know this. However, many of the same people often think,

    “it is unsafe for others to text and drive. I, however, do it carefully, so I’ll do it now.” Do you know who

    else has reasoned that way? Everyone who has ever caused an accident by texting and driving. No

    one thinks, “I may get myself or someone else killed, but I really need to type LOL now, instead of ten

    minutes from now.” Philosophy places you inside this system, rather than on the outside looking in. In

    so doing, it reveals inconsistent thinking. You cannot be an exception to the rule.

    3. Acting According to Belief

    This leads us to the last major thread of philosophical thinking: acting according to belief. As the life of
    Socrates illustrates, the philosopher can’t just talk the talk, but must walk the walk as well.

    Philosophy entails the pursuit of truth, including truth in ethics. Therefore, philosophers hold beliefs about
    what is true with respect to right and wrong, and regarding how one should act. Remember that philosophers
    do not just have opinions on these matters. Their opinions have been dissected and analyzed. If they still hold
    a belief following that process, they not only believe it but know it. They hold it with a higher degree of
    certainty than that with which an unexamined belief is held. If you are relatively certain that something is the
    right thing to do, you are less likely to act on it than if you are very certain that it is the right thing to do. This is
    especially true when the action (i.e., the thing to be done) is demanding.

     EXAMPLE Imagine a dangerous situation, such as one that involves an active shooter. Being
    somewhat sure that an action that puts you in danger is the right thing to do is unlikely to make you

    act. But knowing for certain what is right to do in a situation is more likely to cause you to take action.

    Knowing what is right, rather than merely believing what is right, leads to acting according to belief. By
    thinking things through carefully, one will be more aware of times when one acts in ways that are inconsistent
    with beliefs. For example, most of us believe that we have a moral obligation to the next generation. However,
    we often don’t act accordingly.

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 132

     THINK ABOUT IT

    Do you believe that we have a moral obligation to our children? If you do, do you act in accordance with

    that belief? As an exercise in critical thinking, think of five ways in which you do not act according to this

    belief.
     HINT

    Consider these questions while thinking of ways in which you do NOT act according to the belief that we

    have a moral obligation to our children: Do you recycle? Even when you are on vacation? Do you take

    public transportation when it is available? Do you drive a fuel-efficient vehicle? Do you avoid pressing the

    “wheelchair-accessible” button to open the door when you don’t need it? Do you write to your

    congresspersons, encouraging them to support future-friendly policies? Do you watch sports that involve

    the use of huge amounts of gasoline?

    Most of us hold beliefs, but because we have not examined those beliefs beyond a superficial level, we don’t
    act according to them. However, not every philosopher is Socrates. No one is perfectly rational, or perfectly
    objective, and no one acts in perfect accordance with his or her beliefs. Philosophy enables us to maximize
    rationality, minimize bias, and increase consistency of thought and action.

    The pursuit of philosophy is not only an academic discipline. It should also make us better people.

    Pursuing truth and using reason to examine our beliefs are activities that have value, as do

    developing a worldview and acting according to belief. All of these skills are honed and leveraged

    when philosophy is properly pursued.

    SUMMARY

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 133

    Terms to Know

    ArgumentArgument

    A group of statements containing both a factual claim or claims and an inferential claim or

    claims

    CogentCogent

    An inductively strong argument in which all premises are true

    ConclusionConclusion

    A statement that is intended to be supported by the premises of an argument

    CosmologyCosmology

    The branch of philosophy that treats the universe in its totality

    DeductiveDeductive

    An argument whose inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty

    Deductive ArgumentDeductive Argument

    A type of argument in which the inferential claim is a claim of logical certainty

    DialecticDialectic

    A discourse between two or more people of opposing viewpoints, the ultimate goal of

    which is to discover the truth of the matter through reasoning

    EpistemologyEpistemology

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of knowledge and the

    methodologies that attain it

    EssenceEssence

    What makes a thing what it is

    EthicsEthics

    The branch of philosophy that analyzes and defends concepts of value and thereby seeks

    to determine right and wrong

    Factual ClaimFactual Claim

    A claim that some fact or facts obtained in the world is true

    HylomorphismHylomorphism

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 134

    The metaphysical theory that posits being as a union of form and matter

    InductiveInductive

    An argument whose inferential claim is a claim less than logical certainty

    Inductive ArgumentInductive Argument

    An argument in which the inferential claim is of less than logical certainty

    Inferential ClaimInferential Claim

    A claim that the premises support the conclusion

    InvalidInvalid

    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) do not logically guarantee their conclusion

    Logical CertaintyLogical Certainty

    A state in which it is inconceivable that the conclusion is not supported by the premises

    MetaphysicsMetaphysics

    The branch of philosophy that seeks to uncover and describe the ultimate nature of reality

    Natural PhilosophyNatural Philosophy

    The branch of philosophy that treats nature and the universe

    Necessary ConditionNecessary Condition

    “X” is a Necessary Condition for “Y” if membership in “X” is logically required for

    membership in “Y.”

    OntologyOntology

    The branch of metaphysics that examines the nature of being

    ParadoxParadox

    When seemingly reasonable assumptions lead to either a contradiction or an absurdity

    ParticularParticular

    A concrete, extant entity

    Philosophical AtomPhilosophical Atom

    An indivisible physical entity

    PhilosophyPhilosophy

    The pursuit of truths that cannot be wholly determined empirically

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 135

    Pre-SocraticsPre-Socratics

    A collective term for the group of Greek philosophers practicing philosophy before the

    influence of Socrates

    PremisePremise

    A statement presented for acceptance or rejection in an argument (without support) but that

    is intended to support a conclusion

    RationalismRationalism

    The epistemological view centering around the claim that humans can access certain

    conceptual truths independently of experience

    Socratic MethodSocratic Method

    The pedagogical method of teaching by asking questions to which the student knows the

    answer and thereby leading them to the truth being conveyed

    SoundSound

    A deductively valid argument in which all premises are true

    StrongStrong

    An inductive argument in which the premises render the conclusion probable

    Sufficient ConditionSufficient Condition

    “A” is a Sufficient Condition for “B” if membership in “A” logically guarantees membership in

    “B.”

    The Social ContractThe Social Contract

    An implicit agreement between the citizen and the state in which the citizen agrees to

    follow the law in exchange for all the benefits provided by the state

    UncogentUncogent

    An inductive argument that is not cogent

    UniversalUniversal

    An ontological category that is common to multiple particulars

    UnsoundUnsound

    A deductive argument that is not sound

    ValidValid

    A deductive argument in which the premise(s) logically guarantee their conclusion

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 136

    WeakWeak

    An inductive argument in which the premises do not render the conclusion probable

    ​EmpiricismEmpiricism
    The epistemological view centering around the claim that all knowledge is grounded in

    experience

    ​EssenceEssence
    What makes a thing what it is

    ​Inferential ClaimInferential Claim
    A claim that the premises support the conclusion

    ​SubstanceSubstance
    The “what it is” of any given thing

    © 2022 SOPHIA Learning, LLC. SOPHIA is a registered trademark of SOPHIA Learning, LLC. Page 137

      Unit 1 Tutorials: Great Philosophers
      INSIDE UNIT 1
      Introduction to Philosophy and the Pre-Socratics
      Socrates and Dialectic
      Plato and Aristotle
      Philosophy as a Way of Life
      What is Philosophy?
      1. The Beginning of Western Philosophy
      2. The Big Picture and a Contemporary Definition
      3. Some Major Branches of Philosophy
      Why Study Philosophy?
      1. Philosophy and Higher Education
      2. Benefits of the Philosophical Mindset
      3. Benefits Through the Sciences
      4. Benefit to Society
      5. Benefit to the Individual
      Cosmology and the First Philosophers
      1. Who Were the Pre-Socratic Philosophers?
      2. Some Pre-Socratic Philosophers and their Influential Ideas
      3. Intellectual Legacy of the Pre-Socratics
      The Atomistic Worldview
      1. Philosophy as a Worldview
      2. The Atomistic Worldview
      3. Atomistic Influence
      Parmenides and the Doctrine of Permanence
      1. The Turn to Metaphysics
      2. The Doctrine of the Unchanging One
      3. Zeno’s Paradoxes
      Heraclitus and the Doctrine of Impermanence
      1. Heraclitus on the Secular
      2. Heraclitean Flux and the Unity of Opposites
      3. Parmenides and Heraclitus
      Socrates: The Father of Western Philosophy
      1. Socrates, Patriarch of Western Thought
      2. Socrates, Seeker of Wisdom
      3. The First Step on the Path to Wisdom
      4. Socrates, A Martyr for Wisdom
      The Socratic Approach
      1. The Character of Socrates
      2. Dialectic
      3. The Socratic Method
      Example of the Socratic Method
      Introducing Arguments
      1. What is an Argument?
      2. The Basics of Evaluation
      Evaluation and Analysis of Arguments
      1. Deduction and Induction
      2. Evaluating Deductive Arguments
      3. Evaluating Inductive Arguments
      Evaluating an Argument in Action
      1. Deduction and Induction
      2. Evaluating Inductive and Deductive Arguments
      3. Practice Evaluating an Argument
      The Apology: A Defense of Philosophy
      1. The Apology
      2. Socrates’ Argued That He Did Not Corrupt the Youth
      3. The Unexamined Life Is Not Worth Living
      4. Death Is Nothing or Something
      The Apology — Socrates’ Arguments
      1. Review of The Apology
      2. Extracting Arguments from The Apology
      The Crito: The Duties of the Social Contract
      1. Whose Opinion Counts
      2. The Value of Human Life
      3. The Social Contract
      The Phaedo: The Death of Socrates
      1. A Philosopher Does Not Fear Death
      2. On Souls and Bodies
      Plato: An academic approach to concepts
      1. An Introduction to Plato
      2. Necessary and Sufficient Conditions
      3. The Euthyphro
      Plato’s Forms: The Objects of Knowledge
      1. The Platonic Conception of Knowledge
      2. Plato’s Forms as the Grounds of Knowledge
      Plato Forms: The Foundations of Being
      1. A Beginning Approximation
      2. Forms as the Grounds for Reality
      3. Participation and Particulars
      Applying Plato’s Metaphysics
      1. Review of Plato’s Doctrine of the Forms
      2. Forms as the Grounds of Knowledge
      3. Forms as the Grounds for Reality
      4. Participation and Particulars
      The Footnotes to Plato
      1. Philosophical Legacy
      2. Platonism in Mathematics
      3. Pursuing Truth Over Appearance
      Aristotle: The Dissection of Reality
      1. Aristotle’s Scientific Approach
      2. The Mathematician and the Biologist
      Aristotle on What There Is
      1. First Philosophy: Ontology
      2. Universals and Particulars
      3. Substance
      4. Aristotelian Essences
      5. Hylomorphism
      Plato vs. Aristotle: The Mathematician or the Biologist
      1. Some Important Similarities
      2. Their Main Points of Disagreement
      Aristotelianism: The Naturalistic Worldview
      1. Aristotle’s Intellectual Legacy: Naturalism
      2. Formal Logic
      Aristotle’s Highest Good
      1. The Function Argument
      2. Virtue Ethics
      3. The Doctrine of the Mean
      Applying Aristotle’s Ethics
      1. The Function Argument
      2. Virtue Ethics
      3. The Doctrine of the Mean
      4. Applying Aristotle’s Ethics
      Stoicism: The Ethics of Dispassion
      1. Focusing on What Is in Our Power
      2. How We Direct What Is in Our Power
      3. Ethics as a Role
      Philosophical Analysis as a Way of Life
      1. The Pursuit of Truth
      2. Philosophical Worldviews
      3. Acting According to Belief
      Terms to Know

    Calculate the price of your order

    550 words
    We'll send you the first draft for approval by September 11, 2018 at 10:52 AM
    Total price:
    $26
    The price is based on these factors:
    Academic level
    Number of pages
    Urgency
    Basic features
    • Free title page and bibliography
    • Unlimited revisions
    • Plagiarism-free guarantee
    • Money-back guarantee
    • 24/7 support
    On-demand options
    • Writer’s samples
    • Part-by-part delivery
    • Overnight delivery
    • Copies of used sources
    • Expert Proofreading
    Paper format
    • 275 words per page
    • 12 pt Arial/Times New Roman
    • Double line spacing
    • Any citation style (APA, MLA, Chicago/Turabian, Harvard)

    Our guarantees

    Delivering a high-quality product at a reasonable price is not enough anymore.
    That’s why we have developed 5 beneficial guarantees that will make your experience with our service enjoyable, easy, and safe.

    Money-back guarantee

    You have to be 100% sure of the quality of your product to give a money-back guarantee. This describes us perfectly. Make sure that this guarantee is totally transparent.

    Read more

    Zero-plagiarism guarantee

    Each paper is composed from scratch, according to your instructions. It is then checked by our plagiarism-detection software. There is no gap where plagiarism could squeeze in.

    Read more

    Free-revision policy

    Thanks to our free revisions, there is no way for you to be unsatisfied. We will work on your paper until you are completely happy with the result.

    Read more

    Confidentiality Guarantee

    Your email is safe, as we store it according to international data protection rules. Your bank details are secure, as we use only reliable payment systems.

    Read more

    Fair-cooperation guarantee

    By sending us your money, you buy the service we provide. Check out our terms and conditions if you prefer business talks to be laid out in official language.

    Read more

    24/7 Support

    Our specialists are always online to help you! We are available 24/7 via live chat, WhatsApp, and phone to answer questions, correct mistakes, or just address your academic fears.

    See our T&Cs
    Live Chat+1(978) 822-0999EmailWhatsApp

    Order your essay today and save 30% with the discount code ESSAYHELP