[63]
A Global Ethics for a
Globalized World
Anis Ahmad
Abstract
[Islamic ethics recognizes the role of intuitions, reason, customs and traditions, so
long as all these draw their legitimacy from the
Divine principles.
First and
foremost is the principle of coherence and unity
in life.
The second foundational
ethical principle is the practice of justice or equity, fairness, moderation, beauty
and balance in life. Then come respect, protection and promotion of life. The role
of reason and rational judgment in human decision-making is also important.
Protection of linage and dignity of genealogy, too, has relevance to people of the
entire world. These divinely inspired ethical
principles of Islam – transcending
finitude of human mind and experience – are not local, regional or national on
their origin. Their universality makes them globally
applicable, absolute and
pertinent in changed circumstances and environment. They are human friendly
and offer appreciable solutions to human problem in this age of globalization. –
Eds.]
A phobia generally stands for an obsession or an intense fear of
an object or a situation, like dog phobia, school phobia, blushing
phobia. Phobias are associated with almost any psychiatric condition
but are most often related with anxiety or obsessional states leading to
queer compulsive behavior.1 Islamophobia, a pegurative terminology,
used more frequently in post 9/11 era, refers to a reactionary
understanding of Islam and Muslims as dogmatic, fundamentalist, less
civilized, anti-rational, backward, destructive and terrorist. Islam is
perceived through the prism of news and media as a faith which
prescribes all those things which conflict and negate the western value
system and pose a threat to the western civilization and rationality.2
This conceptual and psychological problem of the western statesmen,
media experts, think tanks and researchers is not recent. Islam and
Muslims have been for centuries regarded rivals, enemies and
opponents of the west. For the past two centuries, at the least, a
political, intellectual and cultural encounter, between the west and the
Muslim world, has taken place. In this encounter the west was has been
on an offensive and the Muslim world took mostly a defensive
approach. With the rise capitalist economy, secular political system and
liberal intellectual tradition in the west, the western imperialism
penetrated its political, economic and cultural colonialism deep in the
Muslim world. One symbol of it was that the official and commercial
language of the colonizer replaced the native languages. Consequently
in some Muslim lands (Algerian, Tunis, Morroco) French because
Prof. Dr. Anis Ahmad is a meritorious Professor and Vice Chancellor, Riphah
International University, Islamabad. He is also Editor of Quarterly Journal Maghrab
awr Islam (West & Islam), published by Institute of Policy Studies, Islamabad.
1 Ley, “Phobia,” 7.
2 Said, Covering Islam, 7.
Policy Perspectives
64
practically their first language and Arabic become secondary; In the
Pakistan sub-continent, Sudan, Malaysia, South Africa and Nigeria
whenever the British colonialism ruled, English because official
language. Similarly Italian and Dutch languages were popularized
among in Libya and Indonesia. Adoption of a foreign language had its
socio-cultural implication on the Muslim people. At the same time their
relationship of the colonizer and the colonized also persuaded the
colonizer to understand the mind of the colonized and take necessary
measures to keep the colonizer subjugated. In order to understand and
control the colonized, imperialists tried to learn about the native
languages and cultures. This persuaded the British, French, Italian and
Dutch, to create centers for study of the Orient with focuses on study of
language and culture of the natives. They also trained a generation of
native scholars who subscribed to the western mind-set, research
methodology and its basic assumptions.
All known civilizations have their distinct concepts of good and
bad. Even those considered as “uncivilized” and heathens believe in
certain norms and values.
They generally respect their elders and love
children, they value honesty and disapprove cheating. Traditionally,
local customs and traditions, after continuous practice, evolve into
norms and laws. These norms and laws define for them what is good or
bad behavior. When ethical behavior is considered an obligation and
duty, it is called deontological ethics. Furthermore while determining
right or wrong, one may take up an objective or subjective approach.
Those who think good and right can be known like natural objects, or
that right and wrong can be empirically verified are called ethical
naturalists. While those who think right or wrong are a matter of
emotions, or attitude of a group, are termed emotivists. Those who
hold to non-cognitivism and think that attitudes of a group determine
ethicality or non-ethicality of a judgment are called ethical relativists.
The word ethics [ethickos in Greek, from ethos meaning custom
or usage] as a technical term also refers to morals and character.
Moralis was used by Cicero, who considered it the equivalent of the
ethikos of Aristotle with both referring to practical activity3. Ethical
behavior in general means good conduct, acting with a sense of right
and wrong, good and bad, and virtue and evil. Philosophers classify
ethics in various categories, for example Normative ethics deals with
“building systems designed to provide guidance in making decisions
concerning good and evil, right and wrong…”4.
With these preliminary observations on the meaning of the
term, we may look briefly on the axiological and teleological aspects of
ethical behavior. The axiological or value aspect subsumes that ethical
behavior is to be considered good. The latter simply means that the
3 Reese, Dictionary of Philosophy, 156.
4 Ibid, 156.
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
65
ultimate objective and purpose of an action should be achievement of
good. In either case western and eastern ethical thought consider social
consensus, at a given time, as the source of legitimacy of an ethical
act. Though certain ethical values apparently carry universality e.g.
truth, the question, what is truth as such, whether truth is practiced for
the sake of truth, or to avoid a personal harm, or for the collective
benefit of a society, can be approached from different perspectives.
In Western thought Bishop Joseph Butler (1692-1752 C.E.) held
that a person‟s conscience, when neither polluted nor subverted or
deranged intuitively, makes ethical judgments. Immanuel Kant (1724-
1804 C.E.) is known for his taking law as the basis of ethics; therefore
here ethical behavior, for him, is a matter of a categorical imperative.
Jeremy Bentham (1748-1832 C.E.) considered the greatest good of the
greatest number of the people as the goal of ethics. Herbert Spencer
(1820-1903 C.E.) evolved the concept of evolutionary utilitarianism.
Edward A. Westermarck (1862-1939 C.E.) pleaded the view of ethical
relativism thus considering ethical systems as a reflection of social
conditions. While William of Ockham (1290-1349 C.E.) regarded ethics
as having religious origin in the will of God where the Divine command
declares what is right or wrong.
Except for a handful of religious thinkers and philosophers,
those in the East or the West
consider intuition, collective
good or social conditions
responsible for considering an
act good and ethical or bad
and immoral. Nevertheless
certain concepts such as
justice, beneficence and non-
malfeasance are commonly
agreed as basic ethical
principles in the West. Islamic
ethics on the contrary draws
its legitimacy from Divine
revelation or Wah}ī. The Qur‟ān and the Prophetic Sunnah provide
universal ethical principles with specific instructions on what is good,
therefore permissible and allowed (h}alāl), what is desirable (mubāh})
and what is bad and impermissible (h}arām) as well as what is disliked
(makrūh).
These two comprehensive terms, h}alal and h}aram cover all
possible areas of human activity wherein one exercises ethical
judgment, and thus acts morally or immorally. Ethical boundaries
(h}udūd) are drawn to indicate areas to be avoided. A vast area of
mubāh} also exists where under general universal Divine principles,
Maqās}id al-Sharī‘ah or objectives of the Divine law, individual and
collective rational, logical and syllogistic reasoning (ijtihād) leads to
judgments and positions on emerging bio-medical and ethical
issues.
All known civilizations have their
distinct concepts of good and bad.
Even those considered as
“uncivilized” also believe in
certain norms and values.
Policy Perspectives
66
The basic difference between the Eastern and Western ethical
philosophy, and the Islamic ethical paradigm can be illustrated with the
help of a simple diagram.
Evolution of Ethical Values in the East
and the West
Ethical Norms
and values
Social Habits
and Behavior
Local Customs
and Traditions
Sociologist, anthropologists and historians of culture trace origin of
ethical values of a people in their physical environment. With the
change in space and time, values and norms are also expected to
change. The norms and values of a pre-industrial society and a post-
modernist society are not expected to be similar. Social, economic and
political evolution is supposed to cause basic changes in the value
system of a people who go through this process. Values and norms,
therefore, are considered relative to socio-economic change. Truth,
beauty and justice are, therefore not absolute but subject to
environmental change and evolution. Man is supposed to adjust his
behavior and conduct accordingly.
Islamic ethics recognizes the role of intuitions, reason, customs
and traditions, so long as all these draw their legitimacy from the
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
67
Divine principles of Sharī‘ah. No customs or traditions contrary to the
principles of Sharī‘ah can serve as the basis of social, economic,
political, legal and cultural policies and practices. Social development
and progress is subservient to Sharī‘ah. Divine legislation (Sharī‘ah, in
the strict sense of the word) is neither a product of social evolution nor
particular to a place, people, society or historical context. Its principles
are operational in all seasons and in a variety of human conditions.
Islamic ethics is founded on divine principles of sharī‘ah (the
maqās}id) which can be summarized as follows: First and foremost is
the principle of coherence and unity in life (tawh}īd). It simply means
that human behavior has to be coherent, unified and not contradictory
and incoherent. If it is ethical to respect human life, the same principle
should be observed when a person deals with his friends or adversaries.
Justice, truth and thankfulness should not be selective. If a person
declares that Allah is the Ultimate Authority in the universe, then His
directions and orders should be followed not only in the month of
Ramadan and in the masjid or within the boundaries of the Ka‘bah, but
even when a person is in the farthest corner of the world one should
observe Allah‟s directions in one‟s personal life, in economic activities,
social transactions, as well as in political decision making. Unity in life
or tawh}īd in practice, therefore, is a value and norm not particular to a
place, time or people.
If a comparison is made with Confucianism for example, one
finds that in Confucianism (founded by Confucius: 551-479 B.C.E.),
there is great emphasis on the noble person (chuntzu). The noble
person is expected to observe
certain values like humanity,
benevolence and compassion
(jen); righteousness (yi), filial
piety (xiao) and acting
according to “rules of
propriety” in the most
appropriate manner, or
observing ritual and ceremony
(li).
Jin or human
heartedness and yi or
righteousness together build a person of high moral quality5.
Righteousness and human heartedness in Confucianism are not for the
sake of any utilitarian end. Righteousness has to be for the sake of
righteousness. This reminds us of the Kantian categorical imperative, or
following ethics as a legal obligation. Confucianism does not accept
ethical relativism. In other words, ethical behavior and a righteous
person stand for “principled morality”.
5 Yu-Lan, The Spirit of Chinese Philosophy, 10-12.
Islamic ethics recognizes the role
of intuition, reason, customs and
traditions, so long as all these
draw their legitimacy from the
Divine principles.
Policy Perspectives
68
The Confucian term li is often translated as “ritual” or
“sacrifice”. The fact of the matter is that it stands for more than doing a
ritual in the prescribed manner. Confucius, in response to one of his
students, is reported to have said: “in funerals and ceremonies of
mourning, it is better that the mourners feel true grief, than that they
be meticulously correct in every ceremonial detail.”6 Ethics in practice
appears a major concern of Confucianism. It also indicates that ethical
consciousness and a desire for ethical and moral conduct and behavior
is a universal phenomenon.
Thus according to the Islamic worldview, ethical and moral
behavior (taqwa, ‘amal-s}āleh), observing what is essentially good
(ma‘rūf) and virtue (birr) is an obligation. Reasoned ethical judgment is
the basis of man‟s relation with his Creator as well as the basis of
serving and interacting with His Creation .Every human action is to be
based on ma‘rūf and taqwa, which are the measurable manifestations
of tawhid or unity in life. Man is neither an economic entity nor a social
animal, but an ethical being. Allah informed the angels before the
creation of the first human couple that He was going to create His
khalīfah, vicegerent or deputy, on earth. Allah did not say a “social
animal” or an “economic man” or a “shadow of god/monarch” or one
“obsessed with libido” was going to be created. khalīfah conceptually
means a person who acts ethically and responsibly. Therefore Man in
the light of the Qur‟ān is essentially an ethical being.
This realization of the unity in life, is the first condition for being
a believer in Islam and this principle has global application. Hence not
only for a Muslim but also equally for a Buddhist, Confucian, a
Christian, or a Hindu it is important to liberate oneself from
contradictions in conduct and
behavior. Specifically for a
Muslim observance of one and
the same ethical standards is
a pre-requisite for Īmān or
faith. An authentic Prophetic
h}adīth states:
“It is reported on the
authority of Anas b. Malik that
the Prophet (May peace and
blessings be upon him)
observed: one amongst you
believes (truly) till one likes
for his brother or for his neighbor that which he loves for himself.” 7
The Qur‟ān in several places underscores unity in action or unity
in behavior and profession as the key to ethical and moral conduct.
6 Creel, Chinese Thought from Confucius to Mao Tse-tung, 33.
7 Saheeh Muslim. Book 1. Hadīth no. 72.
The principle of coherence and
unity in life is the first and
foremost. It simply means that
human behavior has to be
coherent, unified and not
contradictory and incoherent.
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
69
“O Believers! Why do you say something which you
do not do? It is very hateful in the sight of Allah that
you say something which you do not do.” 8
Unity in life as the first core teaching of Islam also happens to
be the basis of what have been called objectives of the Sharī‘ah
(maqās}id al-Sharī‘ah). Since unity in life means elimination of dual
standards of ethics and morality and development of a holistic
personality, its applicability and relevance is not particular to be
Muslims. Needless to say the objective of sharī‘ah are essentially
objectives of humanity as such truly global. The Qur‟an invites the
whole of humanity to critically
examine human conduct and
behavior, and through the
application of tawh}īd, create
harmony, balance, coherence
and unity in human conduct and
social policy. This principle was
not a tribal, Arabian or Makkan
practice. It was revealed to the
Prophet that the Rabb or
Naurisher of the whole of
human community is Allah
alone, therefore He alone to be
taken as Transcendent creator
and sustainer of the whole universe and mankind. The Qur‟anic
terminology Allah is not an evolved form of ilah but proper and personal
name of Transcendent creator of mankind. Islamic law similarly was not
a matter of Arabian customs traditions assigned normativeness by
Islam. Islam cause to Islamize the Arabs and non-Arabs. It never
wanted to Arabize the non-Arabic speaking world community.
The second foundational ethical principle, and an important
objective of the Sharī‘ah is the practice of „adl (justice) or equity,
fairness, moderation, beauty and balance in life. ‘Adl (justice) is one of
the major attributes of Allah, for He is Most Just, Fair and
Compassionate to His creation. At the same time, it is the principle
operating in the cosmos, in the world of vegetation, in the animal
world, sea world as well as in humanity at large. The Qur‟ān refers to
the constitution of man regarding this principle:
“O man! What had lured you away from your
Gracious Rabb, Who created you, fashioned you,
proportioned you.”9
8 As-Saff:61:2-3.
9 Al-Infitaar: 82:6-7.
Second foundational ethical
principle, is the practice of
justice or equity, fairness,
moderation, beauty and balance
in life.
Policy Perspectives
70
In Islam ethical conduct and virtuous behavior (taqwa) is
directly linked with ‘adl:
“O Believers! Be steadfast for the sake of Allah, and
bear true witness, and let not the enmity of a people
incite you to do injustice; do justice; that is nearer to
piety….”10
‘Adl is a comprehensive term. It also includes the meaning of
excelling and transcending in ethical and moral conduct:
“Allah commands doing justice, doing good to others,
and giving to near relatives, and He forbids
indecency, wickedness, and rebellion: He admonishes
you so that you may take heed.”11
Though generally taken to mean legal right of a person, „adl has
much wider implications. At a personal level it means doing justice to
one‟s own self by being moderate and balanced in behavior. Therefore
if a person over sleeps or does not sleep at all, starves in order to
increase spirituality or to lose weight, or on the contrary, overeats and
keeps on gaining weight, in both cases, he commits z}ulm or injustice
to his own self. „Adl is to be realized at the level of family. The h}adīth
of the Prophet specifies that one‟s body has a right on person similarly
his wife has a right on a person.
One who is kind, loving, caring and
compassionate toward family is
regarded by the Prophet a true
Muslim. „Adl has to be the basis of
society.
A human society may
survive despite less food but no
society can survive without „adl or
fairness and
justice.
„Adl in
economic matters means an
economic order with oppressions,
monopoly and unfair distribution of
wealth. It also demands political
freedom and right to association, difference of opinions, criticism and
right to elect most suitable person for public position. If a political
system does not provide freedom of speech, respect for difference of
opinion and practice of human rights it cannot be called a just political
order. The capitalist world order, because of its oppressive nature
cannot be called an „adil order. It remains a z}alim order so long it does
not provide the due share of the laborer.
10 Al-Ma’idah: 5:8.
11 An-Nah}l: 16:90.
A human society may
survive despite less food
but no society can survive
without fairness and
justice.
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
71
‘Adl in a medical context means professional excellence in one‟s
area of competence and specialization, for the simple reason that ‘adl
means doing a thing at its best. It implies devoting full attention to the
patient in order to fully understand the problem and coming up with the
best possible remedy. It also means prescribing a quality medicine with
least financial burden on the patient, and avoiding unnecessary
financial burden on a patient by prescribing irrelevant laboratory tests
or high cost medicine when a less costly medicine can do the same.
Thus if in one single area proper attention is not paid, it is deviation
from the path of ‘adl.
The third vital global ethical principle and one of the objective of
the Sharī‘ah is respect, protection and promotion of life. It too has
wider and vital implications for the whole of mankind. This principle is
drawn directly from the Qur‟ānic injunction that saving one human life
is like saving the whole of mankind, and destroying one single life,
unjustly, is like killing the whole of mankind.12 This Qur‟ānic injunction
makes it obligatory on every believing Muslim to avoid harming life or
killing, except when it is in return for committing manslaughter or
causing lawlessness in society.13
Since the word used in the Qur‟ān is nafs which means, self,
soul, individual human being, it is not particular to the Muslims or
people of a particular faith, creed or ethnicity. No individual or group of
human beings can be killed, or their life harmed without an ethical,
objective and legal justification. It also means that life when even in its
developmental stage is equally honorable and valuable. A fetus hence
has the same sanctity as a full-grown human being. Therefore any
things that can harm the fetus is also to be avoided in order to ensure
quality of life is not marginalized. For example if a female during
pregnancy uses alcoholic beverages, or drugs or even smokes,
medically all these are going to harm the fetus, and thus effect the
quality of life in future of a child yet to harm.
Not only this, but the principle has further serious implications
even for environmental policies. It is also directly relevant to the
manufacturing and production of pharmaceuticals. If the quality of
pharmaceuticals is not controlled, their use is bound to harm life.
This principle is also related to public policy on population. It
does not allow state to interfere in the bedroom of a person and impose
an embargo on childbirth, or allow abortion. These are only a few
serious ethical issue directly related to the principle of value of life.
12 “That whoever kills a person, except as a punishment for murder or mischief in the
land, it will be written in his book of deeds as if he had killed all the human beings,
and whoever will save a life shall be regarded as if he gave life to all the human
beings…” Al-Ma’idah:5:32.
13 Ibid.
Policy Perspectives
72
Obviously these are universal applications of this principle and not
confined to the followers of Islam.
The fourth major ethical principle relates to the role of reason
and rational judgment in human decision-making. The fact that human
beings should have reasoned judgments, and rise above emotional
behavior, blind desires and drives is a major concern of the Sharī‘ah.
Consequently Islam does not permit suspension of freedom of
judgment. An obvious example is, if a person gets addicted to drugs or
hooked to intoxicants, their use influences his personal and social
relations, freedom of will, as
well as personal integrity. In
Islam independence of reason
and rational judgment is a pre-
condition for all legal
transactions. The Qur‟ān
considers the use of intoxicants
immoral (fah}āsh). It is not only
sinful but also legally prohibited.
Modern medical research also
confirms the harmful effects of
drugs and intoxicants on the
mental health of people
irrespective of their race, color
or religion. However Islam‟s concern for reasoned and rational behavior
in personal and social life is not peculiar to Muslims. It‟s universal
values have global relevance to the conduct and behavior of all human
beings at a global level.
The fifth principle, protection of linage and dignity of genealogy,
too, has relevance to people of the entire world, irrespective of their
religion, race, color or language. It makes protection of genetic identity
and protection of lineage an ethical and legal obligation. The Islamic
social and legal system considers free mixing of sexes and pre-marital
conjugal relations immoral as well as unlawful. This has serious
implications for health sciences, social policy and legal system. This
global ethical principle deters a person from commercialization of the
human gene and also from the mixing of genes (such as in the case of
a surrogacy). This principle helps in preserving high standard of
morality in human society. It also discourages anonymity of the gene
and helps in preserving tradition of genetic tree.
This limit review of the objectives of Islamic shari‘ah indicates
that every principle has global relevance to ethical and moral conduct of
persons in a civilized society. The purpose of this brief resume of
universal and foundational Islamic ethical and moral principles, has
been first to dispel the impression that Islamic ethics is particular to the
Muslims; second to understand the objectives and origin of these
values in the Divine guidance and third, to find out how viable they are
in the contemporary world.
Islamic ethical principles
clearly differentiate between a
reasoned and rational judgment
and a judgment based on the
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
73
The principles and the objectives of the Sharī‘ah, as mentioned
above, are practically the objectives of humanity. Many of the
biological, emotional or intellectual and social needs of man have been
interpreted in western social sciences as blind drives, instincts and
animal desires; Islamic ethical principles clearly differentiate between a
reasoned and rational judgment and a judgment based on the so-called
blind drives. For instance, some human actions may have apparent
similarity but they may be poles apart. A person may take a loan from
a bank on a mutually agreed interest rate to establish an industry.
Another person may also borrow money from a bank on the Islamic
ethical principles of profit sharing, and with no interest at all. Both
appear industrial loans yet essentially one supports the capitalistic
exploitative system, while the other encourages commercial and
industrial growth without indulging in interest or usury, totally
prohibited by Islam.
Legitimacy of Ethical Values
Before concluding, it may also be appropriate to add a few words on
the legitimacy of Islamic ethical principles. It may be asked, “do these
principles draw their legitimacy from their customary practice, or draw
their power and authority from somewhere else?
Ethical behavior in all walks of life is a major concern of Islam.
However it does not leave ethical judgment to the personal like or
dislike, or to the greatest good of the largest number of people, though
one of the maxims of the Sharī‘ah directly refers to public good or
maslaha ‘amah. The origin and legitimacy of values in the Islamic world
view resides in Divine revelation (wah}ī). Revelation or kalaam/speech
of Allah should not be confused with inspiration or intuition, which is a
subjective phenomenon. Revelation, wah}ī or kalaam of Allah is
knowledge which comes from beyond and therefore, it is not subjective
but objective. Being the spoken word of Allah, makes it transcend the
finitude of space and time. Though revealed in the Arabic language, it
addresses the whole of humanity (an-Naas). It uses Arabic language
only incidentally, for clarity in communication. The purpose of
revelation in Arabic was to Islamize the Arabs and not to arabize those
who enter in to the fold of Islam.
Islamic values by their very nature are universal and globally
applicable. None of the ethical norms have their roots in local or
Arabian customs and traditions. These are not particularistic, temporal
values that normally change with the passage of time. These are
universal values having their roots in the Divine, universalistic
revelation. The principle of ‘adl discussed above, is not particular to a
race, color, groups or a specific region, or period of history. Respect
and promotion of life is also a universal value. Similarly honesty,
fairness, truth are neither Eastern nor Western, these are universally
recognized applied values.
Policy Perspectives
74
The purpose of these universal Islamic values is to help human
beings develop a responsible vision of life. It is a gross underestimation
to consider life a sport, a moment of
pleasure. Life has meaning, an
ethics by which it has to be lived,
fashioned and organized.
The Islamic world view, as pointed out earlier looks on human
life holistically. It advocates integration and cohesion in life, and avoids
compartmentalization and fragmentation. Tawh}īd or unity in life is
created when one single standard is observed in private and public life
and all human actions are motivated only by one single concern i.e how
to gain Allah‟s pleasure by observing an ethical and responsible life.
Islamic ethics can be summarized in only two points. First and
foremost, is observance of the rights of the Creator; living an ethical
life with full awareness of accountability on the day of Judgment as well
as in this world. Secondly, to fulfill obligations towards other human
beings not for any reward, recognition or compensation, but simply
because it pleases Allah. Serving humanity for the sake of humanity
may be a good cause but what makes serving humanity an ‘ibadah or
worship is serving Allah‟s servants for His sake, and not for any worldly
recognition by winning an excellent reward.
Islamic ethics in practice helps in binding the balanced,
responsible, receptive and proactive personality of a professional. The
primary Islamic ethical values briefly discussed above allow anyone
who follows these in their letter and spirit to reflect as a global citizen,
who transcends above discriminations of color, race, language or
religion. The Qur‟ān invites the entire humanity to adopt the path of
ethical living and practice, in order to make society peaceful, orderly
and responsive to needs of
the community. The Muslim
community is defined in the
Qur‟ān as the community of
ethically motivated persons
(khayra-ummah) or the
community of the middle
path (ummatan-wast}ān)
that does not go out of
balance and proportion and
implements good or ma‘ruf.
Ethically responsible
behavior means a behavior that follows universal ethical norms and
laws and resists all immediate temptations. The strength of character
simply means strict observance of principles a person claims to
subscribe to. Thus Islamic professional ethics guides a professional in
all situations where an ethical judgment is to be made, in medical
treatment as well as in business transactions, and administrative
issues.
It is a gross underestimation to
consider life a sport, a moment of
pleasure. Life has meaning, an
ethics by which it has to be lived,
fashioned and organized.
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
75
Islamic ethics in practice encompasses not only formally known
social work but practically every action a human takes in society.
Islamic professional or work ethics is not confined to customer
satisfaction. A believer has to act ethically in personal as well as social,
financial, political and cultural matters. Change in space and time does
not lead to any change in ethical and moral standards and behavior.
Quality assurance as an ethical obligation is one of the major concerns
of the Qur‟ān. The general
principles of quality
assurance are mentioned at
several places in a variety
of context.
“Weigh with even
scales, and do not
cheat your fellow
men of what is
rightfully theirs…”14
It is further
elaborated when the Qur‟ān directs, that while delivering goods or
products one should not observe dual standards:
“Woe to those who defraud, who when, they take by
measure from men, take the full measure, but when
they give by measure or by weight to others, they
give less than due.”15
A medical practitioner for example, when he gets his
compensation in terms of consultation fee, it is his or her ethical
obligation to advice a patient with full responsibility, care and sense of
accountability to Allah. The same applies to a teacher, who must deliver
knowledge with full honesty, responsibility and fairness without hiding
the truth, or manipulation of facts. It equally applies to students and
researchers who do their utmost in seeking knowledge and truth, and
produce knowledge while avoiding plagiarism and other unfair means in
research.
14 Ash-Shū’ara:26:182-183.
15 Al-Mut}affifīn:83:1-3.
Islamic ethics in practice
encompasses not only formally
known social work but practically
every action a human takes in
society.
Policy Perspectives
76
The divinely inspired ethical principles transcend finitude of
humans mind and
experience. These are not
local, regional or national
on their origin, they are
not for a people with a
specific denomination
either. Their universality
makes them globally
applicable, absolute and
applicable in changed
circumstances and
environment. They are
human friendly but not a
result of human intellectual
intervention and offer
appreciable solutions to
human problem in this age
of globalization.
Wamā tawfīqī illa, bi Allah, wa Allahu A’lamu bi als}awāb.
The divinely inspired ethical
principles of Islam – transcending
finitude of human mind and
experience – are not local, regional
or national in their origin. Their
universality makes them globally
applicable, absolute and pertinent in
changed circumstances.
A Global Ethics for a Globalized World
77
References:
Creel, H.G. Chinese Thought from Confucius to Mao Tse-tung. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1953.
Ley, P. “Phobia.” in Encyclopedia of Psychology. edited by H.J. Eysenck,
et al, Vol III. New York, The Seabury Press, 1972.
Reese, William. Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion Eastern and
Western Thought. New Jersey: Huamanties Press, 1980.
Said, Edward W. Covering Islam, How Media and the Experts Determine
How We See the Rest of the World. New York: Panthoos Book,
1981.
Yu-Lan, Fung. The Spirit of Chinese Philosophy. Boston: Beacon Press,
1947.
Reproduced with permission of the copyright owner. Further reproduction prohibited without
permission.
14 Social Alternatives Vol. 34 No. 1, 2015
Classical Stoicism and the Birth of a Global
Ethics: Cosmopolitan Duties in a
World of Local Loyalties
Lisa hiLL
Do I have responsibilities to strangers and, if so, why? Is a global ethics possible in the absence
of supra-national institutions? The responses of the classical Stoics to these questions directly
influenced modern conceptions of global citizenship and contemporary understandings of our
duties to others. This paper explores the Stoic rationale for a cosmopolitan ethic that makes
significant moral demands on its practitioners. It also uniquely addresses the objection that a
global ethics is impractical in the absence of supra-national institutions and law.
themed artiCLe
What do we owe to strangers and why? Is a global
ethics possible in the face of national boundaries?
What should we do when bad governments order us to
mistreat strangers or the weak? These were just some
of the questions to which the ancient Stoics applied
themselves. Their answers, which emphasised the
equal worth and inherent dignity of every human being,
were to reverberate throughout the Western political
tradition and directly influence modern conceptions of
global citizenship. Yet, how the Stoics arrived at their
cosmopolitanism is often imperfectly understood, hence
the first part of the discussion. Objections that their ideas
were too utopian to be practically useful also reflect
misunderstandings about Stoicism, hence the second
part of the paper.
I begin by exploring the Stoic rationale for the cosmopolis,
the world state, after which I address the objection that
a global ethics is impractical in the absence of supra-
national institutions and law. Well aware that local
loyalties and the jealousy of sovereign states towards
their own jurisdictional authority would represent
significant obstacles to the practice of a global ethic, the
Stoics insisted that the cosmopolis could still be brought
into existence by those who unilaterally obeyed the laws
of ‘reason’ even within the confines of national borders
and in the face of hostile local institutions.
Background
Inspired by the teaching of Socrates and Diogenes of
Sinope (Diogenes the Cynic), Stoicism was founded
at Athens by Zeno of Citium in around 300 BCE and
was influential throughout the Greco-Roman world
until around 200 CE.1 Its teachings were transmitted
to later generations largely through the surviving Latin
writings of Cicero, Seneca, Epictetus, C. Musonius
Rufus and Marcus Aurelius, as well as the Greek
author Diogenes Laertius via his Lives and Opinions of
Eminent Philosophers. The Stoics not only influenced
later generations; they were extremely influential in their
own time. From the outset, Stoicism was a distinctive
voice in intellectual life, from the Early Stoa in the fourth
and third centuries BCE, the Middle Stoa in the second
and first centuries BCE, to Late Stoicism in the first
and second centuries CE (and beyond) when Stoicism,
having spread to Rome and captivated many important
public figures, was at the height of its influence.
Stoic Cosmopolitanism and Global Ethics
The idea that we should condition ourselves to regard
everyone as being of equal value and concern is at
the heart of Stoic cosmopolitanism. The Stoics were
not alone in promoting this ideal: the Cynics were also
cosmopolitan. But it was the Stoics – the dominant
and most influential of the Hellenistic schools – who
systematised and popularised the concept of the
oikoumene, or world state, the human world as a
single, integrated city of natural siblings. Impartiality,
universalism and egalitarianism were at the heart of
this idea.
The Stoic challenge to particularism was extremely
subversive for a time when racism, classism, sexism
and the systematic mistreatment of non-citizens was
a matter of course. It was hardly thought controversial,
for example, that Aristotle (1943: IV. 775a. 5-15) should
declare that ‘in human beings the male is much better
in its nature than the female’ and that ‘we should look
upon the female state as being … a deformity’. Similarly,
ethnic prejudice was the norm rather than the exception
in antiquity. The complacent xenophobia and racism
of Demosthenes’s 341 BCE diatribe against Philip of
Social Alternatives Vol. 34 No 1, 2015 15
Macedon would not have raised a single eyebrow in his
Greek audience:
[H]e is not only no Greek, nor related to the
Greeks, but not even a barbarian from any place
that can be named with honour, but a pestilent
knave from Macedonia, whence it was never yet
possible to buy a decent slave (Demosthenes,
1926: 31).
Reversing these kinds of attitudes (and the behaviour
attendant on them) was the self-appointed task of the
Stoic philosophers.
The Cosmopolitan Ideal, Social Distance and Care
for Strangers
The first step towards promoting a universalistic ethic
entailed changing our whole way of thinking about
social distance. The Stoics were well aware that most
people tend to imagine their primary, secondary and
tertiary duties to others as ranked geographically:
distance regulates the intensity of obligation and people
will normally give priority to themselves, intimates,
conspecifics, and compatriots (in roughly that order),
before strangers, foreigners and members of out-
groups. This view is what is commonly referred to as ‘the
common-sense priority thesis’ or the ‘common-sense’
view of global concerns. Hierocles, the second century
Stoic philosopher, introduces the image of concentric
circles to illustrate how we generally conceive of our
obligations to others:
Each one of us is … entirely encompassed by
many circles, some smaller, others larger, the
latter enclosing the former on the basis of their
different and unequal dispositions relative to each
other. The first and closest circle is the one which
a person has drawn as though around a centre,
his own mind. This circle encloses the body and
anything taken for the sake of the body … Next,
the second one further removed from the centre
but enclosing the first circle; this contains parents,
siblings, wife, and children. The third one has in it
uncles and aunts, grandparents, nephews, nieces,
and cousins. The next circle includes the other
relatives, and this is followed by the circle of local
residents, then the circle of fellow-tribesmen, next
that of fellow citizens, and then in the same way
the circle of people from neighboring towns, and
the circle of fellow-countrymen. The outermost
and largest circle, which encompasses all the
rest, is that of the whole human race (fragment
reproduced in Long and Sedley 1987: 1349).
But the Stoics wanted to radically change this way of
thinking and feeling about others. As Hierocles suggests,
we must first become aware of our own prejudices in
order to repudiate them and thereafter substitute them
with superior cosmopolitan mental habits:
Once all these [circles] have been surveyed, it
is the task of a well tempered man, in his proper
treatment of each group, to draw the circles
together somehow toward the centre, and to keep
zealously transferring those from the enclosing
circles into the enclosed ones (Hierocles fragment
in Long and Sedley 1987: 1/349).
Humanity must embark on a morally demanding
developmental journey that begins (quite naturally) with a
variable quality of attachment towards others, proceeding
to a state of invariable quality of attachment towards
the world at large. The Stoics did not aim to invert the
priority thesis (which would mean that the intensity of our
feelings would increase the further out we went); rather,
they strove for a sameness of feeling for all, regardless
of social distance. Impartiality was their ideal. To be self-
regarding and partial to intimates was not only contrary
to natural law; it was a sign of moral immaturity.
Why Do I Owe Strangers (and the Less Fortunate)
Anything?
What led the Stoics to this ambitious mission? The
answer originates in Stoic theology, which was devised
as a philosophy of defence in a troubled world and
a rival to the religion of the Olympian pantheon. The
Stoic emotional ideal was a combination of spiritual
calm (ataraxia) and resignation (apatheia) that were
to be cultivated in order to achieve happiness/human
flourishing (eudaimonia). The point of religion was to
bring order and tranquillity; something the official Greek
religion of the Olympian gods was quite obviously
incapable of achieving. This religion, with its capricious,
sex-crazed, ill-tempered and unpredictable gods who
meddled in human affairs from the heights of Mount
Olympus hardly inspired calm, let alone compassion.
Neither did its unending demands for propitiation and
sacrifice promote resignation. So the Stoics devised
a less disconcerting religion that spoke of an orderly
universe with no divine intervention whatsoever and
brought the gods not only closer to us, but into us;
no longer distant, terrifying others but, quite literally,
kindly insiders. ‘Reason’, the ‘mind-fire spirit’ existed as
intelligent matter, residing benignly in all life and impelling
it unconsciously and teleologically towards order and
rightness. Humans are not separate from God (or Gods)
but a part of ‘Him’: ‘the universe [is] one living being,
having one substance and one soul’ (Marcus Aurelius
1916: IV.40).
Because the Gods have given each human a particle of
God-like intellect (‘reason’), we have a natural kinship
both with God and with each other (Marcus Aurelius
1916: 12.26). As related parts of the same entity, and
16 Social Alternatives Vol. 34 No. 1, 2015
equally sharing in ‘reason’, we are natural equals on
earth with equal sagacious potential. According to
Cicero, everyone has the spark of reason and ‘there is no
difference in kind between man and man [it] is certainly
common to us all’ (Cicero 1988: I. 30). Seneca says that
the light of educated reason ‘shines for all’ regardless
of social location, which is, after all, merely a matter of
luck and social conditioning. As he quite sensibly points
out, ‘Socrates was no aristocrat. Cleanthes worked at
a well and served as a hired man watering a garden.
Philosophy did not find Plato already a nobleman; it made
him one’ (Seneca 2002: Ep. 44.3). Exclusive pedigrees
‘do not make the nobleman’; only ‘the soul … renders us
noble’ (Seneca 2002: Ep. 44.5). Everyone has the same
capacity for wisdom and virtue and everyone is equally
desirous of these things (Seneca 2002: Ep. 44.6).
True freedom comes from knowledge, from learning to
distinguish ‘between good and bad things’ (Seneca 2002:
Ep. 44.6). Being knowledgeable and therefore ‘good’ is
not just for ‘professional philosophers’. People do not
need to ‘wrap [themselves] up in a worn cloak … nor
grow long hair nor deviate from the ordinary practices
of the average man’ in order to enter the cosmopolis;
rather, admission is open to anyone who insists on using
their own right judgement, in simply ‘thinking out what
is man’s duty and meditating upon it’ (Musonius 1905:
Discourse 16). This is the route to both the moral and the
happy life: when we learn to live according to the natural
law of Zeus, and therefore our natural tendencies, we
are enabled to achieve inner tranquillity (Chrysippus in
Diogenes 1958: ‘Zeno’, VII. 88).2
Duties, Harm and Aid
The Stoics insisted that one of the things that allow
us to live virtuously in accordance with nature is the
correct performance of duties (Sorabji 1993: 134-157).
The virtuous agent is beneficent and just: justice is the
cardinal social virtue (‘the crowning glory of the virtues’)
and beneficence is closely ‘akin’ to it (Chrysippus cited
in Cicero 1990: I. 20). We should always strive to refrain
from harming others since the universal law forbids
it (Cicero 1990: 1. 149.153; Marcus Aurelius 1916:
9.1; Seneca 2002: Ep. 95.51-3). Indeed, ‘according to
[Nature’s] ruling, it is more wretched to commit than to
suffer injury’ (Seneca 2002: Ep. 95.52-3).
But the negative virtue of refraining from harm is not
enough: virtue must also be positive. It is natural for
human beings to aid others (Cicero 1961: III. 62). We
are duty-bound to meet the needs of our divine siblings
(Marcus Aurelius 1916: 11.4) and it is ‘Nature’s will
that we enter into a general interchange of acts of
kindness, by giving and receiving’ (Cicero 1990: I. 20).
The morally mature person knows that she must ‘live for
[her] neighbour’ as she lives for herself (Seneca 2002:
Ep. 48.3).
We have duties of justice, fairness and mutual aid to one
another and the needs of others imply a duty to meet
them: ‘Through [Nature’s] orders, let our hands be ready
for all that needs to be helped’ (Seneca 2002: Ep. 95.52-
3). Moral failure is epitomised by an ‘incapacity to extend
help’ (Epictetus 1989: Fragment 7, 4: 447). It is not only
neutral strangers who are entitled to our assistance, but
also our supposed enemies. Contrary to the ‘common
notion’ that ‘the despicable man is recognised by his
inability to harm his enemies … actually he is much more
easily recognised by his inability to help them’ (Musonius
1905: Fragment XLI). Clearly, the moral demands of the
cosmopolitan ethic are extremely high, requiring that we
treat impartially even the feared and hated. The need for
a high level of moral maturity is one of the reasons why
the Stoics placed so much emphasis on the desirability
of emotional self-control.
Universal Versus Positive, Local Law
The extirpation of passionate attachment and the
moderation of intense loyalties to conspecifics are basic
preconditions for a global ethics. Impartiality is the key
to Stoic egalitarianism: the wise person knows that the
laws governing her behaviour are the same for everyone
regardless of ethnicity, class, blood ties (Clark 1987:
65, 70), and gender (Hill 2001). Judgements about the
welfare of others are always unbiased: ‘persons’ are of
equal value and ends in themselves regardless of their
social location or proximity to us. Reason is common
and so too is law; hence ‘the whole race of mankind’
are ‘fellow-members of the world state’ (Marcus Aurelius
1916: 4.4; see also Epictetus 1989: I.9. 1-3; Cicero 1988:
I.23-31).
Cicero (1961: III.63) says that ‘the mere fact’ of our
‘common humanity’ not only inclines us, but also
‘requires’ that we feel ‘akin’ to one another. The
siblinghood of all rational creatures overrides any local
or emotional attachments because the ‘wise man’
knows that ‘every place is his country’ (Seneca 1970:
II, IX.7; see also Epictetus 1989: IV, 155-165). In order
to ‘guar[d]’ our own welfare we will subject ourselves
to God’s laws, ‘not the laws of Masurius and Cassius’.
When family members rule over others we ‘demolis[h] the
whole structure of civil society’ while putting compatriots
before ‘foreigners’ destroys ‘the universal brotherhood
of mankind’. If we refuse to recognise that foreigners
have the same ‘rights’3 as compatriots we utterly destroy
all ‘kindness, generosity, goodness and justice’ (Cicero
1990: 3. 27-8).
The rational agent will put the laws of Zeus before those
of ‘men’ whenever a conflict between them arises, even
when this imperils the wellbeing of the agent concerned,
as it so often did in the case of Stoic disciples. For
example, when in 60 CE Nero sent Rubellius into exile
to Asia Minor, Musonius went with him in a gesture of
solidarity, thereby casting suspicion on himself in the
Social Alternatives Vol. 34 No 1, 2015 17
eyes of the lethally dangerous Nero. Upon the death
of Rubellius, Musonius returned to Rome, where his
Stoic proselytising drew the further ire of Nero who
subsequently banished him to the remote island of
Gyaros. After Nero’s reign ended, Musonius returned
to Rome but was banished yet again by Vespasian on
account of his political activism.
Musonius thus practised what he preached. He taught
that it is virtuous to exercise nonviolent disobedience
in cases where an authority orders us to violate the
universal law. It is right to disobey an unlawful command
from any superior, be it father, magistrate, or master
because our allegiance – first and always – is to Zeus
and to ‘his’ commandment to do right. In fact, an act
is only disobedient when one has refused ‘to carry out
good and honourable and useful orders’ (Musonius 1905:
Discourse 16). Where the laws of God conflict with the
laws of ‘men’, natural law trumps positive law (Cicero
1988: II.11). As Epictetus (1989: 3.4-7) says: ‘if the good
is something different from the noble and the just, then
father and brother and country and all relationships
simply disappear’. All the Stoics agree on this point
and they directly influenced Kant’s views on the same
subject, namely, that the universal law ‘condemns any
violation that, should it be general, would undermine
human fellowship’ (Nussbaum 2000: 12).
Realist Objections
It is often suggested that cosmopolitanism in general –
and the idea of the world state in particular – is hard to
take seriously because it is practically impossible due
to the persistence of sovereign states and the localised
loyalties that accompany them. On this view, Stoic
cosmopolitanism necessarily involves the commitment
to a world state capable of enacting and enforcing
Stoic principles. However, the cosmopolis is not, strictly
speaking, a legal or constitutional entity (although, of
course, it can be): rather, it is, first and foremost, an
imaginary city, a state of mind, open to anyone capable
of recognising the inherent sanctity of others and who
evinces the Stoic virtues of sympatheia (social solidarity),
philanthropia or humanitas (benevolence), and clementia
(compassion). We become cosmopolites when we work
hard to look beyond surface appearances (Seneca 2002:
Ep. 44.6) and live in obedience to the laws of reason
and of nature, rather than the variable laws of a single
locality. These are the qualities that secure a person’s
membership of the cosmopolis and which also conjure
it into reality.
We are all capable of being cosmopolites. As Musonius
says, the mind is ‘free from all compulsion’ and is ‘in
its own power’; no one can ‘prevent you from using it
nor from thinking … nor from liking the good’ nor from
‘choosing’ the latter, for ‘in the very act of doing this’, you
become a cosmopolite (1905: Discourse 16). Sovereign
states and the citizens within them do not need formal,
supranational structures and legal frameworks to operate
as world citizens; they only need to begin acting as
though the world were a single city which, although
composed predominantly of strangers, is nevertheless
and inescapably one family of natural siblings. Everyone
can and should be a cosmopolite, even if this means
challenging the institutional authority of those who rule.
The fact that the cosmopolis is an imagined community
(albeit constituted by real moral agents committing real
acts of ‘reason’) does not mean that its laws are not more
secure once they have been enshrined in positive law. In
fact, the Stoics preferred to see the laws of Zeus codified
(Bauman 2000: 70, 80). The Roman Stoics, in particular,
sought to bring the cosmopolis into practical existence
through the exercise of power. This is why many threw
themselves into the Sturm und Drang of politics. The true
sage spurns the life of solitary contemplation to devote
him/herself to civic life. There is a fundamental human
desire to ‘safeguard and protect’ our fellow human beings
and because it is natural to ‘desire to benefit as many
people as [one] can’ (Cicero 1961: III.65); it follows that
‘the Wise Man’ will ‘engage in politics and government’
(Cicero 1961: III.68; Diogenes 1958: ‘Zeno’ VII. 21).
Many Stoics sought to influence politics either directly or
indirectly. The Stoic philosopher-king, Marcus Aurelius,
was the most powerful person on earth during his reign
(Noyen 1955), while the Gracchi brothers pushed for
many Stoic-inspired reforms such as admission of all
Italians to citizenship. Those without formal power sought
to influence those who did hold it: Panaetius advised
Scipio Aemilianus, Seneca advised Nero while Blossius
of Cumae advised Tiberius Sempronius Gracchus (see
Hill 2005).
But in the absence of formal institutionalisation the laws
of the cosmos are still held to be real; we remain bound
by them because, as Cicero points out, ‘true law’ is
not ‘any enactment of peoples’ [statute] but something
eternal which rules the whole universe by its wisdom
in command and prohibition’. After all, ‘there was no
written law against rape at Rome in the reign of Lucius
Tarquinius’ yet ‘we cannot say on that account that
Sextus Tarquinius did not break that eternal Law by
violating Lucretia’. The eternal law ‘urging men to right
conduct and diverting them from wrongdoing … did not
first become Law when it was written down, but when it
first came into existence’, which occurred ‘simultaneously
with the divine mind’ (1988: II. 11).
Even if they never managed to constitutionally entrench
the cosmopolis, the Stoics believe it is realised the
moment an agent internalises its moral precepts and
begins to act upon them unilaterally. On this view,
technically, the world state can be brought into existence
by the actions of a single right-thinking person. Therefore
it is unclear that a global ethics is meaningless without
a world state and without political anchoring practices,
and positive laws to guarantee them. At its inception, the
18 Social Alternatives Vol. 34 No. 1, 2015
Stoic cosmopolis was conceived as a moral mindset: no
Stoic ever advocated a legally constituted world-state.
One enters the cosmopolis in and with one’s mind, a
mind that is disciplined to absolute impartiality, capable of
seeing past social conventions and intent on universally
extending benevolence and compassion.
Concluding Remarks
For the Stoics, we are siblings with a common ancestry
who share equally in a capacity for reason. Accordingly,
we are all entitled to full recognition. The global state,
the cosmopolis, is brought into being by this recognition:
it is a function of the capacity to be impartial and to
appreciate that there is an inescapable duty to aid
anyone in need, regardless of their social location or
social proximity. The Stoics knew that this was a hard
task requiring not only a high degree of emotional
control and moral maturity but also a willingness to resist
social convention and local practice. Their injunctions
to reasonable behaviour were made in full knowledge
of the fact that the desired anchoring practices would
most likely be absent; nevertheless, they expected their
disciples to adhere to them, not only in the absence of
such practices but even in the face of hostile anchoring
practices, whether in the form of laws or norms.
References
Aristotle 1943 Generation of Animals, trans. A.L. Peck,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Bauman, R. 2000 Human Rights in Ancient Rome,
Routledge, London and New York.
Brown, E. 2006 ‘The Stoic invention of cosmopolitan
politics’, Proceedings of the Conference Cosmopolitan
Politics: On the history and future of a controversial
ideal, Frankfurt am Main, December, http://www.artsci.
wustl.edu/~eabrown/pdfs/Invention (accessed
03/08/2013).
Cicero 1961 De Finibus Bonorum et Malorum, trans. H.
Rackham, William Heinemann Ltd, London.
Cicero, Marcus Tullius 1988 De Republica; De Legibus,
trans. C.W. Keyes, William Heinemann Ltd, London.
Cicero, Marcus Tullius 1990 De Officiis, trans. W. Miller,
Harvard University Press, London.
Clark, S. 1987 ‘The City of the Wise’, Apeiron, XX,1:
63-80.
Demosthenes 1926 ‘Philippic III’, in Demosthenes, trans.
C. A. Vince and J. H. Vince, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Diogenes, L. 1958 Lives of Eminent Philosophers, trans.
R.D. Hicks, William Heinemann Ltd, London.
Epictetus 1989 The Discourses as Reported by Arrian,
the Manual and Fragments, in two vols, trans. W.A.
Oldfather, Harvard University Press, London.
Hill, L. 2001 ‘The first wave of feminism: were the Stoics
feminists?’ History of Political Thought, 22, 1: 12-40.
Hill, L. 2005 ‘Classical Stoicism and a difference of
opinion?’ in T. Battin (ed.) A Passion for Politics:
Essays in Honour of Graham Maddox, Pearson
Education Australia, Frenchs Forest, NSW.
Long, A. and Sedley, D. 1987 The Hellenistic Philosophers,
in two vols, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Marcus Aurelius 1916 The Meditations, trans. C.R.
Haines, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Musonius R. 1905 Musonius Rufus, Reliquiae, O. Hense
(ed.), Teubner, Chicago.
Noyen, P. 1955 ‘Marcus Aurelius: the greatest practitioner
of Stoicism’, Antiquité Classique, 24: 372-383.
Nussbaum, M. 2000 Ethics and Political Philosophy,
Transaction Publications, New Brunswick.
Seneca, Lucius Annaues 1970 ‘Ad Helvium’, in Seneca,
Moral Essays, trans. J.W. Basore, William Heinemann
Ltd, London.
Seneca, Lucius Annaeus 2002 Epistles, in three vols,
intro. R. M. Gummere, Harvard University Press,
Cambridge, MA.
Sorabji, R. 1993 Animal Minds and Human Morals,
Cornell University Press, Ithaca, NY.
Author
Lisa Hill PhD is Professor of Politics at the University of
Adelaide. Before that she was an Australian Research
Council Fellow and a Fellow in Political Science at the
Research School of Social Sciences, Australian National
University. Her interests are in political theory, history of
political thought and electoral ethics. She is co-author
of: An Intellectual History of Political Corruption, and
Compulsory Voting: For and Against. She has published
her work in Political Studies, Federal Law Review,
The British Journal of Political Science and Journal of
Theoretical Politics.
End Notes
1. Although the school wasn’t officially closed until 529 CE.
2. Happiness is synonymous with wisdom and virtue in Stoicism.
3. Habendam, or what is held or is due to one.
Every Breath
It’s interesting to consider that
every breath I take
has already been breathed
been part of another breath.
Perhaps that dog over there,
smelly and hairy, licking its own arse.
lynne White,
GWynedd, WaleS
Copyright of Social Alternatives is the property of Social Alternatives and its content may not
be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder’s
express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for
individual use.
Delivering a high-quality product at a reasonable price is not enough anymore.
That’s why we have developed 5 beneficial guarantees that will make your experience with our service enjoyable, easy, and safe.
You have to be 100% sure of the quality of your product to give a money-back guarantee. This describes us perfectly. Make sure that this guarantee is totally transparent.
Read moreEach paper is composed from scratch, according to your instructions. It is then checked by our plagiarism-detection software. There is no gap where plagiarism could squeeze in.
Read moreThanks to our free revisions, there is no way for you to be unsatisfied. We will work on your paper until you are completely happy with the result.
Read moreYour email is safe, as we store it according to international data protection rules. Your bank details are secure, as we use only reliable payment systems.
Read moreBy sending us your money, you buy the service we provide. Check out our terms and conditions if you prefer business talks to be laid out in official language.
Read moreOur specialists are always online to help you! We are available 24/7 via live chat, WhatsApp, and phone to answer questions, correct mistakes, or just address your academic fears.
See our T&Cs